• Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    Has a decision been reached on what we are to read? I hate when I read the wrong thing because I was only half way paying attention.Hanover

    The reading for February was Pattern and Being by John Haugeland, but the conversation hasn't quite left the ground yet.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Apply the logic to English, where English is both mentioned and used. If "horses" and "equine animals" are synonymous then "horses are equine animals" is true. If "horses are equine animals" is true then horses are equine animals. Therefore if "horses" and "equine animals" are synonymous then horses are equine animals.Michael

    Your conditional seems to run the wrong way. It is because we know that (and only as long as we know that) horses are equine animals (assuming "are" here signifies necessary identity of extension) that the expressions designating them are synonymous. It's not the other way around. If an expression is introduced in the language as synonymous to another expression that already has a referent, then one will be able to use both expressions to make (trivial) identity claims. That's because this specific way of introducing the new word into the language (as synonymous to another one) insures that it has the same Fregean sense as the old one. But, generally, if two words that are in fact co-referential have different Fregean senses, then the fact that they are indeed co-referential is something that might need to be verified empirically; and this will not ensure synonymy unless the knowledge of the identity becomes widespread in the linguistic community and this knowledge would also be taken to be a criterion for understanding both expressions.

    Now inject some Wittgenstein. If we use the words "horses" and "equine animals" in the same way then "horses" and "equine animals" are synonymous. Therefore if we use the words "horses" and "equine animals" in the same way then horses are equine animals.

    If you mean "using in the same way" to imply that referents are identical then in order to know that "horse" and "equine animals" are indeed used in the same way by us, in the case where we already know how to use them, would require that we check that any horse necessarily is an equine animal and vice versa.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    The "this sentence" is a recursive reference.Michael

    OK. You don't mean "recursive". You mean "self-referential". In that case, sure, if the sentence is allowed to claim of itself that it is to be understood in accordance with the linguistic stipulations stated in the antecedent, then, it is true. But it is then equivalent to the following:

    (1) If "horses" and "rabbits" are synonymous in some language (that has the same syntax and verbs as English), then, in that language, "horses are rabbits" expresses a true claim.

    If you would always say it that way that wouldn't invite any equivocation. But I am usure what philosophical lesson could be drawn from this trivial claim.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    You need to read it like this:

    Given that "horse" means "rabbit" in this language, horses are rabbits.
    Michael

    The above statement may be true as written in 'this language', but it is false as written in English.

    Compare:

    (1) Given that Germans put verbs at the end of their sentences, they sausages eat.

    This is nonsense because stating a convention that applies to another language in the antecedent of a conditional doesn't entitle you to switch language mid-sentence.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    I have repeatedly said that the conclusion is to be understood as speaking New English, where "horse" means "rabbit", and have repeatedly said that The Great Whatever's criticism rests on the very same equivocation which you mention - as he interprets the conclusion in English proper.Michael

    Even with the provision of this explicit disclaimer, as I explained, the counterfactual conditional statement still is nonsense since the truth of the consequent (even understood in New English) is unconditional. But what you mean to say is that it is conditional on the truth of the antecedent.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    And the schema works for the New English language, where "horse" means "rabbit", since both the antecedent and the consequent are true in all circumstances. Your interpretation of the sentence in English proper is a misinterpretation.Michael

    Yes, it would work in New English as used by New English speakers. But then you have to specify in advance that, when you are stating such a shema, you are meant to be understood as speaking New English. Else you are inviting equivocation. When you say something like 'If "horse" meant the same thing as "rabbit" then rabbits would be horses' this is still nonsense in English and equally nonsense in New English since, while the consequent might be true as expressed in that language, it doesn't depend on the truth of the antecedent. From the point of view of speakers of New English, the thought expressed by them when they use the sentence "rabbits are horses" is true quite independently of any linguistic convention.

