• If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    For example, it is conceivable that consciousness of a thought is prior to the thought's intentionality.RussellA

    Perhaps enlightenment is brought to this considering that when certainty is upon one, in some experience or other, it is not the logicality that is insisting, but the world. It is not logic that determines meaningful apriority; it is the existential grounding of the pathos, the affectivity, the value dimension of engagement, that makes this radical affirmation. This is something Kant clearly did not understand. Being in the world is inherently moral/aesthetic, and you find this in Dewey (ARt as Experience, and elsewhere), though Dewey was no metaphysician, Scheler, Von Hildebrandt; and it is in this that the world is self affirming, self evidencing apiori.

    To say consciousnss of a thought is prior to thought's intentionality means that IN the intentional structure there is an inherent self consciousness. Husserl argued like this and that famous essay Sartre wrote, the Transcendence of the Ego, argued against it, because it impeded freedom. I'd have to read about this again to remind me of how this goes.

    Thought must be OF something: Is a sprained ankle intentional? I like hagen dasz, but the noesis of this, the liking regard for it, this can be isolated from noema. How about just being happy? Sitting and doing nothing like a Buddhist, altogether absent of "something"? This is one complaint. Another is that it violates the simplicity of encountering objects in the absolute simplicity of the pure phenomenological. This is Michel Henry, and I think he is right. When the epoche of Husserl is done down to the wire, so to speak, and the conscious encounter is absent of all interpretative impositions, the world looms large in it bare presence of Being.

    Of course, this gets rather technical and alien to common sense. Then again, this is what happens when inquiry goes down that rabbit hole.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    It seems to me by your words, you’re saying the categories have no clear right to do what Kant intended for them, re:, his deduction of them is suspect, or downright illegitimate, therefore they have no sufficient warrant for their employment.Mww

    Right. That is what it amounts to. Kant knew full well that there are no categories. They're noumenal.

    The certainty isn’t in the stone, it’s in the truth of the necessity, which is not outside the logic of my mental affairs.Mww

    Of course it is. What is the stone? It IS sensate intuitions and concepts. And so the stone IS whatever the concept is, and the concept IS its apriori structure. You look out at the horizon of things in your back yard and what do you "see" that is not this? The stone is an intuitive/conceptual construct, and if you remove all perceptual presence, the stone is no longer there. Tree falling in the forest? If no one is there: no tree, no noise, no falling, no forest.

    The stone is not; that which is represented by the word stone, very much is simply out there, independent of my mental affairs. Stone is from those very affairs.Mww

    Well, you may think this, but Kant doesn't. Being "simply out there" is, where, in space? But read the transcendental aesthetic: Space is an apriori for of intuition.

    There is a relation, but not between the thing out there and my mental affairs with respect to it. The relation binds, through synthesis, the phenomena of intuition in sensibility to the logic of cognition in understanding. The ground for that function of synthesis, is imagination, the rules by which all synthesis abides regarding empirical content, are the categories.Mww

    The thing out there IS your mental affairs. Imagination refers to time. See the deduction, which is a time analysis, and time is the foundation for mental affairs. There is no thing "out there" for out there is an apriori form of intuition.

    If he thought there was a need for it, wouldn’t he have included it in what he’d already said was a completed metaphysical system? Besides, the pertinent fundamental transcendental deduction concerns the possibility of experience, the totality of each being no more than just itself, and of course, the totality of experience in general, is unintelligible.

    Totality of experience is not a thing to which transcendental deductions can apply, but rather, represents an aggregate of individual things, to each of which such deductions would apply. In the thought of them. Experience is merely an end, given from a certain methodological means, hence, being an end, or, object of, is not itself subjected to, the means.

    Why is there a need, and what form would restitution for that need take?

    I mean, it took him ten years and 700-odd pages to construct what he thought he needed, so it seems pretty ungracious to suggest later that he forgot something. I know I’m barely smart enough to understand what he did, but I’m certainly not smart enough to question what he should have done.
    Mww

    Really? It is ungracious to critique the Critique?? Can I talk about Plato? Kant' critiqued Hume, who awoke him from his dogmatic slumber.....but that was wrong??

    He did not think about a critique of being-in-the-world because he didn't think of it. Heidegger did, leaning on Kant. That is the way it works. Kant's was a critique, if you will, of Aristotle, Leibniz, Locke, Hume and the rest

    You think my critical comments are MINE? I read phenomenology, Hegel through the post-post Heideggerians, which is essentially a response to Kant, or better, a moving forth with and from Kant into new horizons. For the next month I will be reading Jean Luc Marion on Givenness. He follows Levinas et al, who follows Husserl, criticizes Heidegger, and is inspired by Kierkegaard who criticizes Hegel, and so on. Marion is fascinating, but one will not understand a word if they haven't read Heidegger or Husserl.

    It all builds into body of inquiry and thought, and for the phenomenologists, it takes one to that terminal point where language meets itself in the world. See Blanchot. You might want to read his Thomas the Obscure, and his Space of Literature and The Infinite Conversation. Insane at first, but keep at it, and you finally see what they (Beckett and others) are doing, and it is Kant's work that makes this all possible, because his rationalism is so brilliant and well conceived, he opened a new door to philosophy: the door to critiquing Kant!

    And saying you are not smart enough is like you are begging to be told what to think. I certainly don't understand the entire Critique, few do. Only Kant scholars, and they are mostly just, well, scholarly, meaning they have good memories, and perhaps are analytically and synthetically able, but that doesn't mean they have deep insight.

    Kant didn't understand Kant perfectly well because he at once denied metaphysics and did this in a grand metaphysical thesis. Put philosophy in the hands of a logician, and you will get a thesis about logic and meaning will be treated accordingly. But the attempt to discuss the nature of logic IN a logically structured language setting is blatant question begging, that is, it assumes what needs to be shown.

    So all you’re saying is that he didn’t really deduce anything, when he states for the record that transcendental deductions are “…. an examination of the manner in which conceptions can apply à priori to objects…”, which appears to presuppose the conceptions being applied.

    If appearance tells me a thing exists, logic tells me its existence is necessary. I have no need to deduce any of those pure conceptions justifying my logic, beyond the authority they impose on my thinking. This is what his successors meant by telling us all about what we couldn’t talk about. It isn’t and never was what we can’t; it’s because there no need.
    Mww

    But it IS that you can't, simply because to do so would require the very categorical functions in need of explaining. But the need for doing this is that it takes philosophy to a threshold: a place where language and its logic confront language and its logic. Language has been very useful in dealing with the world, but metaphysics has been an awful matter to clear up, what with Platonism, Christian theology, rationalism, empiricism, and a lot of just bad metaphysics in ethics, epistemology/ontology, and so on. Kant takes the very structure of reason itself and declares a speed limit, a point where logic cannot go, and this is beyond its own representational delimitations.

    But then, metaphysics still beckons! The categories are this: that which cannot be though in itself, but thought nevertheless IN representational possibilities. It has to be understood that whenever one says anything, the categories are presupposed, and so the "saying" cannot be about these. They belong to metaphysics, but you could say "good" metaphysics, because...consider this passage from the Dialectic:

    It is therefore correct to
    say that the senses do not err not
    because they always judge rightly but because they do not
    judge at all. Truth and error, therefore, and consequently also
    illusion as leading to error, are only to be found in the judgment,
    i.e. only in the relation of the object to our understanding.
    In any knowledge which completely accords with the laws
    of understanding there is no error.In a representation of the A 294
    senses as containing no judgment whatsoever there is also
    no error. No natural force can of itself deviate from its own
    laws.
    Thus neither the understanding by itself (uninfluenced
    by another cause), nor the senses by themselves, would fall
    into error.


    Do you notice something a bit fishy here? If the senses do not err because they do not judge at all, then isn't this an admission that the sense qua sense is of the same ontological status is noumena? That is, an absolute? He is right, sensory intuitions are not mistakenly acknowledged, but just because they are acknowledged in the understanding leaves open the question, how is it that they are acknowledged at all AS SUCH? You can say this can only be in the understanding and so to speak at all of sensory intuitions one is thus bound categorically, but this is not what he is saying, or is it? What I am saying above here, is that the pure concepts are "good metaphysics" because it is not a lot of dogmatic foolishness, but is grounded on the way language itself offers its own structure up to itself for review. What you get is a "representational" view of what it is for things to be representations, and it can never get beyond this because it will always be thought begetting thought. And this just has to be accepted....

    UNLESS, of course, we take Kant at his word, and the sensory intuitions do not err. And the same must be said about the pathos, or the emotions, or the affectivity (which I choose). There is a fascinating piece of reasoning here. I can only apprehend such things, which cannot be in error, IN the understanding (and hence the categorical form); however, when I do this, I am faced with something that lies outside this categorical condition, even though it is beheld IN it, the sight, the smell, the music, the love, the suffering, and so on. Kant wants to say that no matter what, the content is conditioned apriori, and we can accept this, say, but this does not alter the nature of the content as what it is; it merely says that it must have this formal structure that apprehends it. The affective dimension of our existence remains what it is, and this presence is unerringly before us.

    By Cartesian standards, this makes the sensory intuitions as well as anything at all that "appears" before us, a headache, a heartbreak, a delicious desire, and so on, an apodictic foundation for ontology. Not the categories, but the content are "pure" in their being there, failing to be acknowledged for what they truly are because judgment about them is clouded by daily life entanglements and sciences presumptions.

    Note that this apodicticity, that of the affectivity, the kind of thing Kant explicitly wants to be excluded from the essence of our existence, is the palpable real's essence, not the essence of vacuous reason.

    The term “exist” is a conception, yes, which can be predicated of things. Existence gives the principle of subsumption for particular things as a condition for them, yet can never be itself a predicate. It follows that the criteria for a pure conception, is that it is always the subject of a proposition and from which is given a principle in relation to time, and cannot be a predicate in the cognition of things. Existence is, therefore, not just a conception, but a pure conception.

    In much the same way is “space” a conception. But insofar as space is the condition of the sensing of things rather than the thinking of them, it is not a pure conception, but instead, a pure intuition, holding to the same transcendental manner of applying a priori to objects but not contained in them.
    Mww

    If you want to think like Kant, okay. But really? Existence is just a principle on the impossible side of phenomena? This makes existence something OTHER than the physical imposition of that tree in my perceptual encounter. IF this exhausts what existence IS, then you should not wonder why Kant' is so assailable. Not that the apprehension of a tree contains no logicality in the judgment about it, but that existence is (putting Heidegger aside) blunt confrontation with the world like a baseball bat coming hard down on one's knees, or the delicate and nuanced feel of silk to the touch, or the agony of love lost, or..... Existence is what issues from the presence of the world as it is present, as it IS, and certainly not from some distant noumenal category of pure reason.

    No Kant never thought of this. He was too busy reducing the world to thought qua thought. Again, not that he was wrong at all. But that the rationalism that dominates his thesis is wrong if it is meant to be exhaustive in its determination as to what it is to be human.

    Ok, so if I see a thing and know what it is, that’s called experience and makes explicit the thing I see has run the full gamut of cognition. It follows that if I’m seeing a pot, I must be thinking the concept in order to know what I’m seeing this time conforms to the thing I saw at some antecedent time and by which I first knew that thing as a pot. If I see and know a thing I must have actualized the concept.

    On the other hand, what do I care about not actualizing a concept when I’m not thinking about some thing? I can almost guarantee I’m NOT thinking about a hellava lot more things than I am.

    When I’m looking at and knowing a pot, and the guy says frying pan….why is it that I don’t hand him the pot? I didn’t hand him the pot only because what I heard him say doesn’t sound like the name of what I see? Wouldn’t I have to actualize both concepts, think the thing belonging to this sound and think the thing belonging to that sound, in order to judge whether or not the sound I heard properly represents the thing I see?

    If I have to actualize concepts for the relations of different sounds, why wouldn’t I have to actualize concepts in the relations of what I know?
    Mww

    I'll follow this bit by bit:

    The first paragraph: but when you see an object, you generally are not "thinking the concept" but rather, the recognition is spontaneous. But yes, your concepts are temporal in nature, and it is the past informing the present. Husserl calls this predelineation: you walk into an environment like a kitchen or a classroom, whatever, and you already know everything, and can instantly produce language that is contextualized in ways that agree with everyone else. It only becomes explicit if it is called upon to be so, as when someone asks you where you bought that pot. But the familiarity hovers, like a halo, speaking phenomenologically, or an aura, such that when your glance turns to a spatula, and a new set of languages possibilities come into play implicitly, and things are ready to hand to deal with. Actualized, as you say.

    When you are not thinking about a spatula, you have not entered into this region of possible thought, and at that time, you don't occurrently care. You do, however, predispositionally care, such that when such an environment comes into play, things are there and ready to hand. True, at any given moment, what you are not regionally taking up is vastly more than what you are. Heidegger calls this general body of possibilities das man, "the they".

    So why is it problematic that you would have more than one concept in play at once? Actualizing a concept can be a mere glance as you write a letter, check the time, and shoo a fly away. The fly is familiar and its presence temporally predelineated, hence the spontaneous shooing, and if one comes up to you and inquires about the fly, the language is there, ready to hand. This is Heidegger's "space". Very different from things physically near and far. Things are near when their relevance hovers close by, as when you think of your good friend and not the glasses on your nose: the friend is much "closer" than your glasses. You see his point: it is rare that you are not engaged in-the-world, and this engagement is YOU, your dasein, your being there. Language is what discloses the world to you, so environments are not spatial in the Kantian sense at all, for your existence is not this kind of spatiality. Your "space" is on of meanings, as you slip in and out of regional contexts. Here I am, sitting here, a stray thought occurs, the relief I finished my taxes, then I think about how little I made this year, and so on. These are "spatial" movements for Heidegger, and this movement into some context he calls deseverance.

    Of course, you do actualize relations between sound as well as between concepts. I must be missing something.

    That’s my opinion.Mww

    I am sure there was a time when there was no language. But the quote by Barnet Newman tries to show that language is truly primordial, found in the squawks and shrill cries of animals. The way this ws taken up was in a conversation about the depths of subjectivity and language. You might want to read this short piece, The Sublime Is Now.

    The world is not given the same logical structure because we don’t know enough about it. Still, what we do know about it can be said to demonstrate logical structure in its relations to us, the simplest being near or far.

    The genesis of logical structure is in us, and it is impossible that we do not know that very structure which we construct for ourselves, the simplest of that being A = A.

    The world is just there, and we determine for ourselves how it is to be understood. Just because we say roses are red doesn’t indicate the impossibility that they be anything else, but only that they are that for us. By the same token, if the rose is red regardless of what we say, it is red necessarily. Our intelligence is not equipped to say which is the case.
    Mww

    This I'll have to address later, when I return from my trip abroad.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Kant did not believe that everything must be reduced to representation.RussellA

    Yes he did.

    Descartes said that there were no thoughts about which we are unconscious. In addition, he said that whilst the object of perception may be doubted, the perception itself cannot be doubted.RussellA

    This is an issue. If I think, then the thought has content. It is never stand alone thinking, and if one is thinking about some object---a stone, a cloud, another thought, a feeling, whatever, then that object is an inherent part of the apodictic affirmation. Descartes cogito is an inherent affirmation of the world's "objects", physical or otherwise.

    However, there is an academic dispute whether Descartes believed that a thought can be non-intentional.RussellA

    The proof would be in the Meditations. But he did, after all, have to bring in impossibility of God to deceive to affirm everything else. I am saying (following my current crush, Michel Henry) that the cogito, "I think" is an abstraction from the object/consciousness unity.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    The hand that cannot grasp itself’Wayfarer

    To me, phenomenology inevitably becomes a mysticism. I mean you end up with a transcendental mystery about your own existence, others, too, but indirectly. The Buddhist is the quintessential phenomenologist.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Therefore, Kant might have said "I think about my hand as an object of experience, not as it is in itself, but as it appears within the limitations that the Categories have imposed on it"

    Kant might have more simply said "I think about a representation"

    It is certainly not the case as Henry suggests that Kant is saying "I represent to myself that I think".
    RussellA

    I think this is right. The "myself" as a transcendental Unity of Apperception is entirely "absent". What Henry IS going to say is that Kant's is a thorough reduction to representation, and therefore all is lost, knowledge of the world and of oneself. This is going to inspire the positivists, as well as the idealists, ironically.

