For example, it is conceivable that consciousness of a thought is prior to the thought's intentionality. — RussellA
It seems to me by your words, you’re saying the categories have no clear right to do what Kant intended for them, re:, his deduction of them is suspect, or downright illegitimate, therefore they have no sufficient warrant for their employment. — Mww
The certainty isn’t in the stone, it’s in the truth of the necessity, which is not outside the logic of my mental affairs. — Mww
The stone is not; that which is represented by the word stone, very much is simply out there, independent of my mental affairs. Stone is from those very affairs. — Mww
There is a relation, but not between the thing out there and my mental affairs with respect to it. The relation binds, through synthesis, the phenomena of intuition in sensibility to the logic of cognition in understanding. The ground for that function of synthesis, is imagination, the rules by which all synthesis abides regarding empirical content, are the categories. — Mww
If he thought there was a need for it, wouldn’t he have included it in what he’d already said was a completed metaphysical system? Besides, the pertinent fundamental transcendental deduction concerns the possibility of experience, the totality of each being no more than just itself, and of course, the totality of experience in general, is unintelligible.
Totality of experience is not a thing to which transcendental deductions can apply, but rather, represents an aggregate of individual things, to each of which such deductions would apply. In the thought of them. Experience is merely an end, given from a certain methodological means, hence, being an end, or, object of, is not itself subjected to, the means.
Why is there a need, and what form would restitution for that need take?
I mean, it took him ten years and 700-odd pages to construct what he thought he needed, so it seems pretty ungracious to suggest later that he forgot something. I know I’m barely smart enough to understand what he did, but I’m certainly not smart enough to question what he should have done. — Mww
So all you’re saying is that he didn’t really deduce anything, when he states for the record that transcendental deductions are “…. an examination of the manner in which conceptions can apply à priori to objects…”, which appears to presuppose the conceptions being applied.
If appearance tells me a thing exists, logic tells me its existence is necessary. I have no need to deduce any of those pure conceptions justifying my logic, beyond the authority they impose on my thinking. This is what his successors meant by telling us all about what we couldn’t talk about. It isn’t and never was what we can’t; it’s because there no need. — Mww
The term “exist” is a conception, yes, which can be predicated of things. Existence gives the principle of subsumption for particular things as a condition for them, yet can never be itself a predicate. It follows that the criteria for a pure conception, is that it is always the subject of a proposition and from which is given a principle in relation to time, and cannot be a predicate in the cognition of things. Existence is, therefore, not just a conception, but a pure conception.
In much the same way is “space” a conception. But insofar as space is the condition of the sensing of things rather than the thinking of them, it is not a pure conception, but instead, a pure intuition, holding to the same transcendental manner of applying a priori to objects but not contained in them. — Mww
Ok, so if I see a thing and know what it is, that’s called experience and makes explicit the thing I see has run the full gamut of cognition. It follows that if I’m seeing a pot, I must be thinking the concept in order to know what I’m seeing this time conforms to the thing I saw at some antecedent time and by which I first knew that thing as a pot. If I see and know a thing I must have actualized the concept.
On the other hand, what do I care about not actualizing a concept when I’m not thinking about some thing? I can almost guarantee I’m NOT thinking about a hellava lot more things than I am.
When I’m looking at and knowing a pot, and the guy says frying pan….why is it that I don’t hand him the pot? I didn’t hand him the pot only because what I heard him say doesn’t sound like the name of what I see? Wouldn’t I have to actualize both concepts, think the thing belonging to this sound and think the thing belonging to that sound, in order to judge whether or not the sound I heard properly represents the thing I see?
If I have to actualize concepts for the relations of different sounds, why wouldn’t I have to actualize concepts in the relations of what I know? — Mww
That’s my opinion. — Mww
The world is not given the same logical structure because we don’t know enough about it. Still, what we do know about it can be said to demonstrate logical structure in its relations to us, the simplest being near or far.
The genesis of logical structure is in us, and it is impossible that we do not know that very structure which we construct for ourselves, the simplest of that being A = A.
The world is just there, and we determine for ourselves how it is to be understood. Just because we say roses are red doesn’t indicate the impossibility that they be anything else, but only that they are that for us. By the same token, if the rose is red regardless of what we say, it is red necessarily. Our intelligence is not equipped to say which is the case. — Mww
Kant did not believe that everything must be reduced to representation. — RussellA
Descartes said that there were no thoughts about which we are unconscious. In addition, he said that whilst the object of perception may be doubted, the perception itself cannot be doubted. — RussellA
However, there is an academic dispute whether Descartes believed that a thought can be non-intentional. — RussellA
The hand that cannot grasp itself’ — Wayfarer
Therefore, Kant might have said "I think about my hand as an object of experience, not as it is in itself, but as it appears within the limitations that the Categories have imposed on it"
Kant might have more simply said "I think about a representation"
It is certainly not the case as Henry suggests that Kant is saying "I represent to myself that I think". — RussellA
A hand cannot grasp itself, but nevertheless, is proof of an external world, as Moore wrote in Proof of an External World
In addition, as Descartes might have said, "I think about my hand, therefore I am".
