Like 5 per 100,000? Maybe nationally, but not by state, and not by city. — Bitter Crank
The police activity that is missing in many communities is detective-led investigations leading to the arrest of people committing murder and manslaughter. — Bitter Crank
More important were various social, economic, and environmental factors, such as growth in income and an aging population. The introduction of CompStat, a data-driven policing technique, also played a significant role in reducing crime in cities that introduced it.
The report concludes that considering the immense social, fiscal, and economic costs of mass incarceration, programs that improve economic opportunities, modernize policing practices, and expand treatment and rehabilitation programs, all could be a better public safety investment. — “Brennan Center”
…
My work looks most closely at where crime is happening, not at individual victims. But there are some things we think we know. Intimate-partner violence increased in 2020. So did hate crimes against Asians. But the overall demographics of victims is incredibly consistent over time. It’s young people of color, particularly young men of color. I don’t see anything yet to indicate that’s changed dramatically.
…
My argument is that in areas where communities go through periods of disinvestment and where institutions break down, people feel like they’re on their own. This creates conditions where violence becomes more likely. As a place becomes more violent, people change their behavior. They become more likely to interpret uncertainty in an aggressive way, more likely to carry a weapon, more likely to act quickly or first if they feel threatened. This is how the presence of violence creates more violence. This cascading effect, where violence begets violence, has been reinforced in the past year.
Last year, everyday patterns of life broke down. Schools shut down. Young people were on their own. There was a widespread sense of a crisis and a surge in gun ownership. People stopped making their way to institutions that they know and where they spend their time. That type of destabilization is what creates the conditions for violence to emerge.
…
When a social order depends on the police dominating public spaces, and that form of social order is questioned and starts to break down, it can lead to a surge in violence. It doesn’t mean that protests cause violence. It means that when you depend on the police to dominate public spaces and they suddenly step back from that role, violence can increase.
… — “Atlantic Interview of Patrick Sharkey”
a relative lack of police services in black communities. — Bitter Crank
If one is concerned with people of color being murdered, then black-on-black violence is relevant; — ToothyMaw
but black-on-black crime is also worth paying attention to — ToothyMaw
But according to intuitionism objects and numbers can also be lawless, where an object is said to be "lawless" if it's existence and/or value isn't decided by the formal system it is part of, but by something not described by, and external to, the formal system. — sime
Hence, according to Devitt, "no doctrine of truth is constitutive of realism". — Banno
DO you thin this somehow incompatible with realism? — Banno
Ideally, fending against informal logical fallacies should protect one against being duped (and, if one is very nice, make one refrain from duping others). — baker
There are some alternative mathematical logics which account for the (un-)provability problem by eliminating the tertium-non-datur and the law of the double-negation by saying "x" means that "a proof can be contructed for x" and "not(x)" means "a proof can be constructed for not(x)". Doing this a failure to construct a proof for "not(x)" no longer necessarily implies "x", which makes the logic weaker (and suitable for an open world). — Heiko
Well I don’t understand the Bible in Latin or German, why should another German book that I don’t understand fail to qualify as a bible? The title sounds grand though.Indeed, why not makeEristische Dialektik our Bible? — baker
Persuade the Audience, Not The Opponent
This is chiefly practicable in a dispute between scholars in the presence of the unlearned. If you have no argument ad rem, and none either ad hominem, you can make one ad auditores; that is to say, you can start some invalid objection, which, however, only an expert sees to be invalid. Now your opponent is an expert, but those who form your audience are not, and accordingly in their eyes he is defeated; particularly if the objection which you make places him in any ridiculous light. People are ready to laugh, and you have the laughers on your side. To show that your objection is an idle one, would require a long explanation on the part of your opponent, and a reference to the principles of the branch of knowledge in question, or to the elements of the matter which you are discussing; and people are not disposed to listen to it. For example, your opponent states that in the original formation of a mountain-range the granite and other elements in its composition were, by reason of their high temperature, in a fluid or molten state; that the temperature must have amounted to some 480 degrees Fahrenheit; and that when the mass took shape it was covered by the sea. You reply, by an argument ad auditores, that at that temperature - nay, indeed, long before it had been reached, namely, at 212 degrees Fahrenheit - the sea would have been boiled away, and spread through the air in the form of steam. At this the audience laughs. To refute the objection, your opponent would have to show that the boiling-point depends not only on the degree of warmth, but also on the atmospheric pressure; and that as soon as about half the sea-water had gone off in the shape of steam, this pressure would be so greatly increased that the rest of it would fail to boil even at a temperature of 480 degrees. He is debarred from giving this explanation, as it would require a treatise to demonstrate the matter to those who had no acquaintance with physics. — “The Art of Being Right”
My inclination is to say simply that we can choose whatever logic suits our purpose. DO you thin this somehow incompatible with realism? — Banno
If you read ~ as an intuitionist, as Dummett would, then ~p only says that you haven't demonstrated p, and ~~p only says that you haven't demonstrated that you haven't demonstrated p. — Srap Tasmaner
Intuitionistic logic can be succinctly described as classical logic without the Aristotelian law of excluded middle:
A∨¬A(LEM)
or the classical law of double negation elimination: . . .