    Henry holds that when phenomenology is taken to its only possible telos, and the reduction reveals to one the bare presence of existence. Husserl is right, and one's consciousness and the object cannot be separated (though objects come and go, and vary in nature). They are a singularity! And therefore the search for apriority sought by Kant is now materialized in the actuality . And this is, I believe, momentous. For now philosophy is free to discuss this unity. A cup IS the unity of what was once called into question in a division between mind and body, thought and thing, and so forth. The cup Is the affectivity, the anticipation, the rational structure, all of the "secondary qualities", and so on, as well as beyond perceptual grasp, that is, transcendence; or better, transcendence itself is IN the unity; the unity is itself transcendence. Note that when one says the cup exists, the ground for this existence cannot come from the cup as a thing that transcends consciousness (science), for this makes existence completely alien to understanding. The ground must lie in the existence of one's own agency that is always already in the immediacy of the apprehending of the cup.

    Descartes was right in the essential method: it is a kind of apophatic method of removing all that stands outside certainty to see what remains, and one can, Kant shows in explicit detail, doubt everything, even thought itself, and this will take some very interesting twists and turns in post modern thinking, but where Descartes' reduction finds the cogito, Henry, following Husserl, sees that this is plainly absurd, for one cannot even imagine thought unbound, in its nature, to the world. There is no such thing as a disembodied thought, and it is not, "I think, therefore I am," but, "I am in a world, therefore I am." This is the beginning for apodictic affirmation of the world, and it puts all thoughts of dualism to rest, because such things only follow AFTER the foundational affirmation. Being-in-the-world is first, primordial.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    A hand cannot grasp itself, but nevertheless, is proof of an external world, as Moore wrote in Proof of an External World

    In addition, as Descartes might have said, "I think about my hand, therefore I am".

    In fact, it seems that my hand not only proves my existence but also that of the external world.
    RussellA

    But you move too quickly. Not the external world, but externality itself is a dimension of perceptual event and the perceptual event is a dimension of externality. They are one! as witnessed IN the milieu of the subject.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    “This”, here, is thinking, and your idea that what’s beneath thinking is impossible to talk about. I would extend that to your question, “what is logic”. Other than bare definition, what’s beneath logic, is impossible to talk about.Mww

    Wittgenstein would say yes, at least in the Tractatus (which he says, paradoxically, is nonsense!). I "see" logic in judgments like, It won't rain unless there are clouds, and in universal statements like, All Catholics believe Jesus is God's son, but the genesis of this structure cannot be witnessed. As Witt said, to do so would be to draw a line between the logic as shown and the explanatory or meta language used to say what it is. BUt this metalanguage would then need the same meta analysis, and so on. This is the paradox of language and metaphysics. Where did all this talk about God come from? From something that was already there, in the language, like constructions of God's omnipotence, omniscience and the rest: just ampilfications of the familiar.

    This is why the positivists loved Wittgenstein. He destroyed metaphysics in a simple stroke of well reasoned thought. But they never read Heidegger. Husserl announced that phenomenology is the REAL positivism. I think he is right.

    I’m not sure what you mean by transcendental thinking. All transcendental is a priori and belongs to reason but thinking both a posteriori and a priori belongs to understanding. In the former is the complete determination of all things in general; in the latter is the determination of one thing at a time. It is by the transcendental substratum for the determination of all things, are given the rules for the possibility of determining particular things. The completely determined in general is an idea; the completely determined in particular is the ding an sich, neither of which is a possible experience.

    If we were in the weeds before, we’re damn near being choked out by them now.
    Mww

    The idea is this: Kant looks at experience and "observes" Aristotle's logical structures. So he identifies logical structures and ask about their genesis---but why is the palpable world not given the same due? Logic is just "there" and we call it apriori because of the necessity of it. But the full totality of our existence is no different in the original evidential provocation. To see this, one turns to Descartes and Hussel's Cartesian approach: Descartes wanted certainty to ground the world in what it is, and he found this in the cogito. To make hundreds of pages short: the cogito cannot be what it is without its object, and so the certainty of the object is necessarily is just as necessary as the cogito because consciousness is always about something. If the cogito is necessarily what it is, then the world the cogito acknowledges is as well. To put is in Kant's language, sensory intuitions are just as necessary as the logic that is "filled" by them. Of course, calling it sensory intuitions is just dismissive.

    What IS this feeling of misery of delight? What IS this curiosity, questioning, body of eyes, nose and skin, perceptual engagement of care, intent, desire; in short, what does it mean to BE here, for a person's whole existence to BE? This question has far more gravitas then pure reason can ever begin to have, and it is simply there, as logic is, seeking, if you will, its transcendental ground.

    See Max Scheler or Von Hildebrandt, the German phenomenologists: It is value, importance itself that is the final analytic of our existence. Pure form literally has no value. Kant was important because he put all eyes on subjectivity, but then he blew subjectivity out of existence. You might find Michel Henry's critique of Kant amusing. The length is I think worthy (my underlines):


    How can one not be struck by this extraordinary
    conceptual situation: it is precisely with Kant, who
    relates the Being of all beings to the Subject, that the
    Subject becomes the object of a radical dispute which
    denies it all possible Being. Or to put it anothey way: it
    is at the very moment when philosophy sees itself clearly
    as a philosophy of the subject that the foundation on
    which it explicitly and thematically bases itself, and
    which it systematically endeavours to elaborate, escapes
    it and, slipping from its grasp, tips over into the void of
    inanity.
    One cannot forget in effect how the rich developments of the
    Analytic end up, like a torrent which
    suddenly dries up, lost in the desert of the Dialectic.
    Now this peculiar turning of the positive into the
    negative happens when the Being of the subject itself
    comes into question, when it is a matter of knowing if
    such a subject exists and, if so, what it might be. The
    Critique of the Paralogism of Rational Psychology in
    fact radically critiques the Being of this subject in such a
    way that anything one might advance about this Being
    includes a paralogism, so that if, in spite of everything, it
    must be spoken about, one can say only that it is an
    "intellectual representation".

    Which means that '~ think" (since we are dealing here
    with the cogito) is equal to "I represent to myself that I
    think". Which means that the Being of the subject is to
    be classed as the object of a representation, an object
    which on the one hand presupposes this subject, and on
    the other never contains by itself, insofar as it is
    represented, the reality
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    I was hoping, by my mention of shoe-tying and book-reading, you might note that my position has always been that humans generally think in images.

    If one speaks to himself, how does he know what to say?
    If to think is to speak to oneself, why not just say one thinks to himself?

    What seems like the proverbial voice in your head is merely extant experience doing its thing, taking up the time when the cognitive part of the system recognizes it’s only repeating itself.
    Mww

    You can say this, that when you are not thinking of a pot and you see and know what it is you are not actualizing the empirical concept 'pot' but ignoring it, at least until, someone says, hand me that pot! and you explicitly hear the word. But consider that the whole culture you live and breathe in has its genesis in language. This was the point about General Motors. Consider what Genera Motors IS. It's not like a cat or a canary or this book such that you can make philosophical issues of body and mind, material and mental, physical and spiritual, and so on. There is none of that "dualism" here, so when we say, think, whatever, what GM IS, we don't have, in the reductive analysis, any ontological difference of this kind. Then what can one say about GM ontologically? If you're Kant, you say it is a diffuse and structured body of conceptuality pragmatically conceived. 'GM' as a concept has no sensory intuitions in its ontology, but when philosophy does its rationalist reduction, it lands where there are, on people, computers, board rooms, chairs and the rest. GM as such doesn't really exist at all outside this contrived context; OTOH, hard to imagine something like this not "existing"---it's in the news, millions are talking about it, employs thousands, has global connectedness, etc.

    Here is where I leave Kant, or, I left him much earlier but now do so explcitly. It might be interesting to see how he could talk about this, but I don't have time for radical ontological rationalism in trying to understand this world. The point I am making is that GM's presence in our everyday lives is a pragmatic language construction, and this is no different from empirical concepts themselves: Everything we "are" and everything we encounter is pragmatically conceived. This is the structure of time itself.

    Is it that once there was no word for anything? Or that language was there at the very beginning, and as our distant ancestors evolved, so did language? I am reading Barnett Newman's The Sublime Is Now, and he writes

    The human in language is literature,
    not communication. Man's first cry
    was a song. Man's first address to a
    neighbor was a cry of power and
    solemn weakness, not a request for
    a drink of water. Even the animal
    makes a futile attempt at poetry.
    Ornithologists explain the cock's crow
    as an ecstatic outburst of his power.


    I picked this up in a discussion about Heidegger, who understands language to be much deeper in the constitution of our existence. Language erupts, if you will, out of the primordiality of an overwhelming world, and evolves into religion and philosophy as it seeks to understand and speak this primordiality.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Perhaps, depending on context, but I’m claiming the irreducible case, hence regardless of context, is Nature. Language relations with the world presupposes the world, and world being the representation of Nature in general, gives the irreducible.

    Which gets us to….by quid juris is it, that synthetic apriority in language relations with the world, is the case? Which in turn requires the answer to, the case….for what?
    Mww

    It depends on how you are thinking about what "the world" is. If you are referring to the naturalist view science takes, then I would disagree, for science and its naturalism presupposes Kant's world. A geneticist calls it a DNA molecule, while Kant calls it sensory intuitions synthetically taken up by concepts. Both are right, let's say, but Kant;s is more basic, an analysis of the presuppositions science rests on. For Kant, nature is representation, and this means it is not reality, but only empirical reality.

    Nature is certainly not irreducible because when we conceive of what nature is, we find Kant and phenomenology "beneath" what the naturalists can say.

    The case for what? Well, it is the case that this stone cannot move itself. It must be moved by something else, and this holds true by necessity, so how can I know this apodicticity that is IN the stone when the stone stands outside of the logic produced in my mental affairs? It MUST be that the stone is not simply out there in a world that is independent of my mental affairs. Rather, there must be a relation that binds the two. Kant proves this in a transcendental deduction, but because it is only about this logical apriority, he misses the need for a transcendental deduction of the totality of experience. I said this earlier, and it is my take on the matter.

    You might find Eugene Fink's first lines of his Cartesian Meditations interesting. He writes:

    Instead of inquiring into the being of the world, as does traditional "philosophy" dom inated by the dogmatism of the natural attitude, or, where inquiry is not satisfied with that, instead of soaring up over the world "speculatively," we, in a truly "Copernican revolution," have broken through the confinement of the natural attitude, as the horizon of all our human possibilities for acting and theorizing,
    and have thrust forward into the dimension of origin for all being, into the constitutive source of the world, into the sphere of transcendental subjectivity.


    Entirely up to you, but Husserl writes his Cartesian Meditations and gives Fink the final chapter, and you might find the whole thing worthy of reading. Husserl/Fink is a neo Kantian (hence, the reference to the Copernican Revolution) but his "revolution" is more radical.

    Ehhhhh….methinks ‘tis not so much a confession as a sad commentary on the sorry state of speculative metaphysics. Funny, too, in that the historical record exhibits that Kant allowed himself precious few indulgences of any kind, so there wouldn’t be anything of the sort to which a confession of his would refer.Mww

    But his Deduction is analogized to a quid juris legal affair, which has "no clear legal title, sufficient to justify their* employment, being obtainable either from experience or from reason." The absence of a clear title means a kind of shot in the dark, for there is no hope of a determinate conclusion. A bit like a cosmologist taking a stab at what there was prior to the big bang, only much worse,

    I’d also like to revisit your quote in which he says, “…(…) if such exist….”. At the time, as you well know, synthetic a priori cognitions hadn’t been entered into the philosophical vocabulary. He had to prove the validity of the concept, and he said “if they exist” because no one had yet thought about them as existing. And they don’t “exist” in the strict categorical sense, but I already spoke to that.Mww

    But really, all one can every say about these pure forms is that they cannot be spoken of. The term 'exist' itself is concept; what isn't? and thus it gives us a principle of subsumption for particulars. and thus conceived in the very disclosure possibilities that it itself presupposes. Kant knew this. No one can talk about noumena existing. The entire Critique is, as Derrida put it, under erasure, or as Wittgenstein put it, nonsense.

    But I don't think it's nonsense at all because I don't think transcendence belongs to logical extravagance alone, nor is it rationalistic overreach. Kant simply forgot, typical of mathameticians and logicians, thta we exit.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    I would perhaps listen to an art expert's opinion that Derain painted Le séchage des voiles in 1905, but I would take any art expert's opinion that this painting is a great work of art with a pinch of salt, even though in fact I do believe that this painting is a great work of art.

    In the world, objects have properties. It is said that some properties are objective facts, such that Derain's painting was painted in 1905, and some properties are subjective judgements, such that Derain's painting is good.

    Some properties, such as good, are clearly subjective judgements, but other properties, such that this object is a painting, which appear objective facts, are also subjective judgements.

    As you say, Quine points out the indeterminacy of translation.

    Person A born in 1950 and brought up in South Africa and person B born in 2005 and brought up in Nevada will have different understandings about the same concept. For example, person A's concept of a forest, a savanna woodland, will be different to person B's concept of a forest, sparse juniper pine.

    As you also say, in fact, person A's understanding of every concept will be different to person B's understanding of the same concept.

    No concept can be an objective fact in the world, but rather every concept must be a subjective judgement. Not only is saying that Derain's Le séchage des violes is good is a subjective judgment, but even saying that Derain's Le séchage des violes is a painting is a subjective judgment.

    In fact, not only would I take an art expert's opinion that the Derain object is good with a pinch of salt, but philosophically, I should also take the art expert's opinion that the Derain object is a painting also with a pinch of salt.
    RussellA

    When you say calling something good is clearly subjective, this needs a bit of analysis. If by good one refers to a context of good qualities and bad ones, and these qualities are factually given, as when you buy a couch and you are looking for a good one, so comfort, size, fabric and the rest come into play, and these may refer to other objective features, as comfort, for you, means very soft and cushiony, and size refers to the objective dimensions of the new setting, and this explanatory context. it turns out, has a great deal of specificity, but when it comes to the manifest qualities that align with comfort, these can be stated rather plainly. So the "good" of the couch is a mostly public matter, and objective;y conceived when the overt features of the couch are in question. But these features have their telos, if you will. in something that cannot be made public, and this is your sense of comfort itself whether it is comfort about the sitting or about the match to its possible new environment, and the like. Comfort or the good feel of something, this brings in another dimension of expereicne. Not something good FOR, but something just plain Good. the good of pleasure as such, the bad of suffering as such. All contingent goods, goods that are FOR something else, eventually end up at this determinacy, when, plainly put, you just say, I like it! This "liking" is just what it is, and the matter goes no further.

    The attempt to say this is not objective but rather subjective rests with an error made confusing contingent qualities with intrinsic goodness they bring about. Comfort to me may be a "matter of taste" but comfort as such is not. It is only that it occurs in one person's world and not in another's, but its occurence is as objective as it gets. Consider that if you are in agony, it is not a matte of opinion or taste, is it?

    So I argue that the good, as well as the bad (categories of experience merely) are not subjective in the essence of the judgment that is about art.

    And so, if you are aesthetically enraptured (Clive Bell's term) by Derain, I would say true, it is a matter of taste, for, let's say, I am not. But this is not to say the rapture doesn't exist, and IS rapture, and is inherently good as far as this goes. It simply means those contingencies of appreciation are not mine.

    This is not, I argue, unlike what Kant does: get past the contingencies of language's entanglements, the incidental features of the judgments we make, and look into essential structures of those judgments, experiences, and you will find something transcendental. The GOOD is transcendental.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Nope. One has to think to conceive of pure thought, which may then be talked about. One doesn’t talk about that of which he has no conception.Mww

    Talk and think here are the same, as are hand signals, telepathy, facial expressions, brailing, etc., as long as these carry meanings that are structured apriori. Note that when you think you are speaking to yourself.

    You’re asking about justifying a contradiction? Of course one cannot talk about what stands outside of talk. You must realize we invent the objects used to represent our thinking, the words. For whatever is used for thinking, a word can be invented to represent it. Whatever is thought about, a word can be invented to represent it.