In fact, it seems that my hand not only proves my existence but also that of the external world. — RussellA
“This”, here, is thinking, and your idea that what’s beneath thinking is impossible to talk about. I would extend that to your question, “what is logic”. Other than bare definition, what’s beneath logic, is impossible to talk about. — Mww
I’m not sure what you mean by transcendental thinking. All transcendental is a priori and belongs to reason but thinking both a posteriori and a priori belongs to understanding. In the former is the complete determination of all things in general; in the latter is the determination of one thing at a time. It is by the transcendental substratum for the determination of all things, are given the rules for the possibility of determining particular things. The completely determined in general is an idea; the completely determined in particular is the ding an sich, neither of which is a possible experience.
If we were in the weeds before, we’re damn near being choked out by them now. — Mww
I was hoping, by my mention of shoe-tying and book-reading, you might note that my position has always been that humans generally think in images.
If one speaks to himself, how does he know what to say?
If to think is to speak to oneself, why not just say one thinks to himself?
What seems like the proverbial voice in your head is merely extant experience doing its thing, taking up the time when the cognitive part of the system recognizes it’s only repeating itself. — Mww
Perhaps, depending on context, but I’m claiming the irreducible case, hence regardless of context, is Nature. Language relations with the world presupposes the world, and world being the representation of Nature in general, gives the irreducible.
Which gets us to….by quid juris is it, that synthetic apriority in language relations with the world, is the case? Which in turn requires the answer to, the case….for what? — Mww
Ehhhhh….methinks ‘tis not so much a confession as a sad commentary on the sorry state of speculative metaphysics. Funny, too, in that the historical record exhibits that Kant allowed himself precious few indulgences of any kind, so there wouldn’t be anything of the sort to which a confession of his would refer. — Mww
I’d also like to revisit your quote in which he says, “…(…) if such exist….”. At the time, as you well know, synthetic a priori cognitions hadn’t been entered into the philosophical vocabulary. He had to prove the validity of the concept, and he said “if they exist” because no one had yet thought about them as existing. And they don’t “exist” in the strict categorical sense, but I already spoke to that. — Mww
I would perhaps listen to an art expert's opinion that Derain painted Le séchage des voiles in 1905, but I would take any art expert's opinion that this painting is a great work of art with a pinch of salt, even though in fact I do believe that this painting is a great work of art.
In the world, objects have properties. It is said that some properties are objective facts, such that Derain's painting was painted in 1905, and some properties are subjective judgements, such that Derain's painting is good.
Some properties, such as good, are clearly subjective judgements, but other properties, such that this object is a painting, which appear objective facts, are also subjective judgements.
As you say, Quine points out the indeterminacy of translation.
Person A born in 1950 and brought up in South Africa and person B born in 2005 and brought up in Nevada will have different understandings about the same concept. For example, person A's concept of a forest, a savanna woodland, will be different to person B's concept of a forest, sparse juniper pine.
As you also say, in fact, person A's understanding of every concept will be different to person B's understanding of the same concept.
No concept can be an objective fact in the world, but rather every concept must be a subjective judgement. Not only is saying that Derain's Le séchage des violes is good is a subjective judgment, but even saying that Derain's Le séchage des violes is a painting is a subjective judgment.
In fact, not only would I take an art expert's opinion that the Derain object is good with a pinch of salt, but philosophically, I should also take the art expert's opinion that the Derain object is a painting also with a pinch of salt. — RussellA
Nope. One has to think to conceive of pure thought, which may then be talked about. One doesn’t talk about that of which he has no conception. — Mww
You’re asking about justifying a contradiction? Of course one cannot talk about what stands outside of talk. You must realize we invent the objects used to represent our thinking, the words. For whatever is used for thinking, a word can be invented to represent it. Whatever is thought about, a word can be invented to represent it.
There are no words possible to represent, we cannot meaningfully talk about, only that which cannot be thought, on the one hand, and, we never invent a word then think a conception belonging to it, on the other. — Mww
Given the subject matter of the Dialectic, I gather that somehow you’re saying Manny’s exposè demonstrating the illegitimacy ol’ Renè’s cogito principle, is just as bad as the principle itself.
Interesting, but I’d have to think awful hard nonetheless about how sophistical arguments and paralogisms are just as bad as that which guards against them. — Mww
Ya know….Kant used mathematics to prove the very possibility of synthetic a priori cognitions. Once their possibility is proved, he then goes about finding them in cognitions other than mathematical. So if it is proven there are rules for understanding, it is perfectly reasonable to suppose there are rules for speaking. On the other hand, while it is perfectly reasonable that to misuse the rules of understanding results in incorrect thinking, it is absurd to suppose the misuse of the rules for speaking results in incorrect speech, or language in general.
