• David Hume
    That's exactly the point I'm making. I'm not saying that our beliefs can either be justified or not (that's an entire epistemological position) I'm disputing that there is any good grounds for specify that science cannot justify the passions, as if there were some other group of things that it could justify. If there's nothing that science can justify (in that way) then the comment is entirely specious, claiming to provide some in formation about 'the passions', when in fact it is merely reporting the limits of science in general.Pseudonym

    I don't understand your point. Science does what it does - it provides explanations of a certain sort. What it does not do is provide warrant for every belief - indeed, for most beliefs. I do not require a scientific explanation of vision in order to believe that there is a table in front of me - all I need is to look and see.

    This rather presumes a position on conciousness which is far from agreed upon.Pseudonym

    No, I do not take any metaphysical positions about consciousness. I am making straightforward observations about beliefs and justifications.

    'Hungry' would be typically held as being that disposition which (in the absence of competing forces) would cause a person to eat. It is perfectly possible that your brain could be in that state, but the part of your brain responsible for generating the epiphenomenon of concious awareness erroneously reports that you are not. In that sense you would be incorrect about your assertion 'I'm hungry'.Pseudonym

    A belief, even a justified belief, does not have to be inerrant.
  • David Hume
    Does this mean that you believe free will to be incompatible with determinism? Would you then say that our sense of free will is an illusion?Perplexed

    Not that this is particularly relevant to either free will or the actual topic of this thread, but charleton is talking out of his ass: science does not "assert determinism."
  • David Hume
    Reductive explanation is a reason to believe. It is the standard reason we believe in everything else, that we have a reductive explanation for its being the case.

    The comment I was disputing was "he is simply saying that the reasoning of science cannot justify them, [the passions]".

    My argument was, in what way can the reasoning of science "justify" anything other than by explaining the causal chain of its existence back a few steps?
    Pseudonym

    You are asking the wrong question. Almost none of our beliefs are justified (in our mind) by science. So if you only accept reductive explanations as justification for beliefs, then you would have to conclude that almost all of our beliefs lack any justification whatsoever - and that cannot be true, because it is part of our usual understanding of the notion of "justified belief" that a large proportion of our beliefs is fairly justified.

    I have a passion 'hunger', science can explain exactly what that passion is in physical terms (brain states), why it is there causally (DNA - protein synthesis - neurons development - interaction with the environment), and also why it is there teleologically (evolutionary function of hunger). What additional thing can science provide with regards to the proposition "the sky is blue" that is missing from what science can tell us about passions such as to warrant the distinction made?Pseudonym

    Whether or not I know of some scientific explanation for my feeling of hunger or my perception of the color of the sky is completely irrelevant to my warrant for holding the respective beliefs.
  • David Hume
    You are equating justification with a reductive explanation. Sometimes that is the case, but not always, and clearly not in the case of "passions." I am sorry, but it is patently silly to say that hunger is "justified" by some reductive neurophysiological account. Justification - as you yourself said - is reason to believe. I don't require to know any facts other than my feeling of hunger in order to justifiably believe that I am hungry. If someone pointed out some other facts that suggest a different conclusion - e.g. that I had a meal less than an hour ago - those other facts wouldn't trump my justification. And if someone did a CAT scan or whatever and concluded that my "brain can be shown to be in a state common to all other humans who desire food," that would be entirely superfluous to the justification that I already have. If I feel hungry then I am hungry. Passions are self-justifying.
  • Implications of Intelligent Design
    If one could show that the properties as enumerated in premise one are not the properties of intelligent design, then those who argue against the argument to intelligent design may have a point. However, the analogy is perfect. In fact it's hard to imagine a better analogy.Sam26

    This must be the Donald Trump school of philosophy.
  • Implications of Intelligent Design
    I want to step back a little and ask this question: How could we generalize the notion of design when all we know is human design? We could, of course, identify things that are common to all or most human designs, but, as @Pseudonym has pointed out, that would trivially include such properties as being produced by people. In order to select broader design criteria, we must already have some idea of what else, other than human design, our definition is going to encompass. But then, of course, to do what @Sam26 wanted to do, i.e. turn that definition around and use it to infer a matter of fact would be invalid. We already bundled that matter of fact into the definition.

    Still...

    I'd set forth that what a designed entity does is fulfill some purpose that, in this case, an intelligent being wants to be fulfilled (hence why I'm bringing up desire before, but here I'm introducing purpose as well).Moliere

    It seems to me that we need some notion of, first, a being who wants, and second, a purpose which fulfills that want.Moliere

    Yes. The lesson from the failure of various attempts to come up with a set of narrow criteria that define design - criteria that apply just to the product of design (complexity and such) - is that design properties must be broad: they must encompass not just the thing that is designed but, essentially, the designer as well.