    There are no words possible to represent, we cannot meaningfully talk about, only that which cannot be thought, on the one hand, and, we never invent a word then think a conception belonging to it, on the other.
    Mww

    Not about contradiction, but outside of contradiction, affirmation, universal quantifiers, references to particle physics, going out for lunch, and so on. "A word can be invented to represent it": To say "what ever is used for thinking" is a bit shaky, because what is "used" for thinking is thinking, or any of the above I mentioned. But "beneath" this is impossible to talk about. Take contradiction: the difference that constitutes a contradictory proposition is a difference in language, exemplified by alphabetical letters. B is what it is in relation to what it is not, A, and all the rest. Each letter defines the definitional boundaries of the others. Thus, contradiction is a closed systemic affair. This is the way meaning has its identity, IN the matrix of language's differences, or as it has been put, in contexts. "Nothing lies outside the con"text"" is infamous, but the idea is that nothing can "exist" apart from the context in which it is conceived. This all began with Kant. This cat on my lap can only be a cat IN the structured logic that identifies it. What it is "beyond" this is impossible to "say". Pure nonsense to even write these words, 'beyond' and 'say'. This is why they go under erasure as they are put forth.

    Given the subject matter of the Dialectic, I gather that somehow you’re saying Manny’s exposè demonstrating the illegitimacy ol’ Renè’s cogito principle, is just as bad as the principle itself.

    Interesting, but I’d have to think awful hard nonetheless about how sophistical arguments and paralogisms are just as bad as that which guards against them.
    Mww

    I mean to say that Descartes' cogito is an attempt to identify what cannot be doubted and thus serves as an anchor for constructing a justification for positing a world of things. It establishes a ground for all things that is axiomatic and apodictic. This is, essentially, what Kant was doing. This philosophical move to apodicticity began with Descartes, and is still alive in the neo Husserlian thnking.

    Ya know….Kant used mathematics to prove the very possibility of synthetic a priori cognitions. Once their possibility is proved, he then goes about finding them in cognitions other than mathematical. So if it is proven there are rules for understanding, it is perfectly reasonable to suppose there are rules for speaking. On the other hand, while it is perfectly reasonable that to misuse the rules of understanding results in incorrect thinking, it is absurd to suppose the misuse of the rules for speaking results in incorrect speech, or language in general.

    And if I don’t agree logic is discovered, then it follows that the discovery of logic in the rules for speech is beyond the agreement pale.
    Mww

    As long as one doesn't make this reasonable thinking into a transcendental affirmation. It certainly works in familiar matters in the world. You witness something, some gaseous presence on the planet Jupiter, understand that this can only be there if certain conditions apply, etc. but to determine those conditions one has to theorize, let's say, because they are not in the empirical evidence itself, but this theorizing must issue from a matrix of understanding that itself has a proper evidential ground. Transcendental thinking says this evidential ground is absent, but we are going to use language that gets its meanings from things that do have this ground.

    But you can't do that. Or can you? I claim, and you know this is THE issue of all issues in philosophy (given that I read continental philosophy, and very little of the analytical tradition) there IS a ground for transcendental thinking. It is our being0in-the-world in which it is found, but remains marginalized because science has such sway in this culture. This will pass.


    Maybe they are, but why can’t a postulate have a use in keeping with the theory to which it belongs. Sorta like Newton’s g: no such thing but a necessary component in the law of universal gravitation.Mww

    You mean there is something about Kant's transcendental thinking that cannot be dismissed! Most definitely! Kant is essential, for me. Deeply profound, but he is nevertheless relegated to the history of philosophy outside of continental thinking. Though this may be changing, because anaalytic thinking has worn out its welcome, I mean, there are important things, but its dismissal of metaphysics is impossible to defend.

    I argue that metaphysics cannot be removed from immanence, what is there before our waking eyes. I think I mentioned that to me, Kant's shortcoming was that he didn;t see that IF one is going to make a transcendental move, it is because he faces something that is present in the world first, and this something is simply given, for him, in the structure of logic discovered in language, everyday language, there, always already there, in Hi, how are you? Look, the rock is going to fall!, and everything else. But this givenness is in ALL things, in the totality of givenness. The world IS givenness, and thus, transcendental thinking is not to be treated abstractly, but existentially, and this changes everything. Value, what Wittgenstein refused to talk about (think about, brail about, whatever), is the essence of aesthetics and ethics. This is transcendental, and morality now finds its true ground for a "good will" and it's not in the deontological ground given by rationality.

    Ethics' essence is found in affectivity, the kind of thing Kant strictly and explicitly dismisses.


    Yes, but the evidential basis for their use lies exclusively in some speculative idea of a system. One who thinks a metaphysical system comes to be on account of the speaking of it, still has to explain where the speaking came from. Not only that, but how to explain, in one example of a veritable plethora thereof, how Joyce and Gell-Mann related the same word for entirely different chains of thought.Mww

    I understand this in terms of contextuality and language games. But then, one inevitably encounters actuality. This is why Witt in the Tractatus said the world and ethics and aesthetics were transcendental and nonsense. He was dismissive of such talk, but then, he never read Heidegger. When is metaphysics NOT metaphysics? When it is dicovered in the analytic of the Real.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    The aesthetic can be looked at in two ways. Firstly, the term was initially used by Alexander Baumgarten. It was borrowed from the Greek word for sensory perception, to denote concrete knowledge that we gain through our senses. Secondly, as a synonym for "taste", in being able to distinguish between those objects worthy of contemplation and those objects not worthy. When we observe an object about which we have a subjective aesthetic feeling, either we have an aesthetic feeling because the object is an aesthetic object, or the object is not an aesthetic object but we are able to perceive an aesthetic in the shapes and colours we experience as sensory phenomena. Post-Kant, the aesthetic is considered as the synthesis of both these, sensory experience and intellectual judgment.RussellA
    These beg the basic question: what is the aesthetic experience "as such"? The Greek sense has no bearing here; and to refer to "taste" simply shows how misaligned philosophy was with the world. Ask, what is the world? with only true descriptive intent, putting aside the zeal for objectifying and categorizing, and one finds something that altogether defies philosophical objectification, and this is where the significance, is discovered. What is sought, as with Kant, is something that is a stand alone, or, as Kierkegaard put is, "stands as its own presupposition". He thought this could only lie in transcendence, but he really didn't understand that if transcendence is what must account for what is witnessed in logic, then the same goes for all of experience, or all of being-in-the-world.

    Consider aesthetics as modality of value, and value to refer to a dimension of our existence that deals with the "good" and so the question goes to the nature of the this very mysterious term, mysterious when considered phenomenologically, and not in some framework of contingency that explains matters is "other terms" and in doing this endlessly begs the question regarding these terms, and then the terms used to account for these, and on. This touches on Derrida, doesn't it? And it is not going to find relief in the traditional thinking.

    You raise the question as to whether science has an interest in the aesthetic features of science, and as to whether that science is in its essence, aesthetic. Science starts with particular observations, and its goal is to discover from these particular observations universal laws. Such universal laws enable science to predict future phenomenal states. There are two ways of doing this. Either by looking at each particular observation one at a time and through reason and logic combine them into a whole, or by immediately perceiving a gestalt, an immediate unity of parts as an aesthetic. In Kant's words, a unity of apperception. Kant's transcendental apperception is the uniting and building of coherent consciousness out of different elementary inner experiences. Such experiences differ in both time and topic, but all belong to the individual's self-consciousness. Science discovers universal laws from particular observations, both by logical reasoning about the parts making up a whole and by aesthetic intuition about a whole made up of parts .RussellA

    Note that you are right say I raised the question as to whether science has interest in aesthetics, but not that wondered if science is in its essence, aesthetic. On the matter I did express interest in, forget about Kant, whose thoughts about aesthetics are complicated, needlessly, if you ask me, and ask why science cannot speak about aesthetics or ethics. It is because these are not discovered empirically. The essence of aesthetics is value, and this is not detectable in a telescope, a microscope, nor in quantitative discussions about these. It is like Michel Henry said regarding science's reductive attempts: tear apart the observable things of a human body, and you will not find a "self" anywhere; you will not find fear, desire, love, hate, anticipation, delight, and so on. None of this shows up, and none of this essential ground for aesthetic and ethical affairs.

    Thus science has no interest because it cannot have an interest. There is nothing to "observe". But then, the essence of aesthetics is, again, value, that is--no value, no aesthetics. So as Kant said, we go around talking as if our judgments about art are objective, but the ground for this lacks universality, and being a good rationalist, this undoes its objectivity. But not really. The question goes to apodicticity: what is the basis for universality and necessity? Rationality's apodicticity lies not in intersubjective agreement, but in its intrinsic properties, e.g., it is the structure itself of something like modus ponens that mkes for its apriority, and this has nothing to do with what others think, so we put aside this disagreement that qualifies something as mere "taste" and we ask simply if the aesthetic "presence" is qualitatively apodictic, that is, does it possess necessity?

    For this we move to a deduction, that is, we reduce the aesthetic/ethics event to its essence (as Kant did with reason) and in this we discover the "pure" affective dimension of our existence (as Kant discovered pure reason). Note how in actual experience, there is no such thing as this purity, for experience is always already entangled. But this is an analytic exercise, and the purity in question is an abstraction from the totality of experience; but having said this, it by no means means that what is isolated for discovery isn't really there. Just the opposite. The whole point is to show that it IS.

    What does one discover in this sketch of a transcendental deduction to "pure" aesthetics? One finds the good and the bad, the bonum and the malum, if you like, for the Latin terms pulls thought away from mundanity. What Moore once called non natural properties, something analytic philosophers cringe at.

    Of course, an actual deduction like this would take a great deal of "quid juris" work, as Kant put it, but I think it works.

    You also raise the question about Kant's rationalism, his logical reasoning. Though, as Hume said, reason cares nothing for human existence. In fact, reason does not "care" at all. Kant combined Rationalism with Empiricism though Transcendental Idealism. Rationalism is the belief that particular sense experiences are necessary in order for us to discover concepts and knowledge. However, they are not sufficient. One needs in addition the ability to logically reason about these particular sense experiences. Empiricism is the belief, as with Rationalism, that particular sense experiences are necessary in order for us to discover concepts and knowledge. However, for the Empiricists, these experiences can be sufficient. Sometimes, however, logical reasoning may be of assistance in clarifying certain sense experiences. The staring point for both the Rationalist and Empiricist are the phenomena of particular observations. It is through these phenomena that there is the possibility of discovering universal truths. There are two aspects to the aesthetic. First, there is the aesthetic object within sensory experience as an objective entity, and second there is the aesthetic object within the mind as subjective feeling. Science also has two similar aspects. First the particular object experienced as phenomena and second the universal object experienced as a concept. Science is the discovery of the universal from the particular. Science starts with the aesthetic objective object within sense experience and discovers the aesthetic subjective object within a concept.RussellA

    This is exposition. Fine.


    One belief about the aesthetic object is that the aesthetic object needs no practical use to be aesthetic. Taking their cue from Kant, many philosophers have defended the idea of an aesthetic attitude as one divorced from practical concerns. This is a kind of “distancing,” or "standing back" from ordinary involvement. Kant described the recipients of aesthetic experience not as distanced but as disinterested. In other words, the recipient does not treat the object of enjoyment either as a vehicle for curiosity or as a means to an end. They contemplate the object as it is in itself and “apart from all interest.” An object such as a hammer, which has a practical use, is not aesthetic because it has a practical use, but rather an object, such as a Derain painting, which has no practical use, can still be aesthetic. Arthur Schopenhauer argued that people could regard anything aesthetically so long as they regarded it as independent of their will. That is, irrespective of any use to which they might put it.RussellA

    I've always though this a most curious use of the term "disinterested". Yes, I know what he means, but really? I mean there nothing more engaging of one's "interest" than art, music and the affectivity of these. I mean, the very definition of what it is to be aesthetic is to BE interested. At any rate, sure, one is not bound to an end, for the experience is an end unto itself, possesses its own validation, stands as its own presupposition. Take this further: the aesthetic experience as such is not contingent on anything else for being what it is. Kant should see that this is the very goal of the Critique, to discover that which is what it is apart from relational derivation.

    Yet there is a paradox here. On the one hand we observe particular shapes and colours within our phenomenal sensory experience which we intuitively find aesthetic. This does not need a reasoned judgment. On the other hand, we instinctively reason that it is not the case that we subjectively perceive an object as aesthetic, but rather that there will be universal agreement amongst everyone perceiving the same object that the object is objectively aesthetic. The aesthetic object is an object of sensory experience. The aesthetic object is not merely as an object of sensory pleasure but also as the repository of significance and value. This synthesis is summarised in Hegel's "the sensuous embodiment of the Idea". There is the sensory: concrete, individual, particular and determinate, and there is the intellectual: abstract, universal, general and indeterminate. This synthesis however gives rise to a paradox, as described by Kant in his antimony of taste.RussellA

    Hegel is another rationalist, and my approach is to do with reason what Kant did with sensible intuition: essentially dismiss it in the reductive attempt to uncover the nature of the aesthetic, the "pure" aesthetic. I acknowledge reason and language, but this stands outside of the "deduction".

    The human expresses their subjective pleasure in an object as if beauty was an objective property of the object. The human is making a universal general objective judgement about their immediate particular subjective feelings. Feelings about an object are particular and individual, so why do we want universal agreement about the nature of the object. There is a contradiction in making a universal judgment based on particular intuitions. The phrase "aesthetic judgment" is a contradiction in terms, yet we make aesthetic judgements all the time For example, I can accept someone as an expert in nuclear physics, of which I have no experience, yet I cannot accept someone as an expert as to the merits of a Derain painting unless I have had personal experience. There are universal rules in science but no universal rules in beauty. Yet we make aesthetic judgments, such that Derain is a great artist. We can make reasoned justifications for our aesthetic judgements, such as about Derain. We can do this because reasoned justifications can never be purely intellectual but must also be partly based on feeling.RussellA

    Now, this is something you believe to be true, right? You really think that "aesthetic judgment" is a contradiction in terms.

    A few things: A minor point about the physicist and art expert, which is I thing even if you haven't seen a Derain, you would still hold the art expert's opinion high.

    Regarding universality and aesthetic judgment, I argue that Saying X is good may disagree with someone else's opinion about X, BUTthis is because we are not talking about the same X, or, I am talking about X! and the other is talking about X2. X1 is good to me, and it would be good to the other as well IF the other were to experience X1, but she is not, een though X goes by the same name, her X2 is not my X1, because if it were, she would appreciate it just as I do; she would by necessity! Why? Because X1 IS the complex of appreciative factors that fingure into my experience, and they are vast, the vast constituents of all that makes the experience of X1 what it is. The other, were she exactly in my shoes, so to speak, would adore X1 as I do because nothing would change in the equation of X1.

    And this is just what Kant has in mind with universality and necessity and agreement which is not a choice but apodictically coercive in formal dimensions of reason. Note that when I say I agree with you as you affirm the logicality and validity of a syllogism, I do not have direct access to your rational grasp of the syllogism. I simply assume we are witnessing the same thing (you know, Quine indirectly takes this kind of thing to task in his indeterminacy thesis) because we speak the coercivity of it with absolute agreement. Well, the same would be the case if with the aesthetic IF I had access to your X1 instead of my own X2. Ask: assuming you experience X1 and I experience X2, are YOU apodictically coerced in your conviction that the qualities you apprehend in X1 are good? Assuming the X1 is not ambiguous, of course you are. Just as when I feel wonderful, I am apodictically coerced into acknowledging this. Kant is transfixed by apriority, but he should be equally transfixed by everything else, simply because everything else is apodictically coercive in this value dimension of our existence.

    Just ask: there you are in terrible suffering. How certain are you about this, and how does this compare to the universality and necessity of apriority? Is the latter really more so? I think not.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Are we mistaking the description of a system, for its operation?

    Kant is “talking” about his own idea of what’s happening when the human animal uses his intellect.

    What’s the problem with talking about pure thought using language, and exercising pure thought without it? Please don’t tell me you talk to yourself, prescribe in words or logic symbols the individual actions required to tie your shoes. Odd that you can tie your shoes faster than you can prescribe each act required in order to tie your shoes, innit?

    When you’re reading something particularly engaging….ever notice the words merely represent a certain assemblage of conceptions you already have, and the author is only trying to make you mentally image what’s he’s already done for himself. And it’s only in the case where you don’t have for yourself this certain assemblage, that you have to stop and read again, or look up to the sky and….you know, think….about what the author wants you to imagine.