And if I don’t agree logic is discovered, then it follows that the discovery of logic in the rules for speech is beyond the agreement pale. — Mww
Maybe they are, but why can’t a postulate have a use in keeping with the theory to which it belongs. Sorta like Newton’s g: no such thing but a necessary component in the law of universal gravitation. — Mww
Yes, but the evidential basis for their use lies exclusively in some speculative idea of a system. One who thinks a metaphysical system comes to be on account of the speaking of it, still has to explain where the speaking came from. Not only that, but how to explain, in one example of a veritable plethora thereof, how Joyce and Gell-Mann related the same word for entirely different chains of thought. — Mww
These beg the basic question: what is the aesthetic experience "as such"? The Greek sense has no bearing here; and to refer to "taste" simply shows how misaligned philosophy was with the world. Ask, what is the world? with only true descriptive intent, putting aside the zeal for objectifying and categorizing, and one finds something that altogether defies philosophical objectification, and this is where the significance, is discovered. What is sought, as with Kant, is something that is a stand alone, or, as Kierkegaard put is, "stands as its own presupposition". He thought this could only lie in transcendence, but he really didn't understand that if transcendence is what must account for what is witnessed in logic, then the same goes for all of experience, or all of being-in-the-world.The aesthetic can be looked at in two ways. Firstly, the term was initially used by Alexander Baumgarten. It was borrowed from the Greek word for sensory perception, to denote concrete knowledge that we gain through our senses. Secondly, as a synonym for "taste", in being able to distinguish between those objects worthy of contemplation and those objects not worthy. When we observe an object about which we have a subjective aesthetic feeling, either we have an aesthetic feeling because the object is an aesthetic object, or the object is not an aesthetic object but we are able to perceive an aesthetic in the shapes and colours we experience as sensory phenomena. Post-Kant, the aesthetic is considered as the synthesis of both these, sensory experience and intellectual judgment. — RussellA
You raise the question as to whether science has an interest in the aesthetic features of science, and as to whether that science is in its essence, aesthetic. Science starts with particular observations, and its goal is to discover from these particular observations universal laws. Such universal laws enable science to predict future phenomenal states. There are two ways of doing this. Either by looking at each particular observation one at a time and through reason and logic combine them into a whole, or by immediately perceiving a gestalt, an immediate unity of parts as an aesthetic. In Kant's words, a unity of apperception. Kant's transcendental apperception is the uniting and building of coherent consciousness out of different elementary inner experiences. Such experiences differ in both time and topic, but all belong to the individual's self-consciousness. Science discovers universal laws from particular observations, both by logical reasoning about the parts making up a whole and by aesthetic intuition about a whole made up of parts . — RussellA
You also raise the question about Kant's rationalism, his logical reasoning. Though, as Hume said, reason cares nothing for human existence. In fact, reason does not "care" at all. Kant combined Rationalism with Empiricism though Transcendental Idealism. Rationalism is the belief that particular sense experiences are necessary in order for us to discover concepts and knowledge. However, they are not sufficient. One needs in addition the ability to logically reason about these particular sense experiences. Empiricism is the belief, as with Rationalism, that particular sense experiences are necessary in order for us to discover concepts and knowledge. However, for the Empiricists, these experiences can be sufficient. Sometimes, however, logical reasoning may be of assistance in clarifying certain sense experiences. The staring point for both the Rationalist and Empiricist are the phenomena of particular observations. It is through these phenomena that there is the possibility of discovering universal truths. There are two aspects to the aesthetic. First, there is the aesthetic object within sensory experience as an objective entity, and second there is the aesthetic object within the mind as subjective feeling. Science also has two similar aspects. First the particular object experienced as phenomena and second the universal object experienced as a concept. Science is the discovery of the universal from the particular. Science starts with the aesthetic objective object within sense experience and discovers the aesthetic subjective object within a concept. — RussellA
One belief about the aesthetic object is that the aesthetic object needs no practical use to be aesthetic. Taking their cue from Kant, many philosophers have defended the idea of an aesthetic attitude as one divorced from practical concerns. This is a kind of “distancing,” or "standing back" from ordinary involvement. Kant described the recipients of aesthetic experience not as distanced but as disinterested. In other words, the recipient does not treat the object of enjoyment either as a vehicle for curiosity or as a means to an end. They contemplate the object as it is in itself and “apart from all interest.” An object such as a hammer, which has a practical use, is not aesthetic because it has a practical use, but rather an object, such as a Derain painting, which has no practical use, can still be aesthetic. Arthur Schopenhauer argued that people could regard anything aesthetically so long as they regarded it as independent of their will. That is, irrespective of any use to which they might put it. — RussellA
Yet there is a paradox here. On the one hand we observe particular shapes and colours within our phenomenal sensory experience which we intuitively find aesthetic. This does not need a reasoned judgment. On the other hand, we instinctively reason that it is not the case that we subjectively perceive an object as aesthetic, but rather that there will be universal agreement amongst everyone perceiving the same object that the object is objectively aesthetic. The aesthetic object is an object of sensory experience. The aesthetic object is not merely as an object of sensory pleasure but also as the repository of significance and value. This synthesis is summarised in Hegel's "the sensuous embodiment of the Idea". There is the sensory: concrete, individual, particular and determinate, and there is the intellectual: abstract, universal, general and indeterminate. This synthesis however gives rise to a paradox, as described by Kant in his antimony of taste. — RussellA
The human expresses their subjective pleasure in an object as if beauty was an objective property of the object. The human is making a universal general objective judgement about their immediate particular subjective feelings. Feelings about an object are particular and individual, so why do we want universal agreement about the nature of the object. There is a contradiction in making a universal judgment based on particular intuitions. The phrase "aesthetic judgment" is a contradiction in terms, yet we make aesthetic judgements all the time For example, I can accept someone as an expert in nuclear physics, of which I have no experience, yet I cannot accept someone as an expert as to the merits of a Derain painting unless I have had personal experience. There are universal rules in science but no universal rules in beauty. Yet we make aesthetic judgments, such that Derain is a great artist. We can make reasoned justifications for our aesthetic judgements, such as about Derain. We can do this because reasoned justifications can never be purely intellectual but must also be partly based on feeling. — RussellA
Are we mistaking the description of a system, for its operation?