    The point is that when we look at human productions that exhibit the features named in premise one, they are the result of intelligent design. In fact, even if you had never seen a watch before (Paley's argument), and stumbled upon one, you surely wouldn't conclude it happened by chance. Why? Because we are very familiar with the evidence of intelligent design.Sam26

    No, the reason we recognize a watch as a designed thing is not because we can recognize some general hallmarks of design just by looking at it. It is hard to get into the mind of a person from a primitive culture, where there are no watches. But plausibly, she would realize that the watch is unlike any familiar objects of nature. At the same time, she might reason that people (or other anthropomorphic agents - gods?) manufacture things that are not otherwise encountered in nature, and on these grounds suppose that the watch is one such artefact. This inference already relies on broad observations - observations that are external to the thing in question.

    (I'm always using too many comma's...)Moliere

    You should worry more about too many apostrophes ;)
  • Implications of Intelligent Design
    My reference to some other ID-ers and creationists was just such an attempt to identify a more favorable sampling, where the number of instances is not too many (not every living organism or every species ever) and not too few (not life or the universe itself, which in any case doesn't fit Sam's criterion). If the Designer only occasionally magics a new design, then the numbers can be at least comparable.

    I then went on to point out that the design criterion used by those other creationists is actually not the one Sam used. And no, of course I don't think that such Design of the Gaps is a good argument.

    There are, I think, just two distinctive families of objects under consideration: human artefacts and biological organisms. Because clearly there are many more within-group commonalities than there are between-group commonalities. And also because it's silly to deny evolution and common descent in this day and age. So, just on statistical grounds, any inference that sorts instances into groups judging by their appearances is going to be extremely weak: there are only two instances here.


    But is there something to the idea that
    Objects of nature have a structure where the parts are so arranged that the whole can achieve or be used to achieve activities of a higher order than any part aloneSam26

    Well, on one level this just seems to beg the question by referring to "parts" that are "arranged" in order to "achieve" or "be used" for something.

    On another level, charitably interpreting the mereological and teleological language as merely descriptive, this could be seen as describing a generic complex system, where parts (with the proviso that mereology is at least partly subjective) interact with each other. In any such system "the whole is more than the sum of its parts." But this reading is much too broad. Not only does it fit everything in this universe, but it even fits countless other possible systems, most of which have nothing to do with design.

    So back to teleology then?

    I'd contend that objects of nature, like a tree or a cat, do not have a structure where the parts are so arranged that the whole can achieve or be used to achieve a higher order than the parts alone. Or, really to put it better and keep our positions linguistically distinct, I think I'd add more to this definition of intelligent design than what you've laid out here.Moliere

    Actually, there may be something - not in all objects of nature, but specifically in biological organisms - that exhibits such a teleological structure. It is hard not to notice how naturally we think in terms of functions when we think about organisms, both from the perspective of their present-day structure and behavior and from the perspective of their evolutionary development. Indeed, this has been noted both by theoretical biologists and by philosophers (Ruth Millikan being particularly notable among the latter). I refer you to this short SEP article: Teleological Notions in Biology.

    But, first, there are plausible reasons for biological organisms having this structure that have nothing to do with being the product of intelligent design (see above). Second, as @StreetlightX noted, the more we learn about them, the more we see how very different those biological "designs" are from all the incontestable examples of design that we know. And, as I said, no reasonable inference can be made from one family of objects to another, very dissimilar family of objects, on the grounds of one tenuous commonality.
  • Implications of Intelligent Design
    The amount of instances that form the basis is extremely weak, so much so as to be completely damning to the analogy. Human artefacts represent a tiny proportion of all things in set A. There is an estimated 300 trillion tonnes of human artefacts in the world. There are an estimated five million trillion trillion bacteria. Even if we average human artefacts at just 1g, bacteria alone outnumber human artefacts by five trillion trillion times. All the failed organisms from the process of evolution outnumber human artefacts. by several trillion times more than this. It is ludicrous to suggest that anything about human artefacts tells us something about natural objects by strength of analogy. It would be like claiming you knew something with great certainty about all architecture because you studied one brick.Pseudonym

    I hesitate to say that this is unfair to @Sam26's argument, because it doesn't look like he has thought through any of it. Still, this is probably not a charitable count. It assumes that every single organism that ever lived is a separate instance of design, which, to my knowledge, no one has claimed in recent times.

    A more recognizable position would be to assume that each species (however tenuous this concept gets for bacteria and archea) is a separate instance of design. That number, of course, would still dwarf the number of human designs. But this would still be a rather extreme creationist position, and @Sam26 has admitted that he accepts evolution. Is Life a single instance of design then? Or perhaps even the nomological structure of the universe? But the formula "parts that together perform a higher order function" (problematic as it is) can hardly apply to life in general or the laws of nature - it is clearly inspired by particular instances of organismal "designs".