    I have no problem whatsoever asserting that’s the way my system works, and I’m almost as certain that’s the way your system works, too. That language must take precedence, is “….beneath the dignity of philosophy….”**, yet at the same time perfectly authorized to ground “…..philosophizing in an orderly manner….”***
    (**1787; ***1644)
    Mww

    Kant's does talk about pure reason, and it does make sense to do so, I claim. But then, as Wittgenstein said later, it really is nonsense as well, because in order to speak of pure reason, one has to stand apart from it and observe it from another perspective, for not to do this would be assuming what needs to be shown, and this is just question begging: language/logic cannot even imagine its own nature. All it can do is work within what this nature provides. Logic is shown, but cannot show itself, for this source is transcendental, that is, in order for it to understand itself, there would need to be a third perspective that stands outside of whta logic shows and outside of what logic IS, but this third perspective itself would then raise the same question, namely, that regarding the source of its authority, and this would require yet another perspective; and this is an infinite regression. It's a bit like trying to bring to light some absolute notion of velocity: one would have to be "absolutely" still to have this perspective, but how does one determine whether or not one is moving AT ALL? One would have to stand "outside" of movement altogether to talk about how fast something is moving absolutely. But one can't do this for this absolute perspective would always be questionable regarding whether of not IT is moving. One would have to stand outside movement ITSELF.

    So reason asking about the nature of reason really is nonsense. And yet, it makes sense as well, because, and this is a difficult issue, I know, because IN language, language's own foundational indeterminacy is observed, and this is not merely in the logic of words, but is experienced in the uncanniness of our existence. The real question of metaphysics only arises when we acknowledge the givenness of the world as "pure" givenness, that is, the purity of givenness lies with "being as such" the openness of our existence. Kant looks at the world as closed, in both content and logic. If all is well and good, he writes under the heading Transcendental Illusion, "No natural force can of itself deviate from its own laws. Thus neither the understanding by itself (uninfluenced by another cause), nor the senses by themselves, would fall into error." What he fails to see is that logic is NOT closed like this, because language, where we find logic, is contingent, and language is contingent because it is historical. In other words, apodicticity is first discovered as a particle of language. Just ask, what is logic? You will find more language. Ask what any of this is, and you will find more language. Language never really "touches" anything beyond language, and yet, as Dewey et al held, it "works"!

    BUT, does this mean the world as it "really is" is just a nonsense term? Like talking about absolute velocity? Tricky. Because as we all know, the world is right there in front of me, and this cannot be doubted, or something there, in its presence, cannot be doubted; impossible to "say" because it is not language. This is where continental philosophy begins, sort of, but I put the inevitable metaethical condition into play: put your finger over a lighted match. Can one doubt this? Now THAT is apodicticity! There is no historicity and its contingency of language here that gives rise to doubt, nor is this an abstraction. It is the opposite of an abstraction, the clearest most vivid thing one can imagine.

    So just to sum up: Kant was seeking a bottom line, and he thought he found it in the purity of logic. But he missed the mark by a mile. We know logic only in the medium of the language that conceives it, and this is discursive, derivative. True apodicticity is found existentially in the only absolute there is, which is outside language. Now, you may see a contradiction here because I argued earlier that language/thought/logic attends everything implicitly in overt experience. This is an issue worthy of discussion.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    And ya know what….logical structure presupposed in understanding a sentence’s meaning, might be restricted to the form of logic, yet the sentence itself by which it is expressed, necessarily concerns the content of that logic. I mean…you can’t really presuppose content, can you? It being as varied and indiscriminate as circumstance permits.Mww

    I wrote some things below, but my final comment seems the best, so I brought it up to the beginning. One of my favorite questions:

    One last thought: Does General Motors exist? Another odd question, for surely it does and has thousands of employees, and so on. But at one time it did not exist. How is it that something that did not exist come into existence? Simple, GM is a complex pragmatic institution that is foundationally a language entity (perhaps therefore a social entity. Says Rorty, who thinks science is a social entity). I think of how it was in language that GM was conceived. carried out, broadened, incorporated, and all the rest. And I think of all the businesses, and schools, and government functions, and then the essential institution of our cuture, the marriages and funerals, the way we organize our time, our zones of possession, and, well, just everything. And then, the critical insight: Isn't a tree simply an "institution" as well? Prior to language, what "is" it?

    The point is that language has brought upon us a dimension of existence in which meanings synthesize, not just logical abstractions, to generate reality, being. I see a stone, and what makes it a stone is not some prior qualities inherent in the stone, for talk about qualities at all IS a language event.

    I've decided to erase all the rest, so it's gone. This little paragraph above makes the point rather well: Our world is a world of institutions, that is, of instituted knowledge claims, such that what is known is derived from the language/culture matrix in which we are immersed. Rorty said the world is made, not discovered, and this has always stuck with me, because when it comes to saying what the world is, what Being and its beings IS, I find nothing but language. But this doesn't diminish what is discovered at all. What, after all, is language? This, too, is a transcendental question: language interrogating language (as we are doing now) regarding the nature of language. Identity is bound up in language, for the question of who I am itself is born out of language.

    And when there is that loud bang behind me, I am always already, ready to assimilate it into a body of institutions already there. Why that sounds like a someting fell off a truck, or like thunder or an explosion, and so on.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Except Kant’s is a speculative metaphysic, in which the transcendental philosophy constructed to account for it, may not properly account for what is the case. Thus, your notion of extrapolation can only refer to the move from what is the case, not to what must be the case to account for it, but only to a possible accounting. Regardless of how exact and internally consistent his system may be, it may not be what’s actually happening between our ears. He’s very specific in saying, if this way is sufficient then it is so only if it is done right. Hence, if pure reason is the way, then to critique it leads to doing it right.Mww
    What is the case is the synthetic apriority in language relations with the world. Clearly the move from this is not going to be something determinate, and I did say this earlier when I was talking about the conditions of a proper logical deduction. What must be the case is always going to be the unknown X, but the point is that it must be something, and if one must give a reason why there must be something, one does the Critique. Extrapolations do not lead to certainies, only indeterminacies, and this is why I think this term right, because Kant's argument does not give us determinacy, for this is impossible.

    Then what kind of deduction is this? Kant tells us it is a quid juris matter, and this is curious, isn't it? This is a legal term, not a matter of fact (quid facti), but one of right, and so he tells us such cases are never perfectly conceived. I think what he is up to is that in dealing with facts of the world, states of affairs, deduction moves to conclusions in the regular way, and an "empirical deduction" is loosely conceived (as Sherlock Holmes "deduces") and not in terms of the deductive argument contra inductive argument distinction; but in dealing with legal determinations, one is not given merely facts. He says this (A 85), speaking of the way the law faces its uncertainties:

    But there are also usurpatory concepts, such as fortune, fate, which, though allowed to circulate by almost universal indulgence, are yet from time to time challenged by the question: quid juris. This demand for a deduction involves us in considerable perplexity, no clear legal title, sufficient to justify their* employment, being obtainable either from experience or from reason.

    That is a big confession, for legal outcomes are never certain when "fortune and fate" are duly considered; because fortune and fate take the argument into a sea of uncertainty impossible to calculate. Justice is not quid facti, nor is the transcendental deduction. This is the best he can do, analogize the transcendental deduction to dejure legal thinking, and the question of whether the logical move is one of extrapolation then goes to whether such quid juris inquiry is extrapolatory.

    Not sure about that. I'll have to think about it.

    What must be the case is determinable by the physical sciences alone, and he makes it quite clear that metaphysics is not a proper science, nor can it be, from which it follows that metaphysics alone cannot necessarily be the case that accounts for what is.

    Knowing metaphysics is not necessarily right in accounting for what is, all that’s left to us is to make it less wrong.
    Mww

    I would argue against the way you put things. Not that science can ever determine what must be the case, but that science deals through premises that are a posteriori, but the logical structure of the judgments in play are apriori in their form. But then, yes, if things fall with repeatable results to the ground, and not otherwise, then a scientific principle can be conceived, and IN this principle there is acknowledged the category of universality (as opposed to an existential quantifier). The logic, not the science, gives this the "what must be the case" in the apodicticity of the universality of the judgment "All things fall toward and not away".

    Less wrong? But how can one be more or less wrong about something transcendental? One is confined entirely to what is given and this is certainly limiting, for what is, after all, the evidence? It is apodicticity in judgment and experience, the so called apiority in synthetic judgments.

    Rather, consider that what is transcendent is discovered IN what is immanent, and here the language that is deployed attempts to step where it has no place.

    So it is the language that sets up Kant's thinking, and this is the language of finitude. The term transcendental is borrowed entirely from mundane thinking, or is it? This, to me, is the fascinating question. Take the "evidence" for the deduction, the structural logical properties of language. One can at best say that this is in the simple giveness of the world, but then, and this is the important part of this, everything is simply given. Kant's move is a metaphysical move, yet the metaphysics that inspires it issues not from some impossible to conceive transcendental foundation for reason, but rather from the transcendence that permeates, if you will, the entire horizon of the world's givenness. To see where Kant ends and the full analysis begins, see Heidegger, then the post Heideggerians, then the post post Heideggerians.

    If one takes the idea of transcendental idealism seriously, one will have to eventually drop the rationalistic reduction, and acknowledge that philosophy must perform a reduction on the entirely of our existence. Husserl begins this, Heidegger continues this with, if you will, the first radical exposition of the human soul (dasein. Soul is my choice of words, but this is just because Kant and early Heidegger's attempt to finitize what we and the world are--notwithstanding the transcendental deduction abstract attempt to go beyond this---are a failure). Radical because we have left the Kantian abstract reduction and stepped into the reality before our waking eyes. You do not stand before a foundational logical anomaly (Kant); you ARE a foundational "anomaly" (though, this opens up other matters, like the what makes something an anomaly).

    Technically, what is irrevocably the case, is Nature. What must be the case to account for Nature, is guesswork originated by our intellect, and that conditioned by time and circumstance. Thus, what must be the case, is in fact quite contingent, the more parsimonious way to account for our intellectual errors.

    If the perspective is limited to the human himself, Nature being given, what is irrevocably the case is nothing more than sensation, insofar as that is the point at which the internal mechanisms of human intellect….of whatever form that may be….become first apparent.

    If you’re referring to aesthetic judgement as what is the case, as opposed to discursive judgement of the understanding, then we’re talking of two different conditions. But in relation to what is, aesthetic judgement respects only how we feel about it, rather than how we account for it.
    Mww

    But Kant's analysis of nature is merely an analysis of logic. Calling the world "sensible intuition" is just dismissive. And the logicality of language is an abstraction; an abstraction from the totality of engagement. The full transcendental dimension of our being-in-the-world is untouched. To say "only how we feel about it" is simply to ignore it. Consider that this feeling is the very basis of, as Von Hildebrandt put it, importance. Wittgenstein refused to talk about value, feeling, aesthetics, not because, as the postivists held, there was nothing there, but because it was too important to allow philosophy to undermine and trivialize it. Wittgenstein was right AND wrong.

    Gettin’ pretty far into the weeds here, so “loosely put” is quite apropos. Those judgements structured by pure reason are principles, therefore called apodeitic or necessary, which serve as rules for the function of understanding in its empirical employment. The structure of judgements in general, called either problematic or assertorical, merely represents the unity between the conceptions in the subject to the predicate of any cognition, a function belonging to understanding alone. Whether or not this conception belongs to that conception, hence the truth or falsity of the cognition relative to those empirical conditions from which they arise, re: phenomena, THAT is the purview of reason.

    When I think, and my thoughts succeed each other without conflict, my judgements are rational and/or logical. If I think, and then I have to think again or think otherwise, in which case there is a conflict in my judgements, it is reason’s judging that informs of the conflict, either regarding my understanding with itself, or my understanding with experience. Not what such conflict is, how it has manifested itself, but that there is one. Hence the transcendental nature of those judgements structured by pure reason as principles, that by which those discursive judgements is informed of its errors.
    Mww

    I have no issues with this, I don't think. I mean, sure, this is the kind of thing Kant is saying. It is just that the weeds are off and away from this. Kant's is a well trimmed lawn with pink flamingoes facsimiles and Snow White dwarf facsimiles here and there.

    If it is the case all things are first evidenced by their effect on the senses, where does judgement appear? Do we really need to judge whether or not our senses have been affected? That they are or that they are not, to be considered as judgements as such? If such is the criteria for the structure of judgements in general, on order for them to appear, what is to be done with the relation between a phenomenon and the conceptions by which it is cognized? And if such is the case, what does pure reason have to do with it?

    It is the case, however, that judgement does appear by the cognition that the “world” is that in which all possible things are first evidenced, but that merely treats “world” as a general condition for things for which evidence is possible. In other words, “world” is the predicate of a principle given a priori in transcendental logic. There remains the need for the intuition of that space in which a thing is first evidenced, and a time by which that thing relates to a perception of it, in neither of which does a judgement manifest itself.
    (Sidebar: here, “world”, in Kant, is “reality”) For whatever that’s worth…..
    Mww

    Go with, the world is that in which all things are evidenced, and leave it at that. The predicate you have in mind would be, For every possible X, if X IS, then X is in and of a world. Something like that. Of course, the burden the is upon the verb 'to be' and this is where works like "Being and Time" come in. That copula 'is' is what needs to be examined.

    No manifestation of discursive judgement in phenomena, but there is imagination, every bit as facilitating as judgement, for a priori argument. As I mentioned above, aesthetic judgement is manifest in the subject as his underlying condition, or, which is the same thing, how he feels about what he perceives. But that relates more to what he feels ought to be, rather than what is.Mww

    Then the feeling about what she ought to be has status as a phenomenon. Depends on who you read, but I see nothing to stop imagination to have equal ontological standing to this lamp on the table. Both are interpretatively grounded and both appear before me. Of course, these are classified "ontically" (in the usual ways) differently, but so is everything.

    The question about affectivity, the "pathos" of our existence, is one that, like Kant's pure reason, begs for a transcendental accounting. But where Kant seeks the ground for an abstraction, inquiry into this "existence" begins with something palpable and inherently important. For example, a spear to the kidney. Now, do an transcendental deduction on THAT. No, I mean literally, do a Kantian styled deduction, keeping certain things keenly in mind: The pain, like the formal dimensions of experience, is a given, and as such has its transcendental ground outside of the interpretative possibilities of the finite totality of what is known. But what is transcendental here is not the impossible abstraction of pure reason, but the existential reality of the "pure" affectivity. What is meant by "pure" affectivity (the word taken here to encompass the ethical/aesthetic dimension of our world).

    LIke Kant, we reduce experience by freeing it of all incidentals, the quid facti states of affairs, so that the essential nature can be revealed. This is an inquiry into the bonum and the malum, and is the most salient feature of our existence being carried to its foundation. The deduction is, of course, to a purity that is, granted, abstracted from ordinary matters, but what is left after the reduction is very different from conceptual form as such. We have touched upon, as Michel Henry puts it, life.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Science needs aesthetics and aesthetics needs science. The tension between art and science may be traced back to the Greeks, to the ancient conflict of Apollo and Dionysus, between order, reason, and logic and chaos, emotion, and ecstasy. There is the sublime in both the aesthetic and the scientific, in both its theory and practice. The aesthetics of science is the study of beauty and matters of taste within the scientific endeavour. Aesthetic features like simplicity, elegance and symmetry are sources of wonder and awe for many scientists, thus motivating scientific pursuit. Both use representation and the role of values. Both combine the subjective with the objective, imagination with creativity, the inspirational and the pragmatic. In e = mc 2 is an aesthetic beauty.RussellA

    Quite a thing to say, and I wonder if Nietzsche would agree, being so close to his Birth of Tragedy. But keep in mind that science has no interest in the aesthetic features of science any more than knitting qua knitting has interest in the joy of knitting. Sure, scientists are fascinated, engaged, in awe, and the rest, but as a body of inquiry and the things it deals with, it does not and cannot touch the aesthetic or the ethical, and this is because what these essentially are cannot be empirically determined.

    Arguing that science is essentially aesthetic is a defensible position, I believe. Rorty thinks like this and Dewey thinks like this, and the sense of it lies in the pragmatic reduction of all of our affairs to experience and its structure, a reduction that takes analysis beneath everyday categories to the
    "essential" existential features, and here we find cognition, affectivity, anticipation, regret, resolution, and on and on possessed in the singularity of a conscious act. But, of course, these are philosophers, not scientists, who think like this.

    But where you talk about continental philosophy, this I understand to be where your interests lie, no? You see in this thread I am arguing with Mww about Kant. Right, of course, to say phenomenology begins with Kant (but then, Kant begins with Aristotle, and Hume, and so on), but I am arguing that Kant is kind of like Hobbes, who wrote the Leviathan as a treatise on legitimate sovereignty: Nobody thinks like Hobbes now (well, Trump, maybe??), but he opened a door wide in the response to what he said, and in that, he is great because he started talk about contract theory. Kant was a rationalist, but reason, Hume said, cares nothing for human existence, for reason does "care" at all.