Kant is “talking” about his own idea of what’s happening when the human animal uses his intellect.
What’s the problem with talking about pure thought using language, and exercising pure thought without it? Please don’t tell me you talk to yourself, prescribe in words or logic symbols the individual actions required to tie your shoes. Odd that you can tie your shoes faster than you can prescribe each act required in order to tie your shoes, innit?
When you’re reading something particularly engaging….ever notice the words merely represent a certain assemblage of conceptions you already have, and the author is only trying to make you mentally image what’s he’s already done for himself. And it’s only in the case where you don’t have for yourself this certain assemblage, that you have to stop and read again, or look up to the sky and….you know, think….about what the author wants you to imagine.
I have no problem whatsoever asserting that’s the way my system works, and I’m almost as certain that’s the way your system works, too. That language must take precedence, is “….beneath the dignity of philosophy….”**, yet at the same time perfectly authorized to ground “…..philosophizing in an orderly manner….”***
(**1787; ***1644) — Mww
And ya know what….logical structure presupposed in understanding a sentence’s meaning, might be restricted to the form of logic, yet the sentence itself by which it is expressed, necessarily concerns the content of that logic. I mean…you can’t really presuppose content, can you? It being as varied and indiscriminate as circumstance permits. — Mww
What is the case is the synthetic apriority in language relations with the world. Clearly the move from this is not going to be something determinate, and I did say this earlier when I was talking about the conditions of a proper logical deduction. What must be the case is always going to be the unknown X, but the point is that it must be something, and if one must give a reason why there must be something, one does the Critique. Extrapolations do not lead to certainies, only indeterminacies, and this is why I think this term right, because Kant's argument does not give us determinacy, for this is impossible.Except Kant’s is a speculative metaphysic, in which the transcendental philosophy constructed to account for it, may not properly account for what is the case. Thus, your notion of extrapolation can only refer to the move from what is the case, not to what must be the case to account for it, but only to a possible accounting. Regardless of how exact and internally consistent his system may be, it may not be what’s actually happening between our ears. He’s very specific in saying, if this way is sufficient then it is so only if it is done right. Hence, if pure reason is the way, then to critique it leads to doing it right. — Mww
What must be the case is determinable by the physical sciences alone, and he makes it quite clear that metaphysics is not a proper science, nor can it be, from which it follows that metaphysics alone cannot necessarily be the case that accounts for what is.
Knowing metaphysics is not necessarily right in accounting for what is, all that’s left to us is to make it less wrong. — Mww
Technically, what is irrevocably the case, is Nature. What must be the case to account for Nature, is guesswork originated by our intellect, and that conditioned by time and circumstance. Thus, what must be the case, is in fact quite contingent, the more parsimonious way to account for our intellectual errors.
If the perspective is limited to the human himself, Nature being given, what is irrevocably the case is nothing more than sensation, insofar as that is the point at which the internal mechanisms of human intellect….of whatever form that may be….become first apparent.
If you’re referring to aesthetic judgement as what is the case, as opposed to discursive judgement of the understanding, then we’re talking of two different conditions. But in relation to what is, aesthetic judgement respects only how we feel about it, rather than how we account for it. — Mww
Gettin’ pretty far into the weeds here, so “loosely put” is quite apropos. Those judgements structured by pure reason are principles, therefore called apodeitic or necessary, which serve as rules for the function of understanding in its empirical employment. The structure of judgements in general, called either problematic or assertorical, merely represents the unity between the conceptions in the subject to the predicate of any cognition, a function belonging to understanding alone. Whether or not this conception belongs to that conception, hence the truth or falsity of the cognition relative to those empirical conditions from which they arise, re: phenomena, THAT is the purview of reason.
When I think, and my thoughts succeed each other without conflict, my judgements are rational and/or logical. If I think, and then I have to think again or think otherwise, in which case there is a conflict in my judgements, it is reason’s judging that informs of the conflict, either regarding my understanding with itself, or my understanding with experience. Not what such conflict is, how it has manifested itself, but that there is one. Hence the transcendental nature of those judgements structured by pure reason as principles, that by which those discursive judgements is informed of its errors. — Mww
If it is the case all things are first evidenced by their effect on the senses, where does judgement appear? Do we really need to judge whether or not our senses have been affected? That they are or that they are not, to be considered as judgements as such? If such is the criteria for the structure of judgements in general, on order for them to appear, what is to be done with the relation between a phenomenon and the conceptions by which it is cognized? And if such is the case, what does pure reason have to do with it?
It is the case, however, that judgement does appear by the cognition that the “world” is that in which all possible things are first evidenced, but that merely treats “world” as a general condition for things for which evidence is possible. In other words, “world” is the predicate of a principle given a priori in transcendental logic. There remains the need for the intuition of that space in which a thing is first evidenced, and a time by which that thing relates to a perception of it, in neither of which does a judgement manifest itself.
