That's exactly the point I'm making. I'm not saying that our beliefs can either be justified or not (that's an entire epistemological position) I'm disputing that there is any good grounds for specify that science cannot justify the passions, as if there were some other group of things that it could justify. If there's nothing that science can justify (in that way) then the comment is entirely specious, claiming to provide some in formation about 'the passions', when in fact it is merely reporting the limits of science in general. — Pseudonym
This rather presumes a position on conciousness which is far from agreed upon. — Pseudonym
'Hungry' would be typically held as being that disposition which (in the absence of competing forces) would cause a person to eat. It is perfectly possible that your brain could be in that state, but the part of your brain responsible for generating the epiphenomenon of concious awareness erroneously reports that you are not. In that sense you would be incorrect about your assertion 'I'm hungry'. — Pseudonym
Does this mean that you believe free will to be incompatible with determinism? Would you then say that our sense of free will is an illusion? — Perplexed
Reductive explanation is a reason to believe. It is the standard reason we believe in everything else, that we have a reductive explanation for its being the case.
The comment I was disputing was "he is simply saying that the reasoning of science cannot justify them, [the passions]".
My argument was, in what way can the reasoning of science "justify" anything other than by explaining the causal chain of its existence back a few steps? — Pseudonym
I have a passion 'hunger', science can explain exactly what that passion is in physical terms (brain states), why it is there causally (DNA - protein synthesis - neurons development - interaction with the environment), and also why it is there teleologically (evolutionary function of hunger). What additional thing can science provide with regards to the proposition "the sky is blue" that is missing from what science can tell us about passions such as to warrant the distinction made? — Pseudonym
If one could show that the properties as enumerated in premise one are not the properties of intelligent design, then those who argue against the argument to intelligent design may have a point. However, the analogy is perfect. In fact it's hard to imagine a better analogy. — Sam26
I'd set forth that what a designed entity does is fulfill some purpose that, in this case, an intelligent being wants to be fulfilled (hence why I'm bringing up desire before, but here I'm introducing purpose as well). — Moliere
It seems to me that we need some notion of, first, a being who wants, and second, a purpose which fulfills that want. — Moliere
The point is that when we look at human productions that exhibit the features named in premise one, they are the result of intelligent design. In fact, even if you had never seen a watch before (Paley's argument), and stumbled upon one, you surely wouldn't conclude it happened by chance. Why? Because we are very familiar with the evidence of intelligent design. — Sam26
(I'm always using too many comma's...) — Moliere
Objects of nature have a structure where the parts are so arranged that the whole can achieve or be used to achieve activities of a higher order than any part alone — Sam26
I'd contend that objects of nature, like a tree or a cat, do not have a structure where the parts are so arranged that the whole can achieve or be used to achieve a higher order than the parts alone. Or, really to put it better and keep our positions linguistically distinct, I think I'd add more to this definition of intelligent design than what you've laid out here. — Moliere
The amount of instances that form the basis is extremely weak, so much so as to be completely damning to the analogy. Human artefacts represent a tiny proportion of all things in set A. There is an estimated 300 trillion tonnes of human artefacts in the world. There are an estimated five million trillion trillion bacteria. Even if we average human artefacts at just 1g, bacteria alone outnumber human artefacts by five trillion trillion times. All the failed organisms from the process of evolution outnumber human artefacts. by several trillion times more than this. It is ludicrous to suggest that anything about human artefacts tells us something about natural objects by strength of analogy. It would be like claiming you knew something with great certainty about all architecture because you studied one brick. — Pseudonym
First, if I was to put forth the argument it would take the following inductive form: — Sam26
By higher order, I mean that when parts are put together they achieve a higher order than any part alone. — Sam26
On the other hand, if those who don't believe in intelligent design aren't committing the fallacy of the self-sealing argument, answer the following: What would count as evidence of intelligent design? — Sam26
In other words, I am suggesting that to follow a rule of induction is no different to following any other rule; it is a normative principle pertaining to language-games, but not in any way that is significant to metaphysics or epistemology. — sime
No one denies that we do think - and behave - inductively (except maybe Popperians). — SophistiCat
Umm, no. Popperians wouldn't claim so either: — Ying
Sorry, i meant warrant being epistemologically vacuous. — sime
The action taken was telling McGahn to have Mueller fired. What exactly would it take for you to accept it as an action/order? Must Trump personally hand deliver a notice of termination? — Michael
Doesn't the difference entirely rest upon the normative and hence subjective context by which we judge behaviour to be future-anticipating? — sime
If a man's beliefs are identified with his non-verbal behaviour — sime
(1) God exists as a matter of necessity,
or
(2) It is at least logically coherent to think of God as a necessary being.
You say that (1) obviously entails the desired conclusion, but as you point out, it is worthless because (1) just is the conclusion. So we have to understand the premise as (2). I am not sure what would be wrong with (2). You have said it is too weak, but I'm not sure why. — PossibleAaran
(2*) The concept of a being that necessarily exists is logically coherent.