    The nature of ethics/aesthetics is the most important philosophical issue there is. As Von Hildebrandt put it, it is the nature "importance" itself that is first philosophy. To understand ethics, one has to to phenomenology.

    I'll stop here, but any thoughts you may have here or elsewhere are welcome.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    That’s in fact all understanding is about. It is the analysis of all that contained in the primitive representation “I think”.

    “…. And thus the synthetical unity of apperception is the highest point with which we must connect every operation of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and after it our transcendental philosophy; indeed, this faculty is the understanding itself.…”

    Thus it is that the function of understanding is distinct from that to which it directs itself when it thinks, or, when the subject exercises his innate capacity for thinking. To understand, on the other hand, presupposes the completion of that analysis, the affirmation or negation of constructed judgements relative to empirical conditions, not yet verified by experience.

    All without a single solitary word, either expressed, or merely thought.
    Mww

    You had written:
    So that which is not understood never appears? Guy’s walking down the street, hears a loud bang from around the corner. An appearance to his ears, manifesting as a sensation of sound is immediately given, without him immediately understanding the cause of it.

    The issue was whether or not the understanding attends spontaneous events like hearing a loud bang. I said it did, for hearing at all, for us, is a structured affair, that is, when we "experience" anything at all, there is the implicit understanding thta this fits into a familiar course of events, and is not alien or threatening. The TUA is a temporal architectonics, so the recollections of prior loud bang experiences and the like are foundationally apriori, even if judgment is not explicitly brought to bear on what is occurring. This was the point. You were saying the loud bang was received without understanding, while I was saying the understanding is always already attendant, if implicitly.

    And I reject that criticism, in that the thinking in CPR resolves the illusion of conceiving the world in any way except as the form of all that is relatable to it, hence hardly meaningless. We perceive things in a world; we don’t perceive worlds. From which follows world is conceivable only as the form of that in which all things are contained, but is not itself contained by it.Mww

    That is actually an interesting thing to say. What do you mean by "We perceive things in a world; we don't perceive worlds"?

    He ignores it in CPR because the analysis of who or what we are is properly the concern of his moral philosophy, which is not transcendental.Mww

    It is a moral philosophy that doesn't understand the nature of ethics. Kant is metaethically out to lunch by conceiving a "good will" to be aligned with reason alone. It is, frankly, devoid of meaningful talk about the foundation of moral obligation.

    The name given to it presupposes the grasp of the conception to which the name relates. It’s occurence in thought, its conceivability, is explicitly the very purity by which the language describing it, is even possible. Language doesn’t grasp, it merely represents what’s already been grasped.

    The purity of language is in thought; the purity of thought is in logic; the purity of logic is in pure reason; the purity of pure reason is the irreducible human condition.
    Mww

    But there is no purity in thought; purity is never witnessed. It is transcendental, and can only be inferred, and inferences require meanings on both sides of the inference to make sense. One cannot say that X represents Y if Y is absent altogether. Thus, all representation does is place a division between what is "present" and what is not. But it is nonsense to do this, for a division requires both sides to be intelligible.

    Calling it "pure reason" is nonsense unless one can identify what this purity is outside of language.
    And this not to say the term transcendental is nonsense. Understanding why this is is a great insight into what it is to be a human (to be a "dasein"). Kant had it right in that metaphysics had to go, but wrong to argue for a rationalistic transcendentalism. Reason "cares" nothing for anything, and to ground our practical matters on this can only come from a the mind of of an anal retentive logician like Kant (who, ironically, is labeled a mere fantasist by another anal retentive logician, Bertrand Russell. Go figure).
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?


    I said Dennett really DOES understand the world. I meant to say, that he does NOT. That this is what happens when all eyes are on how well one constructs an argument.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    CPR doesn’t treat of empirical ontology; it is a purely epistemological thesis, from a metaphysical perspective.Mww

    NO. Ontology and epistemology are two sides to the same existence. Causality, e.g., IS IN the existence of this desk in the logic of sensory intuitions being blind by themselves. What you acknowledge to BE a lamp is a synthesis.

    What…..not a fan of freedom as sufficient cause?Mww

    You would have to explain your thinking here.

    91 pages on sensibility, just under 400 pages on logic, all integral to the human condition. Fine if you wish to deny we are agents of logic, but I’m happily convinced human agency is necessarily predicated on it.Mww

    And what do you think Kant is saying about human agency?

    Nope. Extrapolation from what is the case for us, to how the case is to be known by us. We understand the world; we explain the understanding. Language for the second, not for the first.Mww

    Extrapolation is the move from what IS the case to what must be the case to account for this. What is the case is is judgment. What must be the case given the way judgment is structured is pure reason, loosely put. This is basic. Logic is apriori, and Kant's arguments are apriori. But all things are first evidenced in the "world" and and here is where judgments appear. No manifestation in phenomena, then no ground for apriori argument.


    Nope. What he means by “first” here, is merely that occassion given to a theoretical systemic procedure. There happens to be a particular theoretical system which presupposes a priori conditions, turning sensation into representation according to pure intuitions and productive imagination.Mww

    I wrote this: ""So when Kant says something like, "What must first be given with a view to the a priori knowledge of all objects is the manifold of pure intuition," this sentential construction is itself bound to the categories."

    Obviously this is true since all sentential constructions are so bound. "First" here refers to what is logically first, or presupposed, as when reading this sentence there is a logical structure presupposed in the understanding of its meaning. Logical presupposedness is what the Critique is all about, this digging deep into what must be the case IN the presuppositional underpinning of everyday speaking.

    When I write and think, about my notice of the world. While it may that the categories are always involved when I write, it being a phenomenal exercise, it is not the case for when I think, for it is possible that I think in pure a priori terms, that is, non-empirical, for which the categories are not involved. The logic of my a priori judgements still requires affirmation, at least to be productive, but there is no occassion to seize upon intuition.Mww

    How does the thought you may have about logic, or better, when, say, when you are actually doing symbolic logic, escape the very rigor that is at work in your thinking? How can any thought at all be outside of logicality?

    I need not go beyond relations in time, to discover what is necessary for something to be possible, as I already mentioned. For something to be possible at all its representation must be determinable in any time. Necessity: determinable in all time; existence: determinable in a time.Mww

    There is no issue here. The reference is to what is logically possible. Simply that. It is logically not possible for an object to be two different colors at once or for an object to be at two different velocities at once.

    Agreed, which justifies the claim there is no language in pure thought.Mww

    No language in pure thought? But what is Kant "talking" about? "Pure thought" is simply a language construct that Kant uses to talk "about" things that cannot be talked about. Clearly, one has to "talk" to conceive of pure thought at all, so the issue arises: Can one meaningfully talk about something that stands outside of talk? and it is Kant's own transcendental Dialectic that weighs down on this. In the end, he is just as bad as Descartes.

    Correct, from which follows the rules for speaking are very far from the rules for transcendental deduction.Mww

    I don't see any sense in this at all. The rules are rigorous everywhere. They do not vary. I say, If you go out today, you should bring an umbrella, this has the logically essential structure of a conditional proposition. In everyday talk, of course, it is entangled in many affairs, but the logic is unwavering, and can be reduced to its basic structure in symbolic and then, predicate logic. It is IN tthe rules for speaking that logic is discovered in the first place.

    Wait…..so all you’re talking about is justifying the origin of the categories, while I’m talking about justifying the use of them? What is necessary for the possibility of things makes little sense to me, but what is the ground for the possibility of transcendental deduction of the categories, is a whole ‘nuther ball of wax.

    Dunno where your quote comes from, but in A88/B120 in Kemp Smith is shown that is precisely how the deduction is NOT served.

    “…. they make affirmations concerning objects not by means of the predicates of intuition and sensibility, but of pure thought à priori….”.

    Your a priori conditions upon which the possibility of experience rests”, are precisely those very intuitions my quote denotes as “not by means of”.
    Mww

    The categories have no use. They are theoretical postulates. No one can ever "see" such a thing, nor use it. The evidential basis for any discussion about it lies in exclusively in language and its logical features (which is, well, the absolute WORST kind of question begging, as these features which are being talked about are IN the structure of talking itself, and are assumed to be what they "are". Of course, he understood this; see the quote below. But in declaring an end to metaphysics, one has to draw a line, and he drew one, and this is impossible! He does this grudgingly! This is why Wittgenstein had to refer to it as nonsense, even as he talked about it, saying essentially, in the Tractatus, "what I am saying is nonsense."

    Here is a quote from A 96, a good one:

    Pure a priori concepts, if such exist, cannot indeed contain anything empirical; yet, none the less, they can serve solely as a priori conditions of a possible experience. Upon this ground alone can their objective reality rest. If, therefore, we seek to discover how pure concepts of understanding are possible, we must enquire what are the a priori conditions upon which the possibility of experience A 96
    rests, and which remain as its underlying grounds when everything empirical is abstracted from appearances.


    See, this is the way He says it, not me. "If such exist" is very important, for it is experience and its qpriori structure that warrants the Critique. The pure concepts are an abstraction, a mere postulation, noumenal and remote.

    "Not be means of" is a quibble based on misunderstanding only.

    Nope. This is the nature of a transcendental argument, which is a priori. But not all a priori arguments are transcendental, re: those of understanding in its categorical judgements. Transcendental arguments originate in, and are the exclusive purview of, pure reason alone.Mww

    Extrapolation is the logical move from what is taken as an assumption to what this presupposes. This is what "Upon this ground alone can their objective reality rest," in the above is saying. "This ground alone" refers to experience and the logical structure exhibited in judgment. A transcendental argument is nothing but extrapolation--one begins with what is there, and one infers from t his to what must be the case. All extrapolation is essentially logical, an inference from what is known to what is not known.

    But this is the tricky part, isn't it: A deductive argument that is not like modus ponens, where the conclusion is discovered in the premises. Rather, here, in this transcendental argument, the conclusion is impossible to conceive! And so the conclusion is clearly NOT exhaustively possessed in the premises, or even possessed at all in them. So can it be properly called a deduction at all? Well, it can if you call it a transcendental deduction, but then, the issue turns to the premises and the warrant. SINCE the conclusion is indeterminate, the logic of the Critique is one from the known to an indeterminacy, not a determinacy, and so while it is an apriori argument, the conclusion is extrapolated from the premises, not deduced from this.

    A good question, though: Is Kant's great Deduction, really a deduction at all? Of course, later, it will be put argued that deductions never were deductions in this pure sense because conclusions are never purely deduced as all premises themselves rest on the indeterminacies of language meaning. All bachelors are unmarried cannot be conceived as analytic because the ideas themselves are filled with different senses (Quine. See that argument in The Two Dogmas).
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    I cannot really respond as I have limited knowledge of Husserl, Heidegger and Existentialism in general.

    However, in my agreement with Linguistic Idealism, I have sympathy with the notion in Husserl's Being and Time that the human is not a subjective spectator of objects, but rather that subject and object are inseparable. In my case, linked within language.

    I don't know the background to Existentialism, have not read Kierkegaard and have only limited exposure to Nietzsche. However, I naturally agree with any critique of rationalism, and am supportive of their interest in the problem of meaning.

    I have spent more time on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, respecting his attempt to understand the limits and scope of metaphysics, as well as investigating how reason may be used to gain knowledge about the world.

    As regards Husserl's Logical Investigations, for me there is promise in Brentano's concept of Intentionality and the problem of intentional inexistence, the investigation of the relation between the act of consciousness and the phenomena at which it is directed. I tend more to agree more with the "bracketing" of assumptions about the existence of an external world than the Direct Realist who believes that they directly know the external world.

    Continental philosophy opens up a whole new field of understanding.
    RussellA

    Well, you sound like someone who just might do the work required to understand these people. So often the initial interest is killed by the alien nature of what is being said and the hard work of assimilating the ideas and the jargon. Those who want to think as if nothing really important is going on in philosophy head towards anglo american philosophy which tries to reduce its thematic possiblities to ordinary talk, which is why they rely on science for their bottom line, and this way is nothing but disaster at the level of basic questions. When you try to simply eliminate metaphysics in the willful act of ignoring it, you end up with the trivial tail end of science. And really much worse: Science, as a philosophical ontology/epistemology goes absolutely nowhere, quite literally. And science doesn't even begin, again, literally, to talk about the most salient feature of your existence, ethics/aesthetics.

    Two kinds of philosophers, the anglo american analytic above, and the continental. This latter is usually ignored by the former, certainly due in part to the reluctance to learn any German, French or Greek, in part. A competent paper in Heidegger has to deal, at least in part, with the way German handles ideas because Heidegger is making a bold move to use language in a way that defies tradition, and he does this by endless neologizing The German. He wants to eradicate metaphysics, just as the analytics do, but then, Heidegger, and this is one thing that makes him a deeply profound thinker, recasts metaphysics in finitude! He is just extraordinary, for he realizes that metaphysics is grounded in the essential givenness of the world, and that Kant was right: Philosophy must be rid of centuries of bad Christian metaphysics; THOUGH, I would add, after Heidegger, there is a group of neoHusserlians in post-post modern French theology that take Heidegger;s "exposition of the human soul" if you will, into a finitude that is subsumed by infinity! See Emanuel Levinas, Michel Henry, Jean Luc Marion, et al. Heidegger is huge door that opens up into extraordinary insight. There are also a slew of Catholic Heideggerian, rather than Thomist, as they have always been, theologists like Von Hildebrandt, Karl Rahner, who explain Christian metaphysics through Being and Time's basic thinking.

    Anyway, so good to hear that someone wants to do this "authentic" work in philosophy, rather than the pointless Anglo american thinking. Not that it is a completely worthless. Quine is helpful for balance, and even someone like Daniel Dennett can be helpful, showing what really rigorous thinking comes to when science rules basic ideas. But then, he REALLY does understanding the world at all. And he's not trying to. He just wants arguments to work, and this I define as the basic drive on that sid e of philosophy. They just look at arguments and construct truth table style coherence. Such thinking about truth is propositional and logical, which is fine. But contrast this to Heidegger's alethea! This is the world! This is our existence!
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    I can understand Phenomenology as part of a personal philosophy, but it seems limited if it made up the whole of a personal philosophy.

    Phenomenology rejects rationalism and empiricism in favour of a person's "lived experience", relying on an intuitive grasp of knowledge free from any philosophical intellectualising.

    For example, in Bracketing, one withholds any conscious opinion of what is perceived, taking no position as to the reality of what is seen, but simply to witness it as it presents itself.

    I agree that Phenomenology can be insightful in our understanding about the relation of the mind to the sensations it experiences, but it seems insufficient not to question these sensations and only witness them.

    Philosophy must surely be about questioning, not simply about phenomenologically accepting.
    RussellA

    You are asking a question that is taken up as a major theme in Heidegger. What the nature of questioning? But also, your thoughts on the exclusivity of the "lived experience" need to be addressed, and obviously I can't convince you that reading Heidegger's Being and TIme would be the most important philosophical experience of your life just by saying so. And the arguments are just so involved.

    So all I can really do is mention why it is important.

    Too much to say, but at the basic level one thing stands head and shoulders above others: all that one ever has observed, or can observe, is phenomena. Kant's thing-in-itself is derivative of phenomena, so whatever Kant hd in mind with thing-in-itself had to have been derivative of what is, simply put, there, in what is given. When one discovers apriority in necessity, from whence comes this? and the transcendental ground itself, and this is very important as I see it, this ground itself and the term 'transcendental" must be discoverable in the structure of what is given, and the idea of the beyond, the metaphysical, this, too, is IN the immanent. The only conclusion: immanence IS transcendental. So when I look at my wife, and see her there, she is BOTH there in all the usual ways, AND she is utterly transcendental, for the language that is IN my understanding of her being who she is in foundationally indeterminate.

    There is no line drawn anywhere except that line which is conceived in the liberties of language's openness. Language can conceive of a great deal of things, pragmatic and useful, cultural and institutional (weddings, funerals, e.g., are institutions of culture), theoretical, and so on, so put this all down (see Husserl's epoche) and allow the world to declare itself in a kind of Yielding (gelasenheit. See Heidegger's Conversation on a Country Path about Thinking in his Discourse of Thinking) or listening or meditative thnking. Only here can one discover what all the fuss is about. One has to suspend or "bracket" all that makes the world familiar, in order to "see" this hidden world that is entirely "other" than what familiarity says it is.