(Sidebar: here, “world”, in Kant, is “reality”) For whatever that’s worth….. — Mww
No manifestation of discursive judgement in phenomena, but there is imagination, every bit as facilitating as judgement, for a priori argument. As I mentioned above, aesthetic judgement is manifest in the subject as his underlying condition, or, which is the same thing, how he feels about what he perceives. But that relates more to what he feels ought to be, rather than what is. — Mww
Science needs aesthetics and aesthetics needs science. The tension between art and science may be traced back to the Greeks, to the ancient conflict of Apollo and Dionysus, between order, reason, and logic and chaos, emotion, and ecstasy. There is the sublime in both the aesthetic and the scientific, in both its theory and practice. The aesthetics of science is the study of beauty and matters of taste within the scientific endeavour. Aesthetic features like simplicity, elegance and symmetry are sources of wonder and awe for many scientists, thus motivating scientific pursuit. Both use representation and the role of values. Both combine the subjective with the objective, imagination with creativity, the inspirational and the pragmatic. In e = mc 2 is an aesthetic beauty. — RussellA
That’s in fact all understanding is about. It is the analysis of all that contained in the primitive representation “I think”.
“…. And thus the synthetical unity of apperception is the highest point with which we must connect every operation of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and after it our transcendental philosophy; indeed, this faculty is the understanding itself.…”
Thus it is that the function of understanding is distinct from that to which it directs itself when it thinks, or, when the subject exercises his innate capacity for thinking. To understand, on the other hand, presupposes the completion of that analysis, the affirmation or negation of constructed judgements relative to empirical conditions, not yet verified by experience.
All without a single solitary word, either expressed, or merely thought. — Mww
And I reject that criticism, in that the thinking in CPR resolves the illusion of conceiving the world in any way except as the form of all that is relatable to it, hence hardly meaningless. We perceive things in a world; we don’t perceive worlds. From which follows world is conceivable only as the form of that in which all things are contained, but is not itself contained by it. — Mww
He ignores it in CPR because the analysis of who or what we are is properly the concern of his moral philosophy, which is not transcendental. — Mww
The name given to it presupposes the grasp of the conception to which the name relates. It’s occurence in thought, its conceivability, is explicitly the very purity by which the language describing it, is even possible. Language doesn’t grasp, it merely represents what’s already been grasped.
The purity of language is in thought; the purity of thought is in logic; the purity of logic is in pure reason; the purity of pure reason is the irreducible human condition. — Mww
CPR doesn’t treat of empirical ontology; it is a purely epistemological thesis, from a metaphysical perspective. — Mww
What…..not a fan of freedom as sufficient cause? — Mww
91 pages on sensibility, just under 400 pages on logic, all integral to the human condition. Fine if you wish to deny we are agents of logic, but I’m happily convinced human agency is necessarily predicated on it. — Mww
Nope. Extrapolation from what is the case for us, to how the case is to be known by us. We understand the world; we explain the understanding. Language for the second, not for the first. — Mww
Nope. What he means by “first” here, is merely that occassion given to a theoretical systemic procedure. There happens to be a particular theoretical system which presupposes a priori conditions, turning sensation into representation according to pure intuitions and productive imagination. — Mww
When I write and think, about my notice of the world. While it may that the categories are always involved when I write, it being a phenomenal exercise, it is not the case for when I think, for it is possible that I think in pure a priori terms, that is, non-empirical, for which the categories are not involved. The logic of my a priori judgements still requires affirmation, at least to be productive, but there is no occassion to seize upon intuition. — Mww
I need not go beyond relations in time, to discover what is necessary for something to be possible, as I already mentioned. For something to be possible at all its representation must be determinable in any time. Necessity: determinable in all time; existence: determinable in a time. — Mww
Agreed, which justifies the claim there is no language in pure thought. — Mww
Correct, from which follows the rules for speaking are very far from the rules for transcendental deduction. — Mww
Wait…..so all you’re talking about is justifying the origin of the categories, while I’m talking about justifying the use of them? What is necessary for the possibility of things makes little sense to me, but what is the ground for the possibility of transcendental deduction of the categories, is a whole ‘nuther ball of wax.
Dunno where your quote comes from, but in A88/B120 in Kemp Smith is shown that is precisely how the deduction is NOT served.
“…. they make affirmations concerning objects not by means of the predicates of intuition and sensibility, but of pure thought à priori….”.
Your a priori conditions upon which the possibility of experience rests”, are precisely those very intuitions my quote denotes as “not by means of”. — Mww
Nope. This is the nature of a transcendental argument, which is a priori. But not all a priori arguments are transcendental, re: those of understanding in its categorical judgements. Transcendental arguments originate in, and are the exclusive purview of, pure reason alone. — Mww
I cannot really respond as I have limited knowledge of Husserl, Heidegger and Existentialism in general.
However, in my agreement with Linguistic Idealism, I have sympathy with the notion in Husserl's Being and Time that the human is not a subjective spectator of objects, but rather that subject and object are inseparable. In my case, linked within language.
I don't know the background to Existentialism, have not read Kierkegaard and have only limited exposure to Nietzsche. However, I naturally agree with any critique of rationalism, and am supportive of their interest in the problem of meaning.
I have spent more time on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, respecting his attempt to understand the limits and scope of metaphysics, as well as investigating how reason may be used to gain knowledge about the world.
As regards Husserl's Logical Investigations, for me there is promise in Brentano's concept of Intentionality and the problem of intentional inexistence, the investigation of the relation between the act of consciousness and the phenomena at which it is directed. I tend more to agree more with the "bracketing" of assumptions about the existence of an external world than the Direct Realist who believes that they directly know the external world.
Continental philosophy opens up a whole new field of understanding. — RussellA
I can understand Phenomenology as part of a personal philosophy, but it seems limited if it made up the whole of a personal philosophy.