    As I had suggested, properly interpreted (as Tarski meant it to be interpreted as a theorem in a recursive truth theory for a formal language), the biconditional:

    (1) "Horses are rabbits" is true iff horses are rabbits

    would be true, but the counterfactual (subjunctive) conditional:

    (2) If "horse" meant the same as "rabbit" then horses would be rabbits

    would still be nonsense. In both cases the consequent is expressed in English. The antecedent of the subjunctive conditional claim doesn't tell you in what language the consequent must be read. It rather tell you relative to which counterfactual circumstances the claim expressed (in English) in the consequent ought to be evaluated.
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    Do you know where he explains his change?Michael

    Renewing Philosophy, HUP, 1995, and The Threefold Chord, Columbia UP, 2001 provide useful statements of his mature philosophy.

    The book Hilary Putnam, Cambridge UP, 2005, by Yemima Ben-Menahem also likely is useful but, although I own it, I haven't read it yet.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Then I still don't understand why you think that the T-schema should baffle me.Michael

    That's because the way you are reading it, as applied to the description of counterfactual linguistic stipulations (e.g. a hypothetical language as used in counterfactual circumstances) has an incidence on the meaning of the terms used on the right hand side. Hence you have a habit of saying such things as 'If "rabbits" meant "horses" then rabbits would be horses'. And you invoke Tarski's T-shema as a support for the intelligibility of this use. But the disquotational shema doesn't warrant such a use. What it warrants may be the shema:

    (1) "Rabbits are horses" is true iff rabbits are horses

    This homophonic shema works for the English language since both the antecedent and the consequent are false in all circumstances. But it doesn't warrant your counterfactual conditional claim.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    I may have misunderstood you, but were you saying that the T-schema only works if the sentence used on the right-hand side says something true about the actual world?Michael

    They state truth conditions -- i.e. in what conditions the sentence mentioned on the left hand side is true. The sentence used on the right hand side may state something that is always false (i.e. in all circumstances). In that case the sentence mentioned on the left hand side would be false in all circumstances also. The stipulation of the truth conditions, on the right hand side, just are the stipulations of the conditions under which the sentence mentioned on the left-hand side would be true as interpreted in the object-language.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    You said that the truth of the sentence used on the right-hand side is determined by facts about the extra-linguistic world and not by whatever definitions were stipulated on the left-hand side.Michael

    This is confused because the sentence mentioned on the left-hand side of the T-shema doesn't stipulate anything. Rather the whole T-shema expresses one specific consequence of a Tarskian truth theory for the object-language. The meanings of the words used on the right-hand side of the shemas are the meanings that they have in the meta-language used by the theorist in order to state the consequences of the theory. Those meanings are presupposed in the act of stating the theory. Hence they can't be affected by the stipulations expressed by the T-shemas.

    So even if the words "horse" and "rabbit" mentioned on the left-hand side mean what they do now, the sentence used on the right-hand is true iff horses are equine animals, and as horses are equine animals then the sentence used on the right-hand side is true. And if it's true then the sentence mentioned on the left-hand side is also true.

    I am unsure what you are trying to say. If the words ""horse" and "rabbit" mentioned on the left-hand side mean what they do now, then your T-shema would express incorrect truth conditions for sentences written (or spoken) in the English language. That's because the antecedent would be false in circumstances while the consequent is true (i.e. the actual circumstances where horses indeed are equine animals, but horses aren't rabbits).
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Doesn't this then entail that the below is correct?

    "Horses are rabbits" is true iff horses are equine animals
    Michael

    This might be true in relation to some language where "rabbits" is used to refer to what we are referring to, in English, with the phrase "equine animals". But I don't see your point. Horses still are equine animals whatever linguistic stipulations might be in use in this or whatever alternative linguistic community.
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    David L. Anderson - What is Realistic about Putnam's Internal Realism?Michael

    I wouldn't mind discussing that. But it's worth noting that Putnam has, meanwhile, distanced himself significantly from his earlier accounts of "internal realism" -- enough so to even repudiate the label. He has rather come to endorse a form of pragmatism, though of a different form than the social institutional pragmatism endorsed by Rorty and Brandom.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Why ought it be baffling to me?Michael

    That's because in the second shema -- (2) -- the sentence mentioned on the left has no incidence whatsoever on the meaning of "cheveaux" and "animaux equestres" as they are being used in the meta-language. But this is true also for the case of the first shema -- (1). It is, on the contrary, the independently understood meanings of the words used on the right hand side that are being relied on order to specify or define the meanings of the words of the object-language that are being mentioned (and not used) on the left hand side of the shema.