    So maybe @Sam26 would be sympathetic to such ID advocates as Michael Behe, who accept some role for natural evolution, but stop well short of the universal common descent? The picture that they paint of evolution is that of a creaking, forever stalling mechanism that requires God to engage in unceasing busywork, pushing here and tinkering there to keep things going. The results of this tinkering include such wonders as the emergence of the malarial organism's resistance to the only effective antimalarial drug (Behe's favorite example) - apparently so that more poor African children can suffer and die.

    But Behe and other prominent ID advocates' design criteria are substantially different from the vague one that @Sam26 offered. They can be basically summarized as "Whatever nature cannot do" - Design of the Gaps, in other words. Behe capitalizes on "irreducible complexity" - the idea that a mechanism in which the removal of any single part would compromise its function cannot evolve by natural means and therefore has to be magicked every time. Bill Dembski does something similar with his "universal probability bound" numerology and a number of other abortive attempts at demarcating design as a complement to nature. These ID proponents do not posit that every complex system that presents the appearance of a functional mechanism must be an instance of design (although that may be the conclusion for which some of them aim); rather, they are a priori agnostic on what nature alone can accomplish, but they claim that there is a limit to nature's autonomous capabilities, that what our universe exemplifies goes beyond that limit, and that anything that is left over is ipso facto an instance of "intelligent design."
  • Implications of Intelligent Design
    First, if I was to put forth the argument it would take the following inductive form:Sam26

    As @Pseudonym says, this is not an inductive argument - this is no argument at all.

    By higher order, I mean that when parts are put together they achieve a higher order than any part alone.Sam26

    You really don't see how unhelpful this circular explanation is?


    The theory of Intelligent Design comes down to this:



    OK, so this was a bit of silly fun, and yet this is essentially correct. The Intelligent Design "explanation" is that an agent with unknown motives and unconstrained abilities conceived and brought about by unknown means... whatever it is that cries out for an explanation, just the way it actually happens to be.

    In other words: Magic man dunnit.

    The problem with this "theory" has already been unwittingly identified by one of its proponents in this thread:

    On the other hand, if those who don't believe in intelligent design aren't committing the fallacy of the self-sealing argument, answer the following: What would count as evidence of intelligent design?Sam26

    The answer is, of course - nothing. And that's not a "fallacy of the self-sealing argument" - that is a fatal defect of a theory, which is in-principle untestable. It can account for anything and its opposite. Hell, it could even counterfactually account for nothing! If there were no physical universe, that would just mean that the Designer did not get around to design it. If the universe was not life-supporting - well, apparently that's just what the Designer wanted. If it was completely chaotic - that must have been the plan all along. Good design counts; bad design counts as well! Anything goes - and therefore nothing can serve as evidence.

    Evidence is contrastive: for there to be evidence for, there must be potential evidence against. Bayesian model of inductive inference shows this quantitatively, but in truth every more-or-less sensible empirical epistemology says the same thing.
  • What will Mueller discover?
    Meanwhile, a senior official in Trump administration effectively sabotaged the release of the much-anticipated list of corrupt Russian oligarchs and officials who benefited from their ties to the Kremlin. The impending event caused much anxiety in Russian power circles; reportedly, meetings were conducted at different levels of government just to discuss possible courses of action following the release of the list.

    When the "Kremlin list" finally came out, in Russia it was met with incredulity, mirth and relief. It included the complete list of richest businessmen cribbed directly from the latest Russian Forbes report, plus the list of all heads of government departments, including even such innocent figures as the head of the presidential human rights council. Naturally, such a formal and all-inclusive catalogue is worthless. And one wonders why it took months to come up with a list that could have been compiled within a few hours at most.

    According to Anders Åslund, who was involved in the Congress-mandated effort, that's pretty much what happened. At the last moment some unknown administration official ditched the work of Russia experts and replaced it with this nonsense, which made the whole effort look ridiculous.
  • Science is just a re-branding of logic
    In other words, I am suggesting that to follow a rule of induction is no different to following any other rule; it is a normative principle pertaining to language-games, but not in any way that is significant to metaphysics or epistemology.sime

    Of course induction is normative - I don't understand why you keep saying this as if this is something controversial. And your last remark makes me wonder what you think metaphysics and epistemology are about.
  • Science is just a re-branding of logic
    No one denies that we do think - and behave - inductively (except maybe Popperians).SophistiCat

    Umm, no. Popperians wouldn't claim so either:Ying

    I am not sure why you posted this lengthy excerpt in response to my off-hand remark. In it Popper criticizes Hume's psychological account of induction, ending up endorsing the view that "We obtain our knowledge by a non-inductive procedure."

    First of all, I wasn't referring to Hume specifically. By "inductive thinking" I meant our tendency to identify patterns of occurrences and extrapolate them beyond the available concrete facts, both as a way of explaining what we know and of predicting what we don't know.

    You might instead argue that Popper rather overstates his opposition to induction, and that his own view is distinguished only in some particulars from the common-sense take that I outlined above. But this is not all too obvious from your quote.