(4) Therefore, it is logically possible that there is a being that necessarily exists.
(5) Therefore, there is a being that necessarily exists.
The inference from (4) to (5) is just collapsing the modal operators in accord with S5. The inference from (2*) to (4) assumes that if a concept is logically coherent, it is logically possible that it is instantiated. — PossibleAaran
The starting premise is that it is logically possible that a maximally great being exists. If someone believes that a maximally great being does exist, then they surely also believe that it is logically possible. Now consider someone who doesn't already believe the conclusion. Such a person might believe that the concept of a maximally great being is coherent. I think many people who deny the existence of God do believe that the concept is at least coherent. But then, it could be pointed out to them that this premise, which they believe, entails that a maximally great being exists. Why wouldn't that be an effective argument? — PossibleAaran
All of this is quite uncharitable to Plantinga. — PossibleAaran
He does define his 'super-duper being' very carefully. He defines a maximally great being as one which is maximally excellent in every possible world, and maximal excellence is defined as entailing omnipotence, omniscience and moral perfection. To wit, the first two premises of his argument from the Nature of Necessity, page 214 — PossibleAaran
I think there's a fundamental problem with saying that a logical necessity is logically possible. I can't quite put my finger on what that problem is, though, but as I said before, my instinct is that it's related in kind to Tarski's hierarchy of language. — Michael
But then, suppose I don't have this bias. Suppose that I am not such that, when I see that a premise entails that God exists, I will not accept that premise. — PossibleAaran
You also say that it is illegitimate to predicate necessary existence. Why? You say that Michael's argument shows why. But which argument of Michael's do you mean? — PossibleAaran
Do you mean the argument that we can tack 'necessary existence' onto any concept and then create an argument for its existence, regardless of what the concept is? — PossibleAaran
Perhaps we could argue that the world is the necessary thing, as it seems tautological to say that the world exists in every possible world. — Michael
There are many versions of it, some intensely complicated. The OPs version is Anselmian, and those arguments typically run:
(1) If God exists then God necessarily exists. (G -> nG) [Partial Definition of God]
(2) If its logically possible that God exists then God exists (pG -> G) [From (1)]
(3) It is logically possible that God exists. (pG) [Premise]
(C) God exists (G) [From 1-3]. — PossibleAaran
Imagine a being, such that it cannot fail to exist.
Therefore, it exists. — SophistiCat
You see I don't think so. None of the premises of the argument say 'imagine a being such that it cannot fail to exist'. — PossibleAaran
But necessary existence is a property, and is immune to the criticism which Kant makes. — PossibleAaran
The 'argument' may as well read:
There exists a being, such that, it exists.
Therefore, it exists. — StreetlightX
I don't understand what's the issue either. Maybe let me restate the question. Does determinism apply to a situation where all outcomes can and are realized? — Posty McPostface
Just a simple question, seemingly. — Posty McPostface
R. M. Hare, a non-cognitivist (non-objectivist) moral philosopher, recognized that there was a difference between expressions of emotion and moral utterances, between "I don't like liver" and "murder is wrong", and agreed that Emotivism is unable to account for the normative force of moral claims. He articulated the view, which became to be called Prescriptivism, that moral claims have an imperative, or prescriptive, element. To say that murder is wrong says both "I disapprove of murder" AND "Do thou likewise!" — Mitchell
After all, morality certainly seems to appear to us as "objective", as a command-from-afar, an imperative, something we must do out of free will. — darthbarracuda
Regarding Emotivism, which is being expressed by some of these responses, there seems to me to be a crucial difference between "I don't like liver" or "Boo, Liver!", on the one hand, and "Torturing children for fun is wrong", on the other. — Mitchell
How can anybody assert that the state of some event outside our sphere 'is' in any particular state? Our definition sort of assumes a measurement taken from 'here', and by that definition, those distant events have no measurement and are in complete superposition. — noAxioms
In an infinite universe, aren't we almost surely guaranteed a world where our doppelgangers walk through walls (the molecules align just right) after saying an incantation? Maybe doppleganger Jesus really did take a stroll on the water. — Marchesk
I skimmed that article you linked and was interested to note that Vilenkin makes statements like:
"there are an infinite number of O-regions with identical histories up to the present"
where I think what he means is "there is almost surely an infinite number of .....". That is, I think he over-simplified his statement, presumably because he wanted to make it more accessible to the non-physicist reader, since it is a non-technical article.
I note that in your post you included the crucial qualifier "almost certainly", although it does not occur in the paper. Interestingly, Tegmark also omits the qualifier (bottom of first column on page 4 of this article you linked) but, like Vilenkin, gives no explanation for the omission, and his article is also more pop science than academic.
Do you have a view on why they omitted the 'almost certain' qualifier from their articles? — andrewk