    The main point is that the truth conditions expressed by the sentences being used on the right-hand side of both shemas only depend on what is the case in the world (i.e. the extra-linguistic world) regarding horses and equine animals, and don't depend on any kind of linguistic stipulation embodied in the truth theory which the T-shema is a theorem of.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    The shema that Michael is making use of is the the T-shema used by Tarski to give a recursive definition of the predicate "... is true" for a given formal language. What figures on the right of the shema is a sentence expressed (i.e. used) in a meta-language independently understood by the theorist who understands, or stipulates, the meanings of the terms used in the formal language according to some specific semantic interpretation or model.

    In the context of such a theory, it may be correct to say, for instance, that:

    (1) "Horses are equine animals" is true iff horses are equine animals

    According to the very same semantic model for the modern English language, one could translate this shema in French thus:

    (2) "Horses are equine animals" est vrai ssi les chevaux sont des animaux équestres.

    The same object language is the topic -- English -- but the meta-language has been switched to French. Yet the shema says exactly the same thing. This ought to be clear to TGW (and to Tarski and Wittgenstein), but it ought to be baffling to Michael, it seems to me.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Michael,

    It seems to me everybody in this thread, including you, agree on 90% of the basic underlying assumptions regarding the conventional element in meaning attributions to words of language. Much of the difficulty comes from your using "is" as a word that signals an implicit stipulation about linguistic meaning (i.e. a copula, as in A is the referent of "B") rather than identity.

    For instance, you take the two following sentence to mean the same thing:

    (1) If "horse" was used to refer to rabbits, then rabbits would be properly called "horses"
    (2) If "horse" was used to refer to rabbits, then rabbits would be horses.

    The trouble is that you alone are interpreting the meaning of the consequent in the second counterfactual conditional (i.e. "rabbits would be horses") to be interpreted according to the use that is stipulated in the antecedent (i.e. '"horse" was used to refer to rabbits'). The trouble is that everybody else in this thread understand (correctly, in my view) the words "rabbits" and "horses" to have their ordinary (actual) meanings as used in the consequent of (2), and the phrase "would be" to signify identity rather than meaning stipulation. There indeed can't be any meaning stipulation there since there is no mention of the words "rabbits" or "horses".

    Rather, in the consequent: "then rabbits would be horses", all the words are being used. And your interpretation of them as being used in accordance with the stipulation that figures in the antecedent of the counterfactual conditional makes nonsense of most ordinary counterfactual conditional statements.

    So, almost all of the disagreement in this thread stems from your using the verb "to be", and your interpreting the consequent clauses in counterfactual statements, in non-standard ways. So, you are right that many of your claims are being misinterpreted, but you have some responsibility for that, and you equally often misinterpret their claims for the very same reasons.
  • Re: that other place ...
    I think C. S. Lewis wrote a story in which hell was a rather dreary, dark, dusty city absent of any feeling. No warmly lit windows, no laughter, no greetings. Silence.Bitter Crank

    This rather reminds me of the end of the movie The Beyond, directed by Lucio Fulci. This film is rather cheesy and often ridiculous, though a cult classic; but its depiction of hell as a rather tranquil and cold place is the most gloomy and blood curdling one that I have seen in cinema.
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    (Continued from my previous post)

    Sellars wasn't alone in defending such a notion of synthetic a priori truths that aren't pure, in the Kantian sense, but rather must be relativized to specific conceptual schemes. Peter Strawson and Paul Grice, responding to Quine, in their In Defence of a Dogma, also defended the idea of synthetic a priori statements that are distinguished from other empirical judgments about particulars by making explicit necessary conceptual connections between the concepts used to make such judgments.