    Anyway, this is all very dated stuff, of interest mainly to historians.
  • Science is just a re-branding of logic
    Sorry, i meant warrant being epistemologically vacuous.sime

    I still have no idea what you mean by this. Warrant is what makes epistemology normative. To say that such and such belief is warranted is to say that you can and should believe such and such. What is vacuous about this?
  • What will Mueller discover?
    The action taken was telling McGahn to have Mueller fired. What exactly would it take for you to accept it as an action/order? Must Trump personally hand deliver a notice of termination?Michael

    po2SNcP.png

    "Attempted murder", now honestly, what is that!? Do they give a Nobel prize for "attempted" chemistry?
  • Science is just a re-branding of logic
    Doesn't the difference entirely rest upon the normative and hence subjective context by which we judge behaviour to be future-anticipating?sime

    Of course warrant is normative. How can you say that it is both normative and vacuous? That seems contradictory.
  • Science is just a re-branding of logic
    If a man's beliefs are identified with his non-verbal behavioursime

    That is a very contentious proposition, and in any case, I don't see how it bears on warrant. No one denies that we do think - and behave - inductively (except maybe Popperians).
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    (1) God exists as a matter of necessity,
    or
    (2) It is at least logically coherent to think of God as a necessary being.

    You say that (1) obviously entails the desired conclusion, but as you point out, it is worthless because (1) just is the conclusion. So we have to understand the premise as (2). I am not sure what would be wrong with (2). You have said it is too weak, but I'm not sure why.
    PossibleAaran

    That the second premise seems weak is a point in its favor (whether it really is weaker than the first premise and whether it even makes sense is debatable) - it is what helps to sell it as a premise to someone who does not already believe the conclusion.

    (2*) The concept of a being that necessarily exists is logically coherent.
    (4) Therefore, it is logically possible that there is a being that necessarily exists.
    (5) Therefore, there is a being that necessarily exists.

    The inference from (4) to (5) is just collapsing the modal operators in accord with S5. The inference from (2*) to (4) assumes that if a concept is logically coherent, it is logically possible that it is instantiated.
    PossibleAaran

    Yes, and my point is that this interpretation of possibility makes it unfaithful to the underlying logic, because it suggests that there is some difference between (2) or (2*) and (1), whereas there should be none.

    Actually, it is not all that clear what it means to say "The concept of a being that necessarily exists is logically coherent." I hold the same opinion as you regarding necessary existents: with no constraints on possible worlds other than the rules of logical inference, there should not be any. (I am bracketing off "things" like ideas, abstractions, logical and mathematical entities and the like - presumably, when we talk about the existence of God, we are interested in something more than a mere idea of God.) But then it follows that the concept of a being that necessarily exists is inconsistent with this proposition that I already hold to be true, given the rules. So how is it coherent? Of course, as I mentioned earlier, we could play by different rules, stipulating, for example, that the relevant possible worlds are only those in which God exists (in much the same way as in my earlier example, where all relevant possible worlds contained the same immovable walls in the same places). That idea would be coherent - but unfortunately, stipulating such rules begs the question.

    But again, the reason I resent Plantiga's argument is that he seems to want to sidestep such close examination of the premise, encouraging the reader instead to accept the premise because it sounds so unassuming and innocent. And so seemingly different from the proposition "God exists in all possible worlds" contained inside it. It is as if we were just picking up that outrageous proposition and looking at it at arm's length. But that feeling is betrayed, once the meaning of possibility is switched in mid-argument.
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    Let me make some general remarks first, just to make sure that we are on the same page (and to help those who are less conversant with the topic).

    1. Modality is a way of thinking, talking, reasoning about the world. Modality can be a property of a proposition, but It makes no sense to talk about modal properties of a thing. Modality is a way of talking about things. So a "necessary being" is just a shorthand for saying that it is necessarily the case that such and such exists.

    2. Modality can be understood and deployed in different ways. Those ways differ in their ground rules: what we hold to be fixed about the world, and what we allow to vary. Thus, an epistemic modality is where we reason from available evidence (presumably, also taking certain other things as given, such as known laws of nature). Nomic modality is where we hold just (some) laws of nature as fixed. Metaphysical modality is where we hold certain metaphysical constraints as fixed. And so on. Any set of constraints generates its own modal framework. As a limiting case, a priori (or logical) modality is where only the rules of inference are fixed.

    For example, if I need to make my way from my office on the second floor to another office on the fifth floor, there are different ways in which it is possible for me to accomplish this. I can take different corridors, take different turns, use the stairs or the elevator, etc. But whatever I do, I have to contend with certain necessary facts: the fact that there are walls that I can neither move nor destroy (they are necessary beings in this context - they always exist in the same way, whatever course of action I take). I also cannot fly or teleport, there is a limit to the speed of my movement, etc.