    Takes practice. The phenomenological reduction (epoche) is a "method" of discovery, not merely a theory. It will not fit into science. Science "fits into" the reduction, so to speak, for the reduction is foundational. For Heidegger this means equiprimordial, meaning there is only the frontier of language's openness. From here is gets complicated. See, e.g., What is Metaphysics?
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    That phenomena must meet the criteria of the categories doesn’t exhaust understanding, it enables the manifold of conceptions understanding possesses to be synthesized in the construction of a judgement on the one hand, or, enables an appeal to experience in the case of repetitive perception on the other.

    In order for the affect of the thing on the senses, and the representation of that thing as it is understood, be sufficiently congruent to be knowledge of the thing, there must be rules by which one relates to the other, and, that by which the conceptions annexed to the phenomenon relate to each other. Something must have already prohibited the conception “round” from being imagined as belonging to the conception “tall”, when the thing perceived ended up being cognized initially, or remembered as post hoc experience, as a dinner plate.
    —————-
    Mww

    The point is more simple. We know how this goes. It's just that when one pulls back and realizes where Kant's ontology takes one, it is realized that the entire enterprise is an abstraction of our existence and the world, not something that is even looking for apodicticity in existence. Kant's greatness lies in attention to ordinary judgment in common experience, not in far flung metaphysics. But his conclusion are literally vacuous. Of course, he also didnt realize the nature of language in which this formal analysis is finds its theme, logic.

    If you and I were principally agencies of logic, synthesizing and analyzing the data afforded by the senses, then Kant would have nailed the human condition. But such an idea is absurd.

    The pure conceptions of the understanding are transcendental deductions of reason. Understanding uses them, but they are not given from understanding itself. These in opposition to conceptions arising spontaneously within understanding itself, in response to the influx of intuited representations. Pure conceptions condition sensibility, empirical conceptions condition thinking.Mww

    You mean they are deduced, not that they are deductions. Understanding doesn't "use" them. They are of the structure of the understanding itself. I don't know what you're talking about here.

    Kant wouldn’t say something like that, for knowledge of all objects is always empirical, and what must first be given is the object itself, insofar as it appears to sensibility. That which is representation must first be perception.Mww

    What he means by "first" is presupposed by the possibility of aprioity. There must be a manifold of pure intuition to account for the structure of knowledge of objects. Kant's is an extrapolation from what is the case, to what has to be the case to explain this. The manifold must be the case given the way ordinary judgments are put together. This is fundamental to the whole Critique.

    It's a quote.

    As for the sentential construction being bound to the categories, considering this proposition is a tenet in speculative metaphysics, for which there is no empirical proofs for its objects derived from experience, the categories are not involved, from which follows the construct is not bound by them. Every object of theoretical speculation is transcendental; there are no faculties of human intelligence in concreto.Mww

    The categories are ALWAYS involved. As I write and think. There is no escaping categorical placement. If this isn't making sense, just consider what symbolic logic is. There is NO proposition that escapes logical form. When you awaken, notice a world around you, you are already "in" Kantian categories as the logic of affirmations seize upon intuitions.

    No faculties in concreto? What does this even begin to mean in Kantian thinking?

    What is IN phenomenological possibility? I don’t recognize phenomenological possibility, and I certainly have no idea what is IN possibilities. Nothing is IN a possibility, it is never schema but has schemata under it, re: the schema of possibility is determination of a representation in any time. Common-speak being…that thing that doesn’t appear to me is no possible experience for me.Mww

    No, possiblility here refers to what is necessary for something to be possible at all.

    In things that are possible is not the same as what is in possibilities. I mean….what sense does it make to ask if a thing has possibility, when all we want to know is if the thing is possible. The former presupposes the thing being asked about, which proves it must be a possible thing.Mww

    The matter goes to what must be the case for something that is there before you to be what it is. If I have judgments that are, say, negations, and there is nothing in empirical perceptions explains what a negation is, then I have appeal the form itself, and an explanation for this lies in the nature of the possiblity of logicality, and this lies in out of transcendentally out of reach.


    Which reduces the whole mess to the notion that categories can never be predicates, but only subjects, in logical propositional constructs, and as such, derivatives of what is IN possibilities becomes unintelligible.Mww

    This is not about that. The discussion here is about deriving the categories in the first place, that is, the ground for their postulation. But on the other hand, keep in mind that when we talk about a category, this itself will be done ALSO within the presuppositional ground of speaking at all, and then, when language deals with these presuppositions, the categories' own structures are necessarily in place. Categories "themselves" are transcendental, and cannot be spoken, so when they are spoken "about", the speaking is subject to their own manifest rules.

    Possibilities here should be understood in light of statements like this: "If, therefore, we seek to discover how pure concepts of understanding are possible, we must enquire what are the a priori conditions upon which the possibility of experience rests"--- from what is given to what must be the case to make this possible. This is the nature of an apriori argument. The whole argument of the deduction in an extrapolation.

    If that’s the case, his successors treat it as the proverbial red-headed stepchild, to which Kant would have vehemently objected. Ripped the concept of phenomena right outta its old-fashioned sandbox, consigned it to a post-modern tarpit.Mww

    Would Kant have approved of Husserl or Heidegger; or Kierkegaard? Of course not. But such things never occurred to him. I can't imagine what he would think reading Derrida. He would have to rad Heidegger, first. It would take a radical leap of philosophical imagination. But so what. Kant laid the foundation for just this kind of development. No Kant, no phenomenology. Therein lies his greatness. Not in the sustainability of all he said.

    Tarpit is puzzling. Who do you have in mind, and what is calling this a tarpit about? Or perhaps you're just throwing out frustrations with difficult reading. I find this usually to be the case.

    So that which is not understood never appears? Guy’s walking down the street, hears a loud bang from around the corner. An appearance to his ears, manifesting as a sensation of sound is immediately given, without him immediately understanding the cause of it.Mww

    This sounds naive. Understanding is not about explicit analysis. Read Husserl for this, his Ideas I, but this doesn't mean he is right an all accounts, but here, given that we are agenies of language awareness, there is this awareness implicit in the conscious events of our lives, even in the most immediate ones. So when the loud bang is heard, the familiarity of loud bangs makes the alarming matter meaningful, not alien to the understanding. And while one could say the same for cows and goats regarding the pre established familiarity, it is us whose pragmatic affairs are grasped in language and its logic, and thus, Kantian categories are 'in" the recognition.

    If a newly born were to hear the loud noise, she would clearly react, register the event, but it would not be a loud noise. It would not BE anything. It would be, as Kant would put it, blind intuition, and this, it must be stated with emphasis, is not thinkable. It is transcendental.

    This is not Kant talking here. Note how I have here and there criticized the thinking in the Critique for conceiving the world in a vacuum of meaningless form, I do this because the true philosophical ground for the ansalysis of what and who we are lies in this dimension of our transcendence, which he mostly ignores. Granted, it is a critique of logical purity he aims for, but then, this is my point. A person is not, clearly, reducible to what the Critique has to say. But Kant opens the door for just this discussion.

    Something does not appear iff there is no effect on the senses. If there is an effect, if the senses are affected, there is necessarily an appearance. Full stop. There is no cognitive power in mere perception, therefore any cognitive function is irrelevant with respect to it. On the other hand, something does not become cognized until it is understood.Mww

    But note that when you say "iff there is no eeffect on the senses" you are saying this, and in this you comply with Kant's own insistence on stepping out of mere "blindness". Without language context, for us, that is, and not the animal, it is not as if there is nothing there, but it makes no appearance AS something. Even if you speak of a "pure phenomenon" this never occurs to us outside of, if you will, the purity of the language that grasps it, implicitly of otherwise. What this means is hard to say ourside of the literature.

    What you specify as a “trick” of philosophy, is nothing but some arbitrary, indiscriminate iteration of human intelligence bringing itself to the fore. Different human, different iteration, different form of the same intelligence. Another one might say the duty of philosophy is to discover apodeitically that by which such intelligence manifests, but for which language has no relevance except for expressions of such discoveries.Mww

    Or the beat actually pauses where things are getting close. Where can one settle doubt? Forget the categories as some impossible things in themselves. This is metaphysics, or, misleading metaphysics or metaphysics that draws a hard line, and such lines can never be drawn in any meaningful way because, as Wittgenstein put it, that would require an understanding of what is on both sides of the line, and clearly, the categories cannot be understood.

    Lety's say Kant was right, and the magic of metaphysics lies with apodicticity. so when we witness a stone, and realize the stone cannot move by itself by necessity, it is the necessity that grounds causality in the truly Real, why? Because necessity by definition cannot be gainsaid. But then,we know that it CAN be gainsaid. Logic can be gainsaid? Of course, since logic is given to us in language, and language is historically conceived, so even when on calls something apodictic, it is a calling, a taking something "as" something in language, and this brings the contingency of language down upon what is said. Sure, I can't imagine a thing self moving, but what this IS in itself is utterly transcendental, yes, even calling it transcendental is bound to this contingency. This is roughly Derrida.

    So talk about how intelligence manifests presupposes the language that speaks about intelligence. This does what Kant does, takes thought to its own presuppositions, but makes the important steps forward. The "trick" is to see that when Language takes one to this final confrontation, the matter of language encountering language, as when one says, "what am I?" (see, for a more dramatic unfolding of this, Beckett's Molloy or Blancho's Thomas the Obscure), it finds liberation from, not Kant's categories, but from the illusory assumption that this bottom itself IS a language construction. Language "brings" one to the world, the radical "other" of a world.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    How do we have knowledge?  I feel idealism and materialism and realism all have their points.  But they all seem to have limitations too.  Phenomenology seems interesting, but it too, seems to be only emphasising on the experience side of perception and knowledge, while mentioning the significance of body, consciousness and intentionality, they don't seem to go deeper into those areas.  I could be wrong here. I must admit I hadn't read a lot on phenomenology, and my idea on it is purely from guessing.Corvus

    How about liberating inquiry from a lot of bad thinking that manufactures problems? Phenomenology is not subjective; it is talked about like that because phenomenology allows for these "subjective" matters to be taken up philosophically rather than being dismissed as irrelevant. And so when Heidegger talks about moods (attunements), he is simply allowing for the event of a perception to be what it is rather than dismissing the perceptual end of this entirely. Imagine thinking of a perceptual event excluding perception altogether! When one encounters something, someone, there is IN the interface an interest, a caring, and the like, and in the encounter, there is recollection and anticipation, and predelineated ideas in place, and certainly not simpy an acknowledgement of what is there as a "stand alone" entity. Why does phenomenology talk about such things? Because this is what constitutes an encounter with the world. Talk about what is outside of this is just bad metaphysics.

    Look at it like Rorty does, from a naturalist's pov (keeping in mind he is only a naturalist because he thinks this is the only wheel that rolls and not because he abides by the naturalist's metaphysics): I am here, and in this being here I have these events, and across the street there are things that are just what they are. All that is out there, those things, people, appear here, in this entity I call me and they never enter my locality any more than the street lamp enters the fire hydrant. That's physicalism, yes? And just as the reflection of the hydrant may appear on a sunny day in the metallic surface of the lamp's steel body, but the lamp itself not move an inch, these things I see never enter me, but I "see" them in me as physical aspects of my own existence, but this seeing is not representational, because to have representation you have to have some clear idea about what is being represented apart from the represntation and this is never forthcoming. One can't have a representation of Y in representation X, if one never encounters Y at all. This seeing, thatis IN this physicalist account, in a human brain is absolutely most emphatically nothing at all even remotely like the lamp, and this makes talk about the lamp outside of this physical feature of myself of my own existence impossible! Rorty is stubborn on this point, and there is a feud between Rorty and Putnam such that the latter mocks Rorty for saying he never actually encounters his own wife! Putnam's position is crystal clear, but is it stronger that Rorty's? I mean, how do even begin to deny that his wife is there? But Rorty's pragmatism just calls it like it is: brain events are not lamps, clouds or other people.

    This is where talk about physicalism, naturalism gets one, in an impossible epistemology. What happens in phenomenology is that this epistemic distance has no status, because the lamp post, the fir hydrant, are there, just as they appear to be, and the approach to acknwowledging their existence (their being "really there") never goes beyond this. Things we observe are not actually something else being represented; rather, they are what they are.

    One has never witnessed anything that is not a phenomenon.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    As regards thought, the phenomenological approach makes sense. In part by removing the Cartesian separation between the mind and the mind-independent and in part by removing the problem of the unknowable thing-in-itself. Phenomenology attempts to create the conditions for the objective study of what is usually regarded as subjective, our judgements, perceptions and emotions of our conscious experienced sensations. Phenomenology rejects both Rationalism and Empiricism in favour of the person's lived experiences.RussellA

    Sorry to be a noodge, but not subjective. Continental philosophy doesn't really take up issues in terms of subjective vs objective (though these terms will show up), realism, direct of otherwise, nor is idealism a term used, because terms like this set up a structure of inquiry that is misleading and lacking what is needed for purging from philosophy a lot of bad metaphysics that makes philosophy so resistant to understanding. What is real? is going to be determined in primordiality of the world, what is "there," and a term like realism and its variations, uses as its basic assumption something that is prior to this givenness, an assumption going into first thoughts about what is to be achieved, a kind of assumed Archimedean place where thought first digs in and wields in arguments, then ends up struggling in essentially the same old ways simply because basic thinking is so stubborn. One cannot start with a concept like realism because the sense of the term has yet to be established. I underline this because it is central to the phenomenological approach. All there is, is what is given, and the real is to be determined only from this. Putting it bluntly, idealism, saying all there is is idea, plays against realism, saying all there is is something independent of idea, is a dichotomy that creates two polar opposites that cannot be reconciled, and as long as one thinks like this, one is bound to some sort of compromise, some "in between" thinking that tries to explain things, again, all along knowing full well that this cannot happen, not really, with these concepts foundationally in place.

    Phenomenology really can't be put in this context of thought, but it generally is for a pretty simple reason: most of what people read over here is anglo american analytic philosophy, typically grounded in some form of naturalism and science that makes the stage for thoughtful events. And phenomenology is SO alien these this assumption, and, of course, difficult to penetrate due to this.

    Reading Being and Time is a revolution, turns familiar thinking up side down and if one has a real desire to understand the world, and not just arguments (analytic thought is like this, a reduction of philososphy to language games, which is what you get when you put the fate of philosophy in the hands of a logician like Bertrand Russell. Of course, Kant was a logician, too, and the former thought the latter fantasist, but note how empty Kant is, as if understanding the world could be fit into a strictly formal analytic) one has to read it.

    Of course, most that do this find it dense and weird, and it is. But this is the idea, really: he had to remove philosophy from assumptions that literally created division where there is none, so it is necessary take up an essentially descriptive vocabulary, putting aside this other vocabulary that was inventing problems. The world is not divided ontologically into any parts, things over there, thoughts and feeling here, and there is no epistemic distance between me and this tree at all. There never was!
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Conceived in thought. I don’t know what that means. There are so many forms of pure a priori cognitions, or so many dissimilar applications of them, I wouldn’t be so ready to call out their conditions. But generally, pure a priori cognitions belongs to reason, which eliminates them from the spontaneity of conceptions, hence “conceived in thought”, which belong to understanding.Mww

    It means that when one asks basic questions about the world, one cannot escape the delimitations of representation. All the understanding can ever affirm lies with his rationalist finitude, an ontology of the formal structure of language only. Inquiry can never penetrate beyond this impossible wall into this impossible actuality of things-in-themselves. These are propositional delimitations, and so whatever is said at all must be found to exhibit this categorical adherence, and this exhausts the understanding. To conceive of pure apriority is to conceive with just these apriori structures in place, in other words, the Critique of Pure Reason dos not escape the finitude of logical possiblities. Logic SHOWS us apriority, but when we speak of what it IS we are necessarily bound to the medium of language's meaning possiblities, the categories. So when Kant says something like, "What must first be given with a view to the a priori knowledge of all objects is the manifold of pure intuition," this sentential construction is itself bound to the categories.
    The "pure" categories are entirely metaphysical postulations. But they cannot be warranted because they can only be derivative of what is IN phenomenological possiblities.