    (At this early stage of the debate, and some 25 years before Kripke's Naming and Necessity was published, the analytic/synthetic distinction wasn't neatly demarcated from the necessary/contingent and a priori/a posteriori distinctions; and, indeed, Kripke's demarcations may have obscured some connections between those allegedly purely logical, modal and epistemological distinctions. But this would be a topic for another thread).

    Wittgenstein's "grammatical remarks" also can be construed as the expression of synthetic a priori truths, in this sense. On that view, logical grammar, as opposed to deductive logic (first order predicate logic) aims at making explicit conceptual truths that are tacitly understood by language users, and compliance with which is exhibited in their practice, while also manifesting their understandings of the objects and concepts talked about.

    This brings us back to Haugeland's claim about the constitutive inter-dependence between two levels of objective patterns. Inasmuch as patterns at both levels can be disclosed by means of empirical inquiry, they both are, indeed empirical. Patterns at the higher level, though, concern norms, laws and regularities. They are what Haugeland calls constitutive standards. Objects (i.e. patterns at the "lower level") can't be identified, or indeed, thought about, independently from the constitutive standards that they are subsumed under. One can't identify, or make sense of, a bishop, in the game of chess, that wouldn't be properly moved along diagonals on the chess board. Likewise, one can't identify, or make sense of an object's having a determinate mass that wouldn't weigh anything in the Earth gravitational field and/or wouldn't accelerate when subjected to a net force in accordance with Newton's second law.

    Yet, it is one thing to recognize a chess piece to be a bishop, in a particular case, and another to acknowledge that, as such, it must move along diagonals (i.e. to acknowledge a constitutive rule of chess). Likewise, it is one thing to recognize that an object has a mass of one kilogram and another to recognize (or insist) that it must obey Newton's third law in all circumstances. The latter sort of necessary truths, expressed by synthetic a priori statements relativized to specific empirical domains, make up sets of constitutive standards for the domain. They collectively express an understanding of the objects that belong to this domain. Having such an (at least rudimentary) understanding is a requirement for those objects to be recognizable as what they are.

    We may say, following both Haugeland (in Truth and Rule Following) and Sellars (in Concepts as Involving Laws) that understanding an empirical domain consists in having an (at least) tacit grasp of its constitutive standards. This understanding can be made explicit, and expressed with the use of synthetic a priori statements. Those statements are a priori because the objects that belong to the domain can't exist without obeying the standards. In fact, their obeying the constitutive standards (norms, laws of nature, etc.) is the specific manner in which objects exist in their respective domains.

    This also brings us back to the distinction made by Kant, as quoted by Jamalrob in the beginning of my previous post, between knowledge that begins with experience and knowledge that arises from experience.

    Laws of Newtonian mechanics, or the rules of chess (to stick with those two simple examples) can't be discovered a priori (in an epistemological sense). They either must be disclosed empirically (in the first case) or stipulated (in the second case). Once this has been done, however, the synthetic a priori (in a metaphysical sense) statements that express them determine what must necessarily occur in experience. Synthetic a priori statements therefore determine the range of possible (intelligible) experiences within a given empirical domain. Synthetic a posteriori statements express the content of actual experiences -- that is, experiences of actually existing objects that have specific determinations.

    However, there can be no objective perception, and no objective judgment, when there is no prior understanding of what is possibly experienced (that is, what are possible and intelligible syntheses of various sensible determinations in a single object). Hence, knowledge of synthetic a priori truths begins with experience. This synthetic a priori knowledge makes possible objective judgments about actual objects; judgments, that is, that arise from experiences (synthetic a posteriori judgments).

    Those two levels of empirical inquiry correspond to the two levels of co-constituted patterns discussed by Haugeland in Pattern and Being. The super-ordinate level of laws and/or norms is discernible as a set of consistent patterns that emerges from a wide and systematic range of experiences (experimentations, we may rather say), which delimits possible further experiences, while the sub-ordinate level is populated with patterns of unified determinations that make up the actual objects that figure in experience and that accord with the laws disclosed at the higher level. They are the two levels of understanding (meaningful thoughts) and knowledge (contentful thoughts), that can only be actualized jointly.
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    Can there be true and meaningful synthetic a priori statements?