    3. There are different mathematical theories of modality, or modal logics. A theory is agnostic about the world on which it operates; it is agnostic even about the meaning of modal terms. All it does is it establishes certain rules for manipulating modal propositions. Defining the world and giving meaning to the modal operators gives a particular interpretation to the theory. As long as the rules of the theory are obeyed throughout, you are entitled to make use of its theorems to make meaningful inferences.

    Now, returning to Plantiga's argument:

    The starting premise is that it is logically possible that a maximally great being exists. If someone believes that a maximally great being does exist, then they surely also believe that it is logically possible. Now consider someone who doesn't already believe the conclusion. Such a person might believe that the concept of a maximally great being is coherent. I think many people who deny the existence of God do believe that the concept is at least coherent. But then, it could be pointed out to them that this premise, which they believe, entails that a maximally great being exists. Why wouldn't that be an effective argument?PossibleAaran

    You want to make use of the so-called S5 modal logic. In this theory, stringing several modal operators together has the same effect as taking just the last of those operators. So, something that is possibly necessary is just necessary. Any model (i.e. true interpretation) of this theory has to respect that rule. So when you propose that "it is ... possible that a ... being [necessarily] exists," that has to be understood as just proposing that "a ... being [necessarily] exists." Whatever interpretation you give to this proposition - however you interpret possibility and whatever properties your proposed being possesses - what I wrote above has to be the case, or else this is not a model of S5.

    Yet, the way you want to reason, there seems to be a difference between the following two propositions:

    (1) God exists as a matter of necessity,
    (2) It is at least logically coherent to think of God as a necessary being.

    One is a very strong proposition that obviously entails the conclusion of the argument, and thus it is no good as a premise. The other sounds like a much weaker proposition, one that we could accept without committing to the first proposition. Whether that is actually a reasonable reading of these sentences is not even the point - the fact is that you are trying to equivocate on the meaning of your modal terms. You are insinuating a meaning that is not consistent with the theory whose theorem you then want to use in order to reach the conclusion of the argument. You are not arguing in good faith.
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    All of this is quite uncharitable to Plantinga.PossibleAaran

    He does define his 'super-duper being' very carefully. He defines a maximally great being as one which is maximally excellent in every possible world, and maximal excellence is defined as entailing omnipotence, omniscience and moral perfection. To wit, the first two premises of his argument from the Nature of Necessity, page 214PossibleAaran

    Fair enough, I didn't read that book - my recollection is of his own gloss of the argument in a short paper that I no longer have at hand. So let's assume the more careful formulation as you present it.

    In that case, he seems to be fairly laying his cards on the table (assuming the reader is paying attention!), thus severely handicapping the argument right from the start. His ontological argument is much weaker than Anselm's; he does not just beg the question: the premise that he asks us to accept is much stronger than the conclusion of the argument. Thus, even those who already believe the conclusion independently may not accept his starting premise. (You seem to be of that opinion, judging by what you said concerning the issue of necessary existence.)

    I think there's a fundamental problem with saying that a logical necessity is logically possible. I can't quite put my finger on what that problem is, though, but as I said before, my instinct is that it's related in kind to Tarski's hierarchy of language.Michael

    It is not problematic in the formal system to which Plantinga appeals. But that formal system (modal logic known as S5) basically ratifies your intuition: it posits as an axiom (or is it a theorem?) that adding the qualification of possibility to something that is already necessary changes nothing - it is an empty move devoid of any consequence, like multiplying by one or adding zero. (By the way, the same happens when you qualify possibility with necessity: necessity in that case does no work either.) So when that move is made and expounded on in a natural language formulation that seems to appeal to our informal intuitions concerning possibility, and yet in the end we are assured that "possibility" and "necessity" were used in their strict formal sense all along, you are right to be suspicious.

    But then, suppose I don't have this bias. Suppose that I am not such that, when I see that a premise entails that God exists, I will not accept that premise.PossibleAaran

    I hope I explained why this is not the reason that neither I nor anyone who understands the argument that Plantinga is making - not in retrospect, but right as it is unfolding - would be likely to accept it.

    You also say that it is illegitimate to predicate necessary existence. Why? You say that Michael's argument shows why. But which argument of Michael's do you mean?PossibleAaran

    It is what @StreetlightX and @Michael (and, no doubt, others who have criticized Anselm's argument) have said about predicating existence (necessary existence, as has been discussed, has even more severe problems). Having properties implies existence. So when we predicate a property of something, the qualification "provided that the thing exists" is already implied. When we define a unicorn as "a horse with a single horn," the same definition could be equivalently restated as "a being, such that if it exists, it exists as a horse with a single horn." The actual predicate here is still "being a horse with a single horn," nothing more. So when we "predicate" existence of a being, that is equivalent to saying "a being, such that if it exists, it exists" - which is just a tautology that applies to any hypothetical being.