    Phenomenon is the undetermined object of intuition**, which makes explicit no conception is as yet thought as belonging to it. It is merely the matter of sensation given a posteriori, synthesized with the some relevant form residing a priori in the subject himself. To say it is blind is merely a euphemism indicating nothing can be done with representations in this condition, until understanding gets its grubby paws on it and does its rule-bound logical thing. It thinking thing, donchaknow, by which conceptions are connected to that phenomenon, the condition for a possible objective, that is, empirical, cognition.
    **depending on translator; some call it appearance. Either way, the salient point is, undetermined)
    Mww

    It is a confusing way he puts it. Phenomenology, of which Kant is the, well, grandfather, takes the phenomenon to be the whole that comprises all that in makes appearance possible (unless you want to talk about deviations for this, which is not what this here is about). Something does not appear unless it is understood. The color red does not appear to a newly born; only blooming and buzzing. If Kant wants to call the phenomenon as the material equivalent of sensory intuitions, then fine.

    Which leads me to this: what is you opinion on the presence of, or the validity in conditioning the human cognitive system on, imagery?Mww

    Those thoughts I had about Kranky's OP didn't register, eh?

    Conditioning the human cognitive system? Historicity and time.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    There seems to be three main theories of perception: Idealism, Direct Realism and Indirect Realism.RussellA

    I am going to dismiss these. Not that they are not meaningful, but the approach that informs my thinking has no place for them (though after said approach is opened up, there may be room for this, but differently conceived).

    There is the question about the role of language in distancing the language user to their world.. As the Direct Realist directly perceives the world as it is, there is no distance between themselves and the world. As the Indirect Realist only indirectly perceives the world as it is, there is a distance between themselves and the world. As both the Direct and Indirect Realist use the same language, it does not seem that it is language that is opening up a distance between the observer and the worldRussellA

    If the direct realist perceives the world as it is, I would ask, what do you mean by world? If the indirect realist knows the world indirectly, I would ask the same question.

    It is a question of ontology. When one sees a world, what IS it one is seeing? Then, what is seeing, for this question is begged.

    Realism doesn't make any sense until one has discovered what it means for something to be real. One might ask, is General Motors real? It IS a huge automobile manufacturing company, and we talk about it all the time, but we all know that some time in the company came into existence, and this was done in conversation, thematically grounded in business concepts, and these one time came into existence during historical dealings with economics. And when thinking like this sets in, one finds questions as to where language begins and what is real ends. I mean, it is not as if the matter is so clear, for ask about something like a tree of a cloud, and while you may have an object right in front of you, a palpable sensory imposition, the same language constructs that make General Motors what it is, make a tree what it IS, that is, historically, there were primitive relations to trees that expanded pragmatically, socially, descriptively, into these formal institutions of science and society.

    No doubt, there is something there that is not language, don't get me wrong. But the "what is it?" philosophical question has to solve this matter of what is "there" and what makes it what it IS. Traditional talk about primary and secondary qualities, making the tree what it is as something in time and space is still.....talk.

    Language does stand for the world, but "stands in" for the world, as Derrida put it.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Problem with phenomenology is that it is another Kantian idealism without Thing-in-itself.Corvus

    Well, that is a loaded statement, you know. There is so much philosophy in this, one barely knows where to begin. Kant wasn't wrong (though the Critique can be argued endlessly. Was Strawson right? Here and there, yes), but seriously incomplete; such is rationalism.

    I strongly suspect you ground your philosophy in science. If I am wrong, then you can tell me so, but based on what you have said, even when you qualify your naturalism, it is this that rules your basic assumptions. The thing in itself, and idealism, these need to be dismissed at once. Not that they have no meaning, but that they entirely spoil the philosophy because they need context, and if there is no context, then there is nothing at all.
    Rorty once said that one of his bottom line critiques centered around the idea that it was just impossible to see how anything out there in the world got in here, into a knowledge claim, a proposition that says such and such is the case. He was being a naturalist in this line of thinking, but his naturalism was not the ground level for him, pragmatism was.

    So I would ask you, if you like, to ask Rorty's question of how things out there get in knowledge claims, just to begin showing the strength of phenomenology. It begins with the question of epistemology.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Not all thought; thought determined from sensibility only, related to appearances. The categories do not have anything to do with pure a priori cognitions.Mww

    But pure apriori cognition is only conceived in thought. This is the point. The prison.

    Nahhh….phenomena are representations, defined by the synthesis of matter and form, long before understanding exercises its logical function. We are not cognizant of phenomena, which is what you mean by saying they are blind, so…..Mww

    There is no representation long before the exercise of the understanding's logical function. That is impossible.

    It is sensory intuitions that dare blind without concepts.

    Ahhhh…..speaking. One can construct his thoughts without speaking, but he cannot speak without constructing his thoughts.Mww

    There is no interest here in the difference between talking, thinking, writing. In all of these we find the evidential basis for postulating underlying structure.

    Why are we continuing this conversation, when you can’t seem to find anything good about it?Mww

    I sounded a bit negative because you started off being careless in how you put things across. So no choice on my part, really. I do think you got better. Also, philosophy is inherently negative, or critical, deconstructive. This is what it means to question at all.

    Kranky asks,
    Why are our thoughts different from our senses in that the content of thoughts cannot be doubted?Kranky

    Kranky needs to read Heidegger. When we speak of thoughts, senses, moods and general affectivity, and really anything at all, we are speaking (writing, thinking putting down in brail; really this is not the point. Not yet, that is), and so the issue lies not in the difference between the two, but in that which makes differences in the first place, and this is language, "the house of being," as Heidegger puts it. So when we talk about doubt, we need to look into what it means to doubt, and since this is philosophy, the incidental matters are suspended, you know, the details of this and that talked about in various ways in science, in everyday talk, so as to open up inquiry to the most basic assumptions. What is not suspended are these foundational issues that are not encountered in science, like epistemology, ontology, ethics, aesthetics. But you already know this.

    So doubt. When we doubt the senses, we do because we can, so what makes doubt possible? At the most basic level, it is built into language itself, for language can doubt anything language has to say, and this because of the contingency of language, that is, anything that can be put into a proposition, is never some stand alone affirmation (conditionals are affirmations, as are negations, conjunctions, etc.), but has its meaning bound up in a world of already existing possibilities. When I see a cup on the table, it is not a cup until it is assimilated into a vast contextual historical understanding that comprises everything one has received from culture and language modelled by others. Here we discover what a cup IS. Doubt arises when language constructs a context for doubt, and this is possible for anything, thoughts, abstractions, the Taj Mahal, my love of Hagen dasz, simply because anything that can be said, can be doubted. And this the case because the meaning of these things is embedded meaning, and there are no such singularities in what language can say.

    So thought and the senses can all be doubted. The trick for philosophy is to discover something that can affirmed that stands outside of language, but this discovery can only be "discovered" in language, a thesis, a proposition.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    It is definitely the case that the Moon doesn't exist in me when I am seeing it.  It exists out there in space somewhere. It also is the case that the Moon causes the image to appear in my mind when I am seeing it, because when some nights it is raining or cloudy, the image of the Moon doesn't appear in my mind at all even if I try to see it.

    A lot of processes happen physiologically, neurologically and chemically in the body and brain when we see an object.  It is not a simple event even if we say "I see it there" sounding simple.

    The image of the Moon in our mind is not the biological, neurological or chemical substance in the brain or retina, but something immaterial which emerged from the brain as an abstract entity which is the same nature as concepts.
    Corvus

    Keep in mind that when you speak of a brain, it too is "immaterial which emerged from the brain." Weird as this sounds, this is what your thinking here is forcing one to say. You know, if one insists on talking about consciousness being a kind of epiphenomenon of a brain, one creates again and again the basis for this absurdity. Physicalist talk (or some derivative, modified version) will never make epistemology make any sense.

    One has to drop physicalism, materialism, naturalism as an ontology. think of the world as an event in which there is an interface between consciousness and the world, only both are conceived IN the interface. Things are events and the moon and the perceptual act that meets it are really a singularity. Impossible to think of the one without the other, yet in the division that allows talk about "the one and the other" one is abstracting from an original whole.

    Look at it like Rorty does: in his pragmatic, qualified naturalism, you are here, the moon is over there, two objects, and the one can never "get into" the other. Nonsense to think like this. But when I am sith my sister, if she not...well, there? Clearly not a brain event; I mean, my sister is NOT a brain event; she's right there in front of me.

    My view is that BOTH must be accepted: She is not a brain event and she is not what she is independently of my perceiving her when I perceive her. This is the nly conclusion. But how can I be aware of something outside of brain events? Simple: they are not brain events. My brain is not a brain event! But when I witness my brain (in open brain surgery?), the imposition of the witnessing is, well, strongly constitutive of what I see as my brain. To make the move into how this constitution can be analyzed, one has to read the kind of philosophy that does just this, phenomenology.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    But how can it be closed?

    Our only direct knowledge is that of the sensations in our five senses.

    We perceives shapes and colours, relations and quantities, which are clearly not the thing in the world.

    From these sensations alone we infer a world that has caused these sensations

    We can only make inferences when moving from the epistemology of our sensations to the ontology of a presumed world, but inference is not knowledge

    Even though we only know our own sensations, there is an intersubjective agreement about things like the Moon, but is this public agreement about our intersubjective sensations or about a thing in the world causing these sensations?
    RussellA

    But this is a physicalist's view of things, yes? This kind of thinking is what makes the issue an issue, for it localizes the one, sensations, in an ontology, here, while putting the other, that tree, over there, thereby creating this distance. It is okay to speak of this distance in everyday talk, because it is useful to do so, not to forget the sciences that do this all the time. But philosophically, we pull away from common talk in an attempt to look more closely. When we are introduced to a world in infancy, the world out there is not something that has to be discursively determined. Rather, the moon and the rest are already there. No distance has to be crossed to make it so. So what makes this distance arise at all? It is the language in the "over there" and a "a mile that way" and all the talk about under, over, beneath, and so on, and it is in this language setting that distance comes to be. But these meanings have utility, not some authoritative original ontology. Originally, things had no epistemic distance at all. The moon was simply there, as it continues to be.

    The distance came into existence in the utility and familiarity of language's spatial vocabulary, not in the primordiality of things fundamentally separated. Again, the trees, moon, hills and valleys are originally all simply there; the distance was closed before it even opened up. The way to close the distance is to reaffirm what was there at first, and then move from the obvious state that things are over there, outside of this, inside of that, and then ask, how is this possible? The tree is there, now how in the givenness of this clear fact do we give an account? Clearly, I am already connected.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    he analytic/synthetic dichotomy only refers to the relations of subject/predicate conceptual content. Any thought, that is, any cognition by means of conceptions, is analytic if the conceptions in the subject relate in a certain way to the conceptions in the predicate, but synthetic if they do not.Mww

    I'm rather talking about the synthetic nature of a thought, what brings particulars under a heading just to think AT ALL. I say, That is a fence post! None of these terms in play are free of the universality of reference for all concepts are universals, no matter if one is speaking tautologically or synthetically. It is the very nature of speaking at all I refer to.

    Tree is a particular thing, of all possible things; thought of things in general is possible only under a universal conception, a category. Thought is not always of things, but may be of ideas or mere notions, for which no thing is cognizable as relating to it, in which case understanding has no need of the categories, and the idea is itself the universal, re: justice, beauty and the like. The categories belong to understanding and apply only to phenomena; the universals belong to pure reason alone and never apply to phenomena.Mww

    All particularity is lost with Kant. Calling it a particular thing is an employment of a string of concepts that have no dealings at all with whatever there is "before your waking eyes". Rationalism does this to the world. Justice? Beauty? What are these? Such is the world of representations merely: The understanding is essentially conceptual, all concepts are universals. Pure reason is just this, a philosophical construct in a world of representations. Think like Hegel does: a "particular" tree? But what is particularity if not this before me brought under a universal that subsumes all cases of the same kind? Justice and beauty are no different. Rationalist transcendental thinking never confronts the world at all.
    The kingdom of ends? What is a kingdom to the understanding at the level Kant's epistemological analysis? A synthetic term. An end? The same. Pure reason?


    But thought, in and of itself alone, in its empirical nature, is the act of referring a given intuition to an object by means of a conception. It is absurd to suppose we cannot have any such thought, nonetheless in and of itself alone, as doesn’t have an intuition given from an object of the senses.Mww

    Right, but Kant dismisses the content, the "material" of sensible knowledge in favor of the "science" of apriority. The rich content of the tree, its palpable phenomenal presence, has no place in knowledge, for as it is "as such," it is merely "blind". The transcendental aesthetic covers his concerns about a scientific handling of sensibility. Content is lost, and so, there is no being-a-tree in that thing there minus the presence of the reductive function of the understanding, reductive to mere form. Understanding for Kant is a matter of mere form through and through.

    I might be inclined to accede to the idea that transcendental refers to the structure of thought of a certain mode, but less so as reference to the structure of thought in general. In general, transcendental refers to the structure of experience, in that by it certain kinds are either impossible, or merely illusory.Mww

    But what are the categories if not the essential structure of ALL that thought can think? Nothing escapes this. IF there is knowledge, THEN there is representation; so what is representation? It is essentially defined by what the understanding can say, speak, judge. Look out on a clear day at the horizon of things and what does Kant say that you "know" about anything? You know what the synthetic function of the understanding tells you. All else is blind. This is why his moral theory is so vacuous.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Concepts involved in some manner or other are found in every aspect of Kantian critique.Mww

    No, the meaning here is that Kant is talking about a specific critique, not some matter or other that is merely incidental. Incidental things are bracketed in Kant, and attention is solely on the formal structure of logic. Kant cares little, if at all, for the content of judgments.

    Not all thinking for anybody is synthetic, re: principles. But I agree all analysis of the nature of thinking must be done from within the medium being analyzed.Mww

    No. All thinking is synthetic. A thought at all is the application of a universal. 'Tree' is a universal, subsuming particulars under a general idea, so when we say, Look at that tree, the understanding grasps the particular in the universal. Even when one is talking about things in a most particular way, zeroing in on the uniqueness, one is making a synthetic judgment.

    It’s all both?

    Transcendental refers to a certain mode of cognition, so, no, not all his thinking is in that mode, even if he made a name for himself by rebutting Hume in the proving the possibility of it and validity of its use.

    Transcendental this or transcendental that merely describes the origin of, and the limitations for, the conceptions in use. There is empirical thinking, rational thinking….hell, there’s magical thinking. Transcendental thinking is just a higher level of plain ol’ thinking.
    Mww

    No, it does not refer to a certain mode of cognition. It refers to the structure of thought itself.

    No, not just conceptions in use. He says: "The term 'transcendental', that is to say, signifies such knowledge as concerns the a priori possibility of knowledge, or its a priori employment." thus, it is a feature of all knowledge claims. He divides logic into its parts in the analytical attempt to discover that which is in thought itself that is transcendental. He says, "Logic, again, can be treated in a twofold manner, either as logic of the general or as logic of the special employment of the understanding," as a move to dismiss special employment of the understanding so that he can arrive at the general, where he will begin his Deduction to show how the pure forms determined.

    A ultra-modern phenomenologist chastising an Enlightenment continental philosopher. Where’s the news…or indeed the value….in that?Mww

    Or better, where is the argument in this statement? Henry is not ultra modern. He is considered post, post modern, responding the Nietzschean element of post modern nihilism that sways philosophy toward a radical dismissal of metaphysics. Kant is seen as starting this. Heidegger, too. Not atheism, but a critique that throws cold water over all metaphysics. This is continental philosophy, and the issues are timeless, and Henry is right in the middle.

    the value? What is the value of doing philosophy? What is the value of continental philosophy's issues?

    Supposed to be? Who says? How can anything entirely outside possible understanding be supposed at all, much less supposed as an all-encompassing metaphysic? Noumena is nothing but a conception, for which there is no possible representation, which, incidentally, falsifies the claim that all subjectivity is imprisoned by them.Mww

    Kant's is a philosophy of the self, subjectivity. So ask Kant what subjectivity is and what to you get? The transcendental unity of apperception. All things end up HERE. This is why he is a transcendental philosopher. Noumena is, as you say, a mere conception, but it is played against phenomena, the empirical world we live and breathe in. When he talks about things in themselves, he is not wasting space. He has to talk about this if he is going to talk about the finitude of things that are not what they are "in themselves".