    Haugeland's view about objective perception illuminates this question, I think. There was an interesting thread three months ago about Kant's Prolegomena To Any Future Metaphysics. Let me quote this paragraph from Jamalrob:

    A few words about a priori and a posteriori. These are about justification, i.e., how we come to know things, so they are epistemological concepts. In the CPR Kant says that “There can be no doubt that all knowledge begins with experience”, but that “although our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it arises from experience.” What this means is that it is experience that calls forth knowledge, not that it is the source. For example, it is in experience that we come to know about cause and effect in the first place, but only because events must be experienced in terms of a prior, independent (pure) concept of the understanding.jamalrob

    This distinction between two ways in which knowledge relates to experience, here marked with the phrases "begins with" and "arises from" is interesting but puzzling. It seems clear that the first way for knowledge to relate to experience ("i.e. "begins with") characterizes this form of knowledge (expressible with synthetic a priori statements) as a condition for the very possibility of empirical (i.e. a posteriori) knowledge, and hence for meaningful and contentful "intuitions". Once the conditions for the possibility of such experiences are satisfied, then it is empirical knowledge of particular facts (and particular objects) that can "arise from" experience. This empirical knowledge is expressed with synthetic a posteriori statements.

    The sorts of synthetic a priori statements that were centrally at issue, in the passages from the Critique or Pure Reason quoted by Jamalrob above, were statements that express the content of the pure concepts of the understanding, that is, the Kantian categories. Those are a priori concepts that purport to represent the form thought has in virtue of the fact that it relates essentially to intuition while abstracting from the specific empirical contents those intuitions provide. Whatever one might think of the feasibility of such an inquiry into the form of the pure understanding -- and for a masterful defense and realization, one can refer to Sebastian Rödl's Categories of the Temporal: An Inquiry into the Forms of the Finite Intellect, HUP, 2012 -- it may still sound incredible that there might be synthetic a priori statements that aren't pure in this sense, and that therefore express genuine knowledge about the empirical world, or, more precisely, about determinate domains of empirical objects.

    Yet that is exactly what Haugeland's account of objectivity enables us to better understand. Wilfrid Sellars -- whose Concepts as Involving Laws and Inconceivable Without Them gets credited by Haugeland as anticipatory of some of his own ideas (further developed in his Truth and Rule Following) -- also defended a broader conception of (inpure) synthetic a priori truths.

    Here is a quote from Willem A. DeVries' book on Sellars:

    "Sellars believes that any conceptual framework, necessarily, includes valid forms of material inferences. But synthetic a priori truths are framework relative; there is no set of framework-independent synthetic a priori truths. The structure of our conceptual framework, which is responsible for our a priori knowledge and which we often take to reflect articulation of reality itself, is in fact mind-dependent to a significant degree."

    The denial of framework independent synthetic a priori truths is the denial of what Kant argues for, and Rödl seconds, but this isn't my concern here. What is rather interesting, for my present purpose, is the assimilation of framework dependent synthetic a priori truths with the expressions of valid forms of material inferences.

    Valid forms of material inferences are inferences that are warranted by the conceptual content of terms involved in the premises and conclusion, rather than being warranted by the (deductive) logical form of those statements alone. Hence, for instance, the truth that

    (A) Montreal is north of New York City

    can be validly (materially) inferred from the truth that

    (B) New York City is south of Montreal.

    This inference is materially rather than deductively valid. The inference is valid in virtue of a form of inference that can be made explicit with the use of the synthetic a priori statement:

    (M) "X is south of Y if and only if Y is north of X".

    This synthetic a priori statement is partially constitutive of the meanings (i.e. the conceptual contents) of the relational predicates "... is south of..." and "... is north of...". It may be worth noticing, also, that when this synthetic a priori statement is furnished as an additional premise, then one can logically (i.e. deductively) infer (B) from (A) and (M).

    To be continued in my next post...
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Before language, there were animals who experienced and felt. That's what's fundamental. Language