    Do you mean the argument that we can tack 'necessary existence' onto any concept and then create an argument for its existence, regardless of what the concept is?PossibleAaran

    That, too. Plantinga's argument is, if anything, even easier to parody than the original. Those attributes of Super-Dupeness Maximal Greatness do no work in the argument - they ride free and thus can be replaced with anything whatsoever.
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    Perhaps we could argue that the world is the necessary thing, as it seems tautological to say that the world exists in every possible world.Michael

    Possible worlds for the World are just all the ways in which the World could possibly be (where the sense of "possibility" is left open).
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    There are many versions of it, some intensely complicated. The OPs version is Anselmian, and those arguments typically run:

    (1) If God exists then God necessarily exists. (G -> nG) [Partial Definition of God]
    (2) If its logically possible that God exists then God exists (pG -> G) [From (1)]
    (3) It is logically possible that God exists. (pG) [Premise]
    (C) God exists (G) [From 1-3].
    PossibleAaran

    This doesn't really have much to do with Anselm's argument, other than being a species of an a priori "ontological" argument, one that, in a way of magical thinking, attempts to reify logical constructs.

    Imagine a being, such that it cannot fail to exist.
    Therefore, it exists.
    SophistiCat

    You see I don't think so. None of the premises of the argument say 'imagine a being such that it cannot fail to exist'.PossibleAaran

    I glossed possibility as conceivability - perhaps not quite what Plantinga was trying for. In his version he actually breaks the premise into two in order to obfuscate his meaning. It goes something like this:

    First he asks us to accept that a Super-Duper Being is at least within the realm of the possible (not his exact words, of course, but that doesn't matter, since he doesn't explain what the words mean in this premise). Hopefully, a charitable and careless reader will not ask what a Super-Duper Being is and will grant this premise for the sake of an argument.

    Then he spring the trap: a Super-Duper Being is one that, among other things, exists necessarily (cannot fail to exist). And he further stipulates that the words "possible" and "necessary" were being used in a technical sense of the S5 modal logic, where stacked modal operators collapse into one.

    In the possible world semantics, a Super-Duper being is such that, if it exists in one possible world, it exists in all possible worlds. So the premise then is simply that it does exist in at least one possible world. Of course, stated this way, no one who does not independently believe the conclusion would go along with such an argument (and those who do ought not go along with it either).

    But necessary existence is a property, and is immune to the criticism which Kant makes.PossibleAaran

    It is illegitimate to predicate existence in all possible worlds, just as it is illegitimate to predicate existence in some possible worlds. And @Michael's argument neatly shows why it makes no sense to predicate existence.
  • Ontological Argument Proving God's Existence
    The 'argument' may as well read:

    There exists a being, such that, it exists.
    Therefore, it exists.
    StreetlightX

    Or,

    Imagine a being, such that it cannot fail to exist.
    Therefore, it exists.

    (That's Plantinga's version, only he obfuscates it a bit.)
  • Vicious Circularity
    I don't know about circular arguments, but concepts are sometimes said to have a circular dependency. (Specifically, we are talking here about a "tight" circle, involving only a few concepts.) The dependency is not vicious if it is unavoidable on the one hand, and on the other hand the whole construct works reasonably well.

    For example, it is argued that time and clock have such a virtuous circular dependency. Neither concept can be understood without the other, but together they seem to make sense.
  • Why were 2 of my threads deleted?
    When TheMadFool, Bahman, this "programming god" guy vomit up several new topics each day, any deletion for "low post quality" is going to look arbitrary at best, malicious at worst.
  • Exploding Elephants
    Nice video.

    The material ontology consisting of inert, amorphous matter substrate as a distinct existent, with form and/or animating spirit or force or process acting on it as another distinct component of existence is both ancient and surprisingly ubiquitous and persistent. For example, ancient materialists, who you would not think of as natural allies of Plato, also believed something like this. And this sort of thinking is still current.

    Of course, proponents of this view would not be much discouraged by your exploding elephant - they would just push "matter" to lower, sub-cellular scales (as, of course, has long since been done in the normal process of scientific reductionism).


    Another thing that this video reminded me of (again): You often hear people say how machine-like biological mechanisms appear to be - surely, a hallmark of design! I think this is just a superficial impression that is an artifact of the way we analyze and present scientific models, which is like engineering in reverse (or reverse engineering). The impression I get is the opposite. When you look at living things with an unprejudiced eye, as well as when you learn the bewildering array of biological facts, such as those described in the video, it strikes you just how messy and complicated and thoroughly alien these things are. They are so obviously not designed by anything like a human designer*, but grown, evolved through billions of generations across billions of individuals in a blind and unthinking, but massively integrated process: integrated across all physical scales, all the way to the bio-chemical and even quantum mechanical level.

    And what role does this inert, formless "matter" play in all this? It seems like a useless kludge, and we should rid our thinking of it.