Phenomenology rejects rationalism and empiricism in favour of a person's "lived experience", relying on an intuitive grasp of knowledge free from any philosophical intellectualising.
For example, in Bracketing, one withholds any conscious opinion of what is perceived, taking no position as to the reality of what is seen, but simply to witness it as it presents itself.
I agree that Phenomenology can be insightful in our understanding about the relation of the mind to the sensations it experiences, but it seems insufficient not to question these sensations and only witness them.
Philosophy must surely be about questioning, not simply about phenomenologically accepting. — RussellA
That phenomena must meet the criteria of the categories doesn’t exhaust understanding, it enables the manifold of conceptions understanding possesses to be synthesized in the construction of a judgement on the one hand, or, enables an appeal to experience in the case of repetitive perception on the other.
In order for the affect of the thing on the senses, and the representation of that thing as it is understood, be sufficiently congruent to be knowledge of the thing, there must be rules by which one relates to the other, and, that by which the conceptions annexed to the phenomenon relate to each other. Something must have already prohibited the conception “round” from being imagined as belonging to the conception “tall”, when the thing perceived ended up being cognized initially, or remembered as post hoc experience, as a dinner plate.
—————- — Mww
The pure conceptions of the understanding are transcendental deductions of reason. Understanding uses them, but they are not given from understanding itself. These in opposition to conceptions arising spontaneously within understanding itself, in response to the influx of intuited representations. Pure conceptions condition sensibility, empirical conceptions condition thinking. — Mww
Kant wouldn’t say something like that, for knowledge of all objects is always empirical, and what must first be given is the object itself, insofar as it appears to sensibility. That which is representation must first be perception. — Mww
As for the sentential construction being bound to the categories, considering this proposition is a tenet in speculative metaphysics, for which there is no empirical proofs for its objects derived from experience, the categories are not involved, from which follows the construct is not bound by them. Every object of theoretical speculation is transcendental; there are no faculties of human intelligence in concreto. — Mww
What is IN phenomenological possibility? I don’t recognize phenomenological possibility, and I certainly have no idea what is IN possibilities. Nothing is IN a possibility, it is never schema but has schemata under it, re: the schema of possibility is determination of a representation in any time. Common-speak being…that thing that doesn’t appear to me is no possible experience for me. — Mww
In things that are possible is not the same as what is in possibilities. I mean….what sense does it make to ask if a thing has possibility, when all we want to know is if the thing is possible. The former presupposes the thing being asked about, which proves it must be a possible thing. — Mww
Which reduces the whole mess to the notion that categories can never be predicates, but only subjects, in logical propositional constructs, and as such, derivatives of what is IN possibilities becomes unintelligible. — Mww
If that’s the case, his successors treat it as the proverbial red-headed stepchild, to which Kant would have vehemently objected. Ripped the concept of phenomena right outta its old-fashioned sandbox, consigned it to a post-modern tarpit. — Mww
So that which is not understood never appears? Guy’s walking down the street, hears a loud bang from around the corner. An appearance to his ears, manifesting as a sensation of sound is immediately given, without him immediately understanding the cause of it. — Mww
Something does not appear iff there is no effect on the senses. If there is an effect, if the senses are affected, there is necessarily an appearance. Full stop. There is no cognitive power in mere perception, therefore any cognitive function is irrelevant with respect to it. On the other hand, something does not become cognized until it is understood. — Mww
What you specify as a “trick” of philosophy, is nothing but some arbitrary, indiscriminate iteration of human intelligence bringing itself to the fore. Different human, different iteration, different form of the same intelligence. Another one might say the duty of philosophy is to discover apodeitically that by which such intelligence manifests, but for which language has no relevance except for expressions of such discoveries. — Mww
How do we have knowledge? I feel idealism and materialism and realism all have their points. But they all seem to have limitations too. Phenomenology seems interesting, but it too, seems to be only emphasising on the experience side of perception and knowledge, while mentioning the significance of body, consciousness and intentionality, they don't seem to go deeper into those areas. I could be wrong here. I must admit I hadn't read a lot on phenomenology, and my idea on it is purely from guessing. — Corvus
As regards thought, the phenomenological approach makes sense. In part by removing the Cartesian separation between the mind and the mind-independent and in part by removing the problem of the unknowable thing-in-itself. Phenomenology attempts to create the conditions for the objective study of what is usually regarded as subjective, our judgements, perceptions and emotions of our conscious experienced sensations. Phenomenology rejects both Rationalism and Empiricism in favour of the person's lived experiences. — RussellA
Conceived in thought. I don’t know what that means. There are so many forms of pure a priori cognitions, or so many dissimilar applications of them, I wouldn’t be so ready to call out their conditions. But generally, pure a priori cognitions belongs to reason, which eliminates them from the spontaneity of conceptions, hence “conceived in thought”, which belong to understanding. — Mww
Phenomenon is the undetermined object of intuition**, which makes explicit no conception is as yet thought as belonging to it. It is merely the matter of sensation given a posteriori, synthesized with the some relevant form residing a priori in the subject himself. To say it is blind is merely a euphemism indicating nothing can be done with representations in this condition, until understanding gets its grubby paws on it and does its rule-bound logical thing. It thinking thing, donchaknow, by which conceptions are connected to that phenomenon, the condition for a possible objective, that is, empirical, cognition.