Not having verified p isn’t the same as having verified not-p. You need to verify not-p for p to be false. — Michael
Other than that - I do not understand your concept of rTruth completely: E.g. If you feel a poke in the back, is there "really" something that pokes you? I guess the answer is "no": it is a conclusion that everything has cause. I am not sure that all realists would reduce reality to just the given content of consciousness. In another thread I pointed out that (following e.g. Heidegger) reality seems to be purely negative - that it is mainly what _prevents_ you to assume something. In logics this would be a statement not(x) where x is the "state of affairs as assumed". — Heiko
Yet again, if the verificationist hasn’t verified the square root of 123 then he isn’t omniscient. It’s that simple. — Michael
The operative concept of “knowability” remains elusive but is meant to fall somewhere between equating truth uninformatively with what God would know and equating truth naively with what humans actually know. Equating truth with what God would know does not improve intelligibility, and equating it with what humans actually know fails to appreciate the objectivity and discoverability of truth. ...
The great problem for the middle way is Fitch’s paradox. It is the proof that shows (in a normal modal logic augmented with the knowledge operator) that “all truths are knowable” entails “all truths are known”... — "SEP
Because under verificationism that isn’t sufficient to be omniscient. Omniscience requires having verified every proposition or their negation. — Michael
It is however the contrapositive of Theorem 5 that is usually referred to as the paradox:
(K Paradox)∀p(p→◊Kp)⊢∀p(p→Kp).
It tells us that if any truth can be known then it follows that every truth is in fact known. — SEP on Fitch
Fitch’s paradox of knowability (aka the knowability paradox or Church-Fitch Paradox) concerns any theory committed to the thesis that all truths are knowable. Historical examples of such theories arguably include Michael Dummett’s semantic antirealism (i.e., the view that any truth is verifiable)
But verificationism holds that p is true if and only if it has been verified.
And it follows that everything that is true has been verified. — Banno
I'm not arguing that robots experience things here. I'm arguing that it's a superfluous requirement. But even if you do add this superfluous requirement, it's certainly not the critical element. To explain what brings me the bananas when I ask for them, you have to explain how those words makes something bring me bananas. — InPitzotl
If for example, the grass is wet, it has to have become wet somehow. If we were in a world where this can only happen by rain, the conclusion clearly is that it must have rained. — Heiko
The difference is that normally we use the material implication as an actual implication, as in the truth of the antecedent implies the consequent. Being a bachelor implies being an unmarried man. Being a man implies being mortal. Winning 270 Electoral College votes implies becoming the next President of the United States. — Michael
Logic can determine that a set of premises /cannot/ be true or show that the truth of a given conclusion holds under given premises and derive such already implied conlusions. — Heiko
Nothing. Your argument has no practical use. I have to evaluate the truth of your conclusion to evaluate the truth of your premise. — Michael
(That is, while the argument form may be valid, the interesting bit - whether the consequence is true - is directly evaluated by reference to the facts. In this respect, soundness is a coincidence of valid form and fact.) — Ennui Elucidator
You have to prove your premises true to prove your conclusion. — Michael
It is a premise, I don't have to prove it to assume it.You proved that 1 is true, you haven't proved that 2 is true. How do you prove that if 2 + 2 = 4 then the cat is on the mat? — Michael
It isn't. The argument is only a proof if you can prove 1 and 2 to be true. A deductive argument can have false premises after all. How do you prove 2 to be true? By proving that 2 + 2 = 4 and that a cat is on the mat. You need "the world" to do this. — Michael
it's not paraconsistent logic - which holds that A, ~A ⊨ B is not a valid inference; this is the view usually associated with anti-realism. — Banno
Beall suggests that the knower gives us some independent evidence for thinking Kp∧¬Kp, for some p — “SEP on Fitch’s Paradox”
I'm not sure there's really a problem then. If premise 1 is true then premise 2 is true only if the cat is on the mat. So the realist can say that the realist account of truth is required for premise 2 to be true. — Michael
The statement "the cat is on the mat" is definitionally true — TheMadFool
You're addressing the discrepancy with natural language? — Michael
A closely related analysis for formality is that formal rules are totally abstract. They abstract away from the semantic content of thoughts or claims, to leave only semantic structure. The terms ‘mother’ and ‘cousin’ enter essentially into argument (5). On this view, expressions such as propositional connectives and quantifiers do not add new semantic content to expressions, but instead add only ways to combine and structure semantic content. Expressions like ‘mother’ and ‘cousin’, by contrast, add new semantic content.