    * And it's no use saying that the designer is totally unlike a human designer: that just removes any reason for inferring design in the first place.
  • Majoring in Philosophy
    to do philosophy really well you have to be able to write clearly and precisely.Sam26

    You mean there are really people who think this is not the case? I find that amazingSam26

    I take it you weren't exposed to much Continental philosophy in your curriculum ;)
  • The "Real" Socratic Paradox
    Well, there are purely conceptual resolutions based on disentangling equivocations about words such as "good" and "evil."

    Another consideration is that we are not always presented with a binary choice of good vs. evil. In any morally non-trivial situation we end up doing some sort of moral balancing, choosing the least evil or the good that seemingly outweighs the attendant evil. And different people in different epistemic situations will balance the scales differently, hence one person may judge another person's choice as evil on the balance.

    Also, Socrates assumes a perfectly rational agent, but people are not perfectly rational agents. What constitutes intentional action or desirable action is not always clear. Sometimes we do something we seemingly don't want to do, even without being forced. Sometimes we do what we know we ought not to do. I don't think these ambiguities can be satisfyingly fixed with conceptual analysis, because there is no unambiguous fact of the matter, not in such simple terms.
  • Can something be deterministic if every outcome is realized?
    I don't understand what's the issue either. Maybe let me restate the question. Does determinism apply to a situation where all outcomes can and are realized?Posty McPostface

    In a deterministic universe every possible outcome can and is realized (in its time), since every event realizes the only outcome that is possible at the moment when it happens.

    Does this answer your question?

    Do you even have any clear idea about what you are asking? I get a strong impression that you don't.
  • Can something be deterministic if every outcome is realized?
    No, it doesn't.

    "In such a universe" - what universe? You mentioned interpretations, plural. Are you thinking of some particular interpretation?

    And why would determinism not makes sense?

    Really, why do you start a thread if you can't even express your thought in a few coherent sentences?
  • Can something be deterministic if every outcome is realized?
    I honestly have no idea what you are talking about.
  • Can something be deterministic if every outcome is realized?
    Just a simple question, seemingly.Posty McPostface

    I don't understand the question.
  • Nothing is intrinsically morally wrong
    R. M. Hare, a non-cognitivist (non-objectivist) moral philosopher, recognized that there was a difference between expressions of emotion and moral utterances, between "I don't like liver" and "murder is wrong", and agreed that Emotivism is unable to account for the normative force of moral claims. He articulated the view, which became to be called Prescriptivism, that moral claims have an imperative, or prescriptive, element. To say that murder is wrong says both "I disapprove of murder" AND "Do thou likewise!"Mitchell

    I agree, moral attitudes seem to be prescriptive: they are aimed at compelling or constraining actions, which other attitudes such as pleasure, disgust, sadness, gratitude, fear, tenderness, etc. do not do in and of themselves. And they tend to have a more-or-less general character: not just do that in this particular instance, but whenever anyone finds themselves in similar circumstances, they ought to do something like that. So an argument can be made that moral attitudes can be grouped into a natural kind distinct from other attitudes (although the boundary is going to be somewhat fuzzy).

    But that is a modest, commonsensical conclusion of conceptual analysis: it only assures us that the predicate "moral" is meaningful and expressive. It doesn't tell us much about the metaphysics of morality.
  • Nothing is intrinsically morally wrong
    After all, morality certainly seems to appear to us as "objective", as a command-from-afar, an imperative, something we must do out of free will.darthbarracuda

    What you describe sounds like morality simpliciter. What is particularly "objective" about it? Or, to put it another way, what would a non-objective morality be like in your view?
  • Nothing is intrinsically morally wrong
    Regarding Emotivism, which is being expressed by some of these responses, there seems to me to be a crucial difference between "I don't like liver" or "Boo, Liver!", on the one hand, and "Torturing children for fun is wrong", on the other.Mitchell

    Of course there is a difference. There is even a difference between "I don't like liver" and "I don't like Brussels sprouts." But, assuming emotivism for the sake of an argument, what is "crucial" about this difference, other than the strength of the emotion?

    That is not a rhetorical question, but an invitation to elaborate the point. "Emotion" is one word, but that doesn't mean that all emotions are of the same sort. Is there a difference here that cannot be accommodated under some ordinary idea of emotion?
  • The problem with the concept of pseudoscience
    Science is a social endeavor. There are universities and research centers that produce research. There are scientific journals and book publishers that publish research. There are conferences that organize meetings and presentations. There are governmental and non-governmental agencies that distribute funds and commission and stimulate research programmes. There are educational institutions that teach science fundamentals, and government institutions that issue educational guidelines and select textbooks. There are entrepreneurs and corporate R&D departments that turn research into practical applications.

    All of these institutions, each in their own capacity, are engaged in evaluating science, one way or another. At the most basic level, that comes down to the question: Is it even science? So it is no use to stamp your feet and rail against those who ask and answer that question, @darthbarracuda. They have to. And no, science, or "science," is not going away, and thank god for that.