**depending on translator; some call it appearance. Either way, the salient point is, undetermined) — Mww
Which leads me to this: what is you opinion on the presence of, or the validity in conditioning the human cognitive system on, imagery? — Mww
There seems to be three main theories of perception: Idealism, Direct Realism and Indirect Realism. — RussellA
There is the question about the role of language in distancing the language user to their world.. As the Direct Realist directly perceives the world as it is, there is no distance between themselves and the world. As the Indirect Realist only indirectly perceives the world as it is, there is a distance between themselves and the world. As both the Direct and Indirect Realist use the same language, it does not seem that it is language that is opening up a distance between the observer and the world — RussellA
Problem with phenomenology is that it is another Kantian idealism without Thing-in-itself. — Corvus
Not all thought; thought determined from sensibility only, related to appearances. The categories do not have anything to do with pure a priori cognitions. — Mww
Nahhh….phenomena are representations, defined by the synthesis of matter and form, long before understanding exercises its logical function. We are not cognizant of phenomena, which is what you mean by saying they are blind, so….. — Mww
Ahhhh…..speaking. One can construct his thoughts without speaking, but he cannot speak without constructing his thoughts. — Mww
Why are we continuing this conversation, when you can’t seem to find anything good about it? — Mww
Why are our thoughts different from our senses in that the content of thoughts cannot be doubted? — Kranky
It is definitely the case that the Moon doesn't exist in me when I am seeing it. It exists out there in space somewhere. It also is the case that the Moon causes the image to appear in my mind when I am seeing it, because when some nights it is raining or cloudy, the image of the Moon doesn't appear in my mind at all even if I try to see it.
A lot of processes happen physiologically, neurologically and chemically in the body and brain when we see an object. It is not a simple event even if we say "I see it there" sounding simple.
The image of the Moon in our mind is not the biological, neurological or chemical substance in the brain or retina, but something immaterial which emerged from the brain as an abstract entity which is the same nature as concepts. — Corvus
But how can it be closed?
Our only direct knowledge is that of the sensations in our five senses.
We perceives shapes and colours, relations and quantities, which are clearly not the thing in the world.
From these sensations alone we infer a world that has caused these sensations
We can only make inferences when moving from the epistemology of our sensations to the ontology of a presumed world, but inference is not knowledge
Even though we only know our own sensations, there is an intersubjective agreement about things like the Moon, but is this public agreement about our intersubjective sensations or about a thing in the world causing these sensations? — RussellA
he analytic/synthetic dichotomy only refers to the relations of subject/predicate conceptual content. Any thought, that is, any cognition by means of conceptions, is analytic if the conceptions in the subject relate in a certain way to the conceptions in the predicate, but synthetic if they do not. — Mww
Tree is a particular thing, of all possible things; thought of things in general is possible only under a universal conception, a category. Thought is not always of things, but may be of ideas or mere notions, for which no thing is cognizable as relating to it, in which case understanding has no need of the categories, and the idea is itself the universal, re: justice, beauty and the like. The categories belong to understanding and apply only to phenomena; the universals belong to pure reason alone and never apply to phenomena. — Mww
But thought, in and of itself alone, in its empirical nature, is the act of referring a given intuition to an object by means of a conception. It is absurd to suppose we cannot have any such thought, nonetheless in and of itself alone, as doesn’t have an intuition given from an object of the senses. — Mww
I might be inclined to accede to the idea that transcendental refers to the structure of thought of a certain mode, but less so as reference to the structure of thought in general. In general, transcendental refers to the structure of experience, in that by it certain kinds are either impossible, or merely illusory. — Mww
Concepts involved in some manner or other are found in every aspect of Kantian critique. — Mww
Not all thinking for anybody is synthetic, re: principles. But I agree all analysis of the nature of thinking must be done from within the medium being analyzed. — Mww
It’s all both?
Transcendental refers to a certain mode of cognition, so, no, not all his thinking is in that mode, even if he made a name for himself by rebutting Hume in the proving the possibility of it and validity of its use.
Transcendental this or transcendental that merely describes the origin of, and the limitations for, the conceptions in use. There is empirical thinking, rational thinking….hell, there’s magical thinking. Transcendental thinking is just a higher level of plain ol’ thinking. — Mww
A ultra-modern phenomenologist chastising an Enlightenment continental philosopher. Where’s the news…or indeed the value….in that? — Mww
Supposed to be? Who says? How can anything entirely outside possible understanding be supposed at all, much less supposed as an all-encompassing metaphysic? Noumena is nothing but a conception, for which there is no possible representation, which, incidentally, falsifies the claim that all subjectivity is imprisoned by them. — Mww
If there is a thing having reasonable status by my understanding of it, which implies a non-contradictory judgement, why would I invite doubt to come into play? Doubt arises when the status of a thing is understood as something less than reasonable, meaning, in short, the concepts under which the representation of the thing is subsumed, do not belong to each other with sufficient justice. — Mww
Reality is entirely other, by definition, re: that which corresponds to sensation in general. How he came up with that definition is an example of his transcendental thinking, but it is not a proper indication of why his thinking is called transcendental. Given his definition of what thinking is, it is clear not all his thinking, nor anyone’s for that matter, is transcendental, but is only so from the relation of conceptions, or the origin of the ideas, contained in it. — Mww
This other….the aforementioned “other”, as in, reality? That which corresponds to sensation in general can never be representation, so you’re saying Kant was mistaken in not realizing it actually is? So he got his entire paradigm-shifting, drop-your socks, OMG metaphysical do-over….wrong????