[/quote[
. — “SEP on Logical Consequence”
how does one account for the existence of irrationality, abstraction, subjectivity and opinion via logical/ reasonable means? — Benj96
IS it that (2) already seems to evaluate "the cat is on the mat"? — Banno
Perhaps there is a reason to allow the notion of logical consequence to apply even more broadly. In Gentzen’s proof theory for classical logic, a notion of consequence is defined to hold between multiple premises and multiple conclusions. The argument from a set X of premises to a set Y of conclusions is valid if the truth of every member of X guarantees (in the relevant sense) the truth of some member of
Y. There is no doubt that this is formally perspicuous, but the philosophical applicability of the multiple premise—multiple conclusion sense of logical consequence remains an open philosophical issue. In particular, those anti-Realists who take logical consequence to be defined in terms of proof (such as Michael Dummett) reject a multiple conclusion analysis of logical consequence. For an Anti-realist, who takes good inference to be characterised by the way warrant is transmitted from premise to conclusion, it seems that a multiple conclusion analysis of logical consequence is out of the question. In a multiple conclusion argument from A to B, C, any warrant we have for A does not necessarily transmit to B or C: the only conclusion we are warranted to draw is the disjunction B or C, so it seems for an analysis of consequence in terms of warrant we need to understand some logical vocabulary (in this case, disjunction) in order to understand the consequence relation. This is unacceptable if we hope to use logical consequence as a tool to define that logical vocabulary. No such problems appear to arise in a single conclusion setting. (However, see Restall (2005) for a defence of multiple conclusion consequence for Anti-realists; and see Beall (2011) for a defence of certain sub-classical multiple-conclusion logics in the service of non-classical solutions to paradox.)
— “SEP on Logical Consequence”
I don't think that quite right - rather it accepts that the height is neither known nor unknown; and hence paraconsistent. — Banno
In the literature, especially in the part of it that contains objections to paraconsistent logic, there has been some tendency to confuse paraconsistency with dialetheism, the view that there are true contradictions (see the entry on dialetheism). The view that a consequence relation should be paraconsistent does not entail the view that there are true contradictions. Paraconsistency is a property of a consequence relation whereas dialetheism is a view about truth. The fact that one can define a non-explosive consequence relation does not mean that some sentences are true. The fact that one can construct a model where a contradiction holds but not every sentence of the language holds (or where this is the case at some world) does not mean that the contradiction is true per se. Hence paraconsistency must be distinguished from dialetheism (though see Asmus 2012).
— “SEP on Paraconsitent Logics”
Beall suggests that the knower gives us some independent evidence for thinking Kp∧¬Kp, for some
p, that the full description of human knowledge has the interesting feature of being inconsistent. With a paraconsistent logic, one may accept this without triviality. And so it is suggested that one go paraconsistent and embrace Kp∧¬Kp as a true consequence of the knowability principle. Beall concludes that Fitch’s reasoning, without a proper reply to the knower, is ineffective against the knowability principle.
— “SEP on Fitch’s Paradox”
A is both true and false. Which is... different. — Banno
At the core of the explanation, one has to grasp a very basic mathematical distinction. I speak of the difference between a relation and a function. A relation is something that relates a certain kind of object to some number of others (zero, one, two, etc). A function, on the other hand, is a special kind of relation that links each such object to exactly one thing. Suppose we are talking about people. Mother of and father of are functions, because every person has exactly one (biological) mother and exactly one father. But son of and daughter of are relations, because parents might have any number of sons and daughters. Functions give a unique output; relations can give any number of outputs. Keep that distinction in mind; we’ll come back to it a lot.
Now, in logic, one is generally interested in whether a given claim is true or false. Logicians call true and false truth values. Normally, and following Aristotle, it is assumed that ‘value of’ is a function: the value of any given assertion is exactly one of true (or T), and false (or F). In this way, the principles of excluded middle (PEM) and non-contradiction (PNC) are built into the mathematics from the start. But they needn’t be.
To get back to something that the Buddha might recognise, all we need to do is make value of into a relation instead of a function. Thus T might be a value of a sentence, as can F, both, or neither. We now have four possibilities: {T}, {F}, {T,F} and { }. The curly brackets, by the way, indicate that we are dealing with sets of truth values rather than individual ones, as befits a relation rather than a function. The last pair of brackets denotes what mathematicians call the empty set: it is a collection with no members, like the set of humans with 17 legs. It would be conventional in mathematics to represent our four values using something called a Hasse diagram, like so:
{T}
↗ ↖
{T, F} { }
↖ ↗
{F}
Thus the four kotis (corners) of the catuskoti appear before us.
In case this all sounds rather convenient for the purposes of Buddhist apologism, I should mention that the logic I have just described is called First Degree Entailment (FDE). It was originally constructed in the 1960s in an area called relevant logic. — “Priest on Beyond True and False”
Another strategy, however, is suggested by Berkeley’s reference in PHK 3 and 48 to “some other spirit,” a strategy summarized in a further limerick:
Dear Sir, your astonishment’s odd
I am always about in the Quad
And that’s why the tree
continues to be
since observed by, Yours faithfully, God
— “SEP on Berkeley”
Fitch article in SEP — Banno