    The prison: Calling all phenomena not what things really are in themselves, puts human knowledge in a place where thought cannot escape TO the things themselves. Reality, what is really real is structually beyond grasp.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    If there is a thing having reasonable status by my understanding of it, which implies a non-contradictory judgement, why would I invite doubt to come into play? Doubt arises when the status of a thing is understood as something less than reasonable, meaning, in short, the concepts under which the representation of the thing is subsumed, do not belong to each other with sufficient justice.Mww

    People have non contradictory judgments all the time in "their understanding," no? After all, understanding like this does not play out universally, and so people have entangled doubts about many things, but this is just incidental. Less than reasonable given what one understands has no philosophical status. So the concepts involved in some matter or other are not found in the scope of Kantian critique. Even in science, these are "paradigms" of science. Science itself has doubts. But again, this is not a Kantina issue, not an ontological or epistemological issue. These themes begin with doubt, that is, arguments that look at, say, how it is that a judgment can be both about the world and be apriori, and conclude to something that excludes doubt, affirmation, conditional propositional making and the rest.




    Reality is entirely other, by definition, re: that which corresponds to sensation in general. How he came up with that definition is an example of his transcendental thinking, but it is not a proper indication of why his thinking is called transcendental. Given his definition of what thinking is, it is clear not all his thinking, nor anyone’s for that matter, is transcendental, but is only so from the relation of conceptions, or the origin of the ideas, contained in it.Mww

    Thinking for Kant is synthetic, and to think about how this is so, or what its nature is, must be done in the very medium that is under analysis. This is the basis for positing the transcendental. Thinking shows us a world, as Wittgenstein will say, but cannot show us what thinking is.

    The origin of ideas? What do you mean by this?

    Not all his thinking is transcendental? Well, it's all analytic. And it leads to claims of what is transcendental.

    This other….the aforementioned “other”, as in, reality? That which corresponds to sensation in general can never be representation, so you’re saying Kant was mistaken in not realizing it actually is? So he got his entire paradigm-shifting, drop-your socks, OMG metaphysical do-over….wrong????

    Nahhhh, he didn’t get it wrong; other folks just think they got it more right, when all they really got, was different.
    Mww

    What exists for Kant that can be talked about at all? Concepts without intuitions are empty, intuiitons without concepts are blind. So what is "there" is a synthesis, and one cannot reasonable talk about one absent the other lest having the transcendental dialectic come down one, that is reason wandering off by itself creating illusory thinking. This is what Michel Henry calls "the lost desert of the Dialectic" where subectivity and everything else goes to die, because nothing escapes prison of representational status. The world reduced to representation, not itself "really" there, but something "other".

    What he got wrong is that noumenon is supposed to be an all encompassing metaphysics entirely outside of possible understanding. But how does one arrive at such a concept if not for evidence that issues from the phenomenon? What he discovers in judgment that is apriori is entirely possessed by the discovery itself, and to separate the phenomenon from the noumenon places a limitation on the latter, draws a line where one begins and the other ends, but this is impossible, for one would have to have a vision of both sides to do this. Again, this is Wittgenstein's argument against metaphysics. But this is not to say nothing is transcendental at all. It is to say everything is transcendental; that the transcendental IS the immanental. How can this be? The world we live in is BOTH.

    This is what Kant missed. Philosophers miss this because, an analytic anglo american thinking , transcendentalism is off limits. They are just positivists drunk on the success of science.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?



    I mean, think about it: what is scienctific knowledge and how does it present to me the moon as it is? One has to look not at the quantification, for this doesn't give us anything but relational structures in a system that is ontologically distinct from the presence of the moon itself. Or just plain familiarity. If you see a thing once, and it is sui generis whatever it is, then it is, being sui generis, alien to understanding, and always will be. But introduce this into public scrutiny and its categories historically generated, again and again, it becomes familiar, (see Wittgenstein's Lecture on Ethics for his own example) not by what it is, for this hasn't changed at all, but for the assimilation into the already familiar. But what in the presuppositions of this familiarity establishes the thing to be what it is, or what it has come to be? More relational and mathematical quantifications, which themselves are clearly NOT that thing.

    There is this impossible epistemic and thus ontological distance between knowledge and the world, until, that is, this distance is closed.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    The Idealism of Berkeley doesn't think that anything physical exists outside the mind.RussellA

    not quite. It holds that what is out there IS the perceptual reality of God's perceiving. You know, God is in the quad, as it goes. Not to say this is right, but at least it tries make some sense of the participation of mind in the event of perceptual discovery. God dominated philosophy back then, but the problem remains, addressed by phenomenology only.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    It exists in the physical world with no relation to the mind. However, when you perceive it, it appears in your mind. It doesn't exist in your mind. Your mind just sees it. Seeing is not existing itself.Corvus

    But then, what contributions does "the mind" make to "the moon" being the moon when it encounters that out there we call the moon? Clearly the moon is not simply in one's mind, but nor is the moon simply out there. It is the simplicity that spoils this response, for to say the mind "just sees it" is to ignore the question of epistemic distance as if it didn't exist. Science may do this, for this is not the kind of thing it thinks about, but philosophy? This is where philosophy begins.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Which would be a more appropriate word, do you think? And, to what would that word be applicable?

    What he thinks….covers a lot of ground. Got something in particular in mind, relative to his doubting?
    Mww

    Doubt is something that comes into play in a setting where things that are not doubted have some reasonable status. Kant is not talking about doubting the sun will rise tomorrow. He talking about the nature of sun rising itself. This is why his thinking is called transcendental: reality is not seen, doubted, affirmed, denied, and the rest. Reality is entirely "other".

    Kant's fatal flaw was in not seeing that this radical other cannot be other than that which is called representation, for nothing can stand outside of this other. Metaphysics subsumes physics, not say that physicists are metaphysicians, but to say that physics, and all science and the everydayness of the world, IS also something else entirely.
  • Different types of knowledge and justification
    I'm familiar with the broad critiques of 20th century philosophy. I am not really a fan though. For one, they very often start from the premises of the Anglo-empiricist tradition (even if this is normally to somehow debunk it), or draw on those who did (e.g. Wittgenstein), but I think those premises are quite deficient. That and you get a sort of broad rejection of the pre-modern tradition, largely on the back of Kant's charge of dogmatism and Heidegger's charge of "ontotheology."Count Timothy von Icarus

    I guess by Kant's dogmatism you refer to the transcendental dialectic, which Michel Henry (who is my current interest) refers to as "the lost desert of the dialectic." And Heidegger's ontotheology has to be understood in light of his own spooky "What IS Metaphysics?" which I always appreciated as a nice balance, but he never really understood religion.

    Debunking the angloempiricist tradition: what else is there? There is Buddhism, which is really just a radical phenomenology, as I see it.

    I think these critiques are far weaker than is generally acknowledged, and start from an inaccurate understanding of "classical metaphysics." For example, as Gadamer and others have pointed out, Heidegger starts from the late-medieval nominalism he is familiar (e.g. Suárez) with and then backwards projects this onto classical metaphysics writ large. Yet neo-scholastics and Catholic philosophy more generally tends to look at the late-medieval/Reformation period as one giant "wrong turn" in philosophy to begin with.Count Timothy von Icarus

    I can't imagine Heidegger as a nominalist. Things in the world are "of a piece" with language that "opens" them (alethea). Presocratics, Kant, Hegel, Husserl, and not to forget Kierkegaard whom he dismisses as a religious writer, but read his Concept of Anxiety and you find a lot of what is in Being and Time. And Nietzsche. And the Greeks.

    But I'm not saying you're wrong, just that I don't find the expicit presence of nomilalism. Perhaps I'll read Gadamer and Suarez to see this. Is this where I will find this "onto classical metaphysics writ large"? Why onto classical?

    Greek, yes. But classical in any other way, I don't see it. You know better than I, no doubt.

    The reduction of "reason" (and the activity of the intellect more generally) to discursive ratio alone is a primary culprit here, and the post-structuralist epistemic challenges don't seem immune from this tendency. More broadly, the entire notion of reason as primarily occurring within the context of "language games" tends to be simply presuppose this view of reason, and normally many of the Anglo-empiricist epistemic presuppositions (again, even if they oppose that camp's conclusions). Likewise, the emergence of Sausser's semiotics, and the resultant decoupling of the sign and signified requires that one not begin from the tripartite semiotics embraced by C.S. Peirce, John Deely, etc., which comes out of the Latin tradition (originally from Saint Augustine in the Doctrina Signorum).Count Timothy von Icarus

    But phenomenology is not about language games, though one can compare Wittgenstein with hermeneutical indeterminacy. Post structuralists like Derrida are not into tripartite semiotics. Derrida takes Saussure as a starting place to show how structuralism fails to center meaning, but see John Caputo's thoughts: His deconstruction only leads to one place, which is the completion of Husserl's reduction in a complete annihilation of the presumption to know. This is more Meister Eckhart (I pray to God to be rid of God) than it is post structuralism. It is a revelation.

    I can see resistance to this. It is really, as Levinas would put it, a giving over to the tout autre, which, I have come to believe, is the essential telos of philosophy. Rorty understood this, and switched to teaching literature, which has the actuality of living affairs, but he was a philosopher, not a mystic. He never saw the significance of it.

    And again, this is not to contradict all you say. It is just to point out the importance of post-post modern thinking: Wittgenstein wanted to put and end to metaphysics because it trivialized this, not because he thought it absent of meaning.

    This perhaps explains an historically interesting phenomenon. Catholics love their phenomenology. Husserl's prize student Edith Stein is a Catholic saint. The phenomenologist philosopher Karol Józef Wojtyła became the pope and saint John Paul II. Ferdinand Ulrich is another example, or Hans Urs von Balthasar or Erich Pryzwarra.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Interesting the way this goes, the Heideggerian theologists, Karl Rahner, Michel Henry, Jean Luc Marion, and of course, Edith Stein, not a Heideggarian, but a Husserlian phenomenologist ( was coincidentally reading her dissertation on Empathy when you mentioned her). Catholics are still mostly Thomists, no? I read read precious little of Summa Theologica

    But Heidegger achieved the first comprehensive exposition of the soul, and he might not object to my putting it like this, given that near his death, he stated he never really left the church, surprising Karl Rahner. His openness of truth and human existence and the "nothing" of metahysics restores God to a primordiality lost in tradition (though he would not put it like this. His is a thesis of equiprimodiality, leaving, and aligned here with Wittgenstein, authentic insight to the unspoken. Big issue. Depends on who you read. I lean toward affirmation, evidenced by ethics and aesthetics.

    Yet the epistemic and metaphysical conclusions reached in this alternate tradition tend be quite different (and in some sense, vastly more optimistic). I cannot help but think that this divergence comes from avoiding some of the bad epistemic premises that come down through Hume and Kant and dominate both analytic and continental thought (although prehaps overcome in Hegel to some degree), and the deflation of reason (a sort of concomitant of Charles Taylor's "buffered self," which trends in continental thought, enactivism, etc. have tried to overcome, but often without wholly leaving behind some of its presuppositions). My take is that there is a certain forgetfulness here, an inability to see other options because history has been swept aside by the "devastating" charges of the "critical philosophy."Count Timothy von Icarus

    I don't have much patience for analytic philosophy. All talk, no substance, literally. As Kierkegaard once said of Hegel, they simply forgot that we exist. Which is why think phenomenology finally has it right, that is, the movement toward givenness and the the actuality that lies before one cancels the scholarly work, or, allows it to recede into an invisible understanding that is the stability of being in a world. One now steps into eternity, says Meister Eckhart, and implicitly, Derrida, I mean, Derrida follows the matter all the way down the rabbit hole and one does not end up with bad metaphysics. Rather, it is, finally, the world and its inherent religious dimension in the existential disclosure. This is where philosophy has been trying to go since the beginning of inquiry. I think philosophers like Rorty (Dewey, James, Peirce) are right, well, reject metaphysics, but simply see the world as foundationally empty. I recall Simon Critchley criticizing Rorty for trying a secular pragmatic analysis of ethics while standing in the nullity of an argument.

    Charles Taylor's Sources of the Self I have right here. I will begin later today. Thank for that!

    No, I don't. I think we are in agreement here? I was just pointing that out as a common position that seems relevant to the consideration of "what it is like to be..." I think human imagination, while fallible, is capable of accurately covering such ground to varying degrees, and I also think that claims to special epistemic status due to being a member of a group tend to be bunk. This is not to say they might not be appropriate in some cases, but they are often called upon to adjudicate questions in economics, political science, etc., where I think the special pleading is not appropriate.Count Timothy von Icarus

    You know, I think this right. To talk about othes in these contexts involves one in the broader contexts of political ends, trying to secure funds to redress actual problems, relying on iffy data, spinning research, and so on, and this turns positions into distortions, and these are thrown into the collective thinking, congealed into meaning, then become assumptions in an ideology. The ctuality is lost, as with the way a very nice observation that people are harmed by careless talk turns into dissertations about how we should modify or limit speech and podium pounding campaigns, making statistics into social realities. I AM in favor of a gentler world, more caring of others, but I don't want the new "simulacra" of the politically driven media.

    If that, or thereabouts, is what you are talking about.


    don't see language as a "barrier," here. I think language, sign systems, models, etc. (and the senses) are best thought of a means of knowing, that through which we know, not what we know. The sign vehicle in the semiotic triad is not some sort of impenetrable barrier that forever keeps the object and the interpretant separated, but is rather the very means of their nuptial union, which is why the sign relation is irreducibly triadic and defies reductionist analysis. The difficulty in "knowing what it is like to be a bat," rather flows from the difference in sense knowledge (which is itself ultimately a primarily a means).Count Timothy von Icarus

    I would agree if is wasn't for that pesky business of the question, the "piety of thought". It is not as if there is no question as to the relation between language and the world. The triad only makes sense if such questions are just ignored. Phenomenologists say the world we live in and talk, make plans, and so on, is fine. It is the bulk of our lives (the they, Heidegger calls it, not pejoratively. He calls normal time "vulgar" time, again, not to mock this, but to say it stands outside analysis, as Einstein might call everyday concepts of gravity preanalytic, and thus vulgar) that is like this. But philosophy wants to close in on the presuppositions of all this, which brings question to all things, and language, the question language asks of itself, seems to be the final question.
  • If our senses can be doubted...why can't the contents our of thoughts too?
    Even if that were the case, isn’t it necessarily presupposed there is an object to identify, correctly or otherwise? If so, then deny that very same necessary object as a content of perception, is contradictory, from which it follows…..barring absurdity….that object itself cannot be doubted.Mww

    But Mww, I thought you were a Kantian (I recall from some time ago). He would never allow that kind of thing. Objects of perception are not to be denied empirically, but philosophically, doubt is a mild word for what he thinks.
  • Different types of knowledge and justification
    So, is this properly knowledge? It does seem to involve an adequacy of experience to things. If it isn't knowledge, what do we make of the fact that it seems possible to imagine "what it is like to be" more or less accurately, or to gain direct experience in some of these cases? If we aren't gaining knowledge of "what it is like to be..." then what are we gaining? "Memory?" But then it seems we can use that memory to say: "that's not what that is like!" That is, to call some description false, implying that such memories contain truth (and thus knowledge).

    I would allow that intellectual knowledge might be most properly called knowledge. However, understanding ("intellectual consideration") would also seem to be of a higher intellectual order than justified propositional belief, and "knowing what it is like to be..." seems to include a crucial element of understanding. Maybe Mary the Color Expert is relevant here too perhaps. The perfection of the conformity of the intellect to being seems like it might require a grasp of things not reducible to language (but of which language can serve as a sign).
    Count Timothy von Icarus

    Of course, if you ask Derrida, this conformity is an impossible problematic. Grasping things not reducible to language is the "other" side where understanding meets its metaphysical (under erasure) counterpart, for to acknowledge at all is a transcendental affair as that which is acknowledged stands at an epistemic distance from ipseity (to borrow the jargon typically used for this kind of talk), and no matter how strong the grasp is, it is structurally untouchable (notwithstanding Husserl, et al).

    But anyway, you seem to be talking about empathy, and whether it is possible. Do you really think being in a marginalized group makes one so radically different from those who are not, but sympathize, that knowing what their plight, their issues, their pov, should be called into question? The knowledge claim of one who stands outside a group depends not so much on the qualitative distinctness of the group, but rather on the universal descriptive features of this group and seeing here that there is warrant for their cause. But interpretatively. one does stand at a distance as one stands naively outside any field. This, though, doesn't make empathy impossible, just limited.

    The bat? That is a theoretical distance that is almost absolute, again, especially given that language itself is an alien imposition on all things.