Nahhhh, he didn’t get it wrong; other folks just think they got it more right, when all they really got, was different. — Mww
The Idealism of Berkeley doesn't think that anything physical exists outside the mind. — RussellA
It exists in the physical world with no relation to the mind. However, when you perceive it, it appears in your mind. It doesn't exist in your mind. Your mind just sees it. Seeing is not existing itself. — Corvus
Which would be a more appropriate word, do you think? And, to what would that word be applicable?
What he thinks….covers a lot of ground. Got something in particular in mind, relative to his doubting? — Mww
I'm familiar with the broad critiques of 20th century philosophy. I am not really a fan though. For one, they very often start from the premises of the Anglo-empiricist tradition (even if this is normally to somehow debunk it), or draw on those who did (e.g. Wittgenstein), but I think those premises are quite deficient. That and you get a sort of broad rejection of the pre-modern tradition, largely on the back of Kant's charge of dogmatism and Heidegger's charge of "ontotheology." — Count Timothy von Icarus
I think these critiques are far weaker than is generally acknowledged, and start from an inaccurate understanding of "classical metaphysics." For example, as Gadamer and others have pointed out, Heidegger starts from the late-medieval nominalism he is familiar (e.g. Suárez) with and then backwards projects this onto classical metaphysics writ large. Yet neo-scholastics and Catholic philosophy more generally tends to look at the late-medieval/Reformation period as one giant "wrong turn" in philosophy to begin with. — Count Timothy von Icarus
The reduction of "reason" (and the activity of the intellect more generally) to discursive ratio alone is a primary culprit here, and the post-structuralist epistemic challenges don't seem immune from this tendency. More broadly, the entire notion of reason as primarily occurring within the context of "language games" tends to be simply presuppose this view of reason, and normally many of the Anglo-empiricist epistemic presuppositions (again, even if they oppose that camp's conclusions). Likewise, the emergence of Sausser's semiotics, and the resultant decoupling of the sign and signified requires that one not begin from the tripartite semiotics embraced by C.S. Peirce, John Deely, etc., which comes out of the Latin tradition (originally from Saint Augustine in the Doctrina Signorum). — Count Timothy von Icarus
This perhaps explains an historically interesting phenomenon. Catholics love their phenomenology. Husserl's prize student Edith Stein is a Catholic saint. The phenomenologist philosopher Karol Józef Wojtyła became the pope and saint John Paul II. Ferdinand Ulrich is another example, or Hans Urs von Balthasar or Erich Pryzwarra. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Yet the epistemic and metaphysical conclusions reached in this alternate tradition tend be quite different (and in some sense, vastly more optimistic). I cannot help but think that this divergence comes from avoiding some of the bad epistemic premises that come down through Hume and Kant and dominate both analytic and continental thought (although prehaps overcome in Hegel to some degree), and the deflation of reason (a sort of concomitant of Charles Taylor's "buffered self," which trends in continental thought, enactivism, etc. have tried to overcome, but often without wholly leaving behind some of its presuppositions). My take is that there is a certain forgetfulness here, an inability to see other options because history has been swept aside by the "devastating" charges of the "critical philosophy." — Count Timothy von Icarus
No, I don't. I think we are in agreement here? I was just pointing that out as a common position that seems relevant to the consideration of "what it is like to be..." I think human imagination, while fallible, is capable of accurately covering such ground to varying degrees, and I also think that claims to special epistemic status due to being a member of a group tend to be bunk. This is not to say they might not be appropriate in some cases, but they are often called upon to adjudicate questions in economics, political science, etc., where I think the special pleading is not appropriate. — Count Timothy von Icarus
don't see language as a "barrier," here. I think language, sign systems, models, etc. (and the senses) are best thought of a means of knowing, that through which we know, not what we know. The sign vehicle in the semiotic triad is not some sort of impenetrable barrier that forever keeps the object and the interpretant separated, but is rather the very means of their nuptial union, which is why the sign relation is irreducibly triadic and defies reductionist analysis. The difficulty in "knowing what it is like to be a bat," rather flows from the difference in sense knowledge (which is itself ultimately a primarily a means). — Count Timothy von Icarus
Even if that were the case, isn’t it necessarily presupposed there is an object to identify, correctly or otherwise? If so, then deny that very same necessary object as a content of perception, is contradictory, from which it follows…..barring absurdity….that object itself cannot be doubted. — Mww
So, is this properly knowledge? It does seem to involve an adequacy of experience to things. If it isn't knowledge, what do we make of the fact that it seems possible to imagine "what it is like to be" more or less accurately, or to gain direct experience in some of these cases? If we aren't gaining knowledge of "what it is like to be..." then what are we gaining? "Memory?" But then it seems we can use that memory to say: "that's not what that is like!" That is, to call some description false, implying that such memories contain truth (and thus knowledge).
I would allow that intellectual knowledge might be most properly called knowledge. However, understanding ("intellectual consideration") would also seem to be of a higher intellectual order than justified propositional belief, and "knowing what it is like to be..." seems to include a crucial element of understanding. Maybe Mary the Color Expert is relevant here too perhaps. The perfection of the conformity of the intellect to being seems like it might require a grasp of things not reducible to language (but of which language can serve as a sign). — Count Timothy von Icarus