    As for the demarcation criteria, in the real life they can be vague and messy, and vary depending on who is asking the question. But I think that what is known as "falsifiability" does get at some important, though fairly obvious, idea. It is inherent in the very notion of empirical knowledge. In order to qualify as such, empirical knowledge has to be sensitive to observations. And the more sensitive it is, the more engaged it is with empirical observations - the more relevant it is.

    Popper was not the first to realize this, nor the last. He was just one of the philosophers of science and epistemologists who were trying to formalize this empiricist intuition and incorporate it into his own theory. In the end, it seems, his theory didn't prove to be all that influential (most of those who name-drop Popper know very little of it), but he did succeed in popularizing some terms and basic notions.
  • Level III Multiverse again.
    How can anybody assert that the state of some event outside our sphere 'is' in any particular state? Our definition sort of assumes a measurement taken from 'here', and by that definition, those distant events have no measurement and are in complete superposition.noAxioms

    Superposition states are states too (they are also called "mixed" states, as opposed to "pure" states). But I think I get your point: if we haven't been in contact with some remote region of the universe, then within that interval of time its wavefunction has been evolving independently from us, and there is no coherence between us and any one of its branches.
  • Level III Multiverse again.
    In an infinite universe, aren't we almost surely guaranteed a world where our doppelgangers walk through walls (the molecules align just right) after saying an incantation? Maybe doppleganger Jesus really did take a stroll on the water.Marchesk

    Yes, I think Vilenkin entertains similar fun scenarios, but frankly, not having followed the derivations, I am a little hesitant to commit to such specific predictions.
  • Level III Multiverse again.
    The case of a simple bound system, such as a hydrogen atom, is easier to analyze than a more general case: we can actually solve the quantum equations and enumerate every possible state. There is, however, a theorem for the general case in quantum mechanics, which puts a limit on the number of possible states, or degrees of freedom, given a volume and energy density within that volume.

    The general point that I wanted to make is that if there are separate systems with a finite number of possible states between them, then for them to be found in the same state at some moment, they do not have to have identical histories up to that moment. Even in a purely deterministic universe, as these systems transition from one state to another, they may end up in the same state at some point simply by chance. What that chance is - high, low, "almost surely" - will depend on a more detailed analysis.
  • Level III Multiverse again.
    I skimmed that article you linked and was interested to note that Vilenkin makes statements like:

    "there are an infinite number of O-regions with identical histories up to the present"

    where I think what he means is "there is almost surely an infinite number of .....". That is, I think he over-simplified his statement, presumably because he wanted to make it more accessible to the non-physicist reader, since it is a non-technical article.

    I note that in your post you included the crucial qualifier "almost certainly", although it does not occur in the paper. Interestingly, Tegmark also omits the qualifier (bottom of first column on page 4 of this article you linked) but, like Vilenkin, gives no explanation for the omission, and his article is also more pop science than academic.

    Do you have a view on why they omitted the 'almost certain' qualifier from their articles?
    andrewk

    Well, I cannot answer for Vilenkin or Tegmark, but I think they were speaking informally.

    How we interpret these results depends on how we think about probability. If we interpret probability as a quantitative measure of credence, or degree of belief, then there isn't really a difference between "almost surely" and "surely": in either case, the credence is exactly zero. This failure to make a distinction between possibility and impossibility may be a deficiency of the epistemic interpretation of probability (not to mention the problems of formal probabilistic modeling that have been raised here).

    But if we further think about our concepts of probability and possibility, this might be argued to be a distinction without a difference. We can hardly tell the difference in credence between an event that has a probability of 10-10 in a single trial and one with a probability 10-100. We stop making a difference long before "almost surely".

    There is still a possible/impossible distinction though. But is there, really? If "an event A is impossible" means for you that you should live your life as though A will never happen, then events with an extremely low probability are as good as impossible. You live your life assuming that the air will not suddenly evacuate the room through the window, leaving you choking on the floor, even though science says that such an event is possible (and even has a well-defined, finite probability!)
  • Level III Multiverse again.
    Let's bring down the scale to a manageable size to explore this concept. Instead of Earth, let's consider one hydrogen atom. Now, an atom has a finite number of configurations, or states that it can possibly be in (10 for hydrogen, I think). Since there are obviously a lot more hydrogen atoms than that, there have to be a lot of atoms that are absolutely identical, regardless of their prior histories.

    You can see how this can be scaled up by adding more atoms and particles to the system: they each have some finite number of states, and so do their combinations, even allowing for interactions. The number of degrees of freedom rises dramatically as you expand outwards, but the principle remains the same.

    I won't vouch that the math actually works out for macroscopic systems, i.e. that the number of possible states increases slower than the size of the system, but that is the argument that Vilenkin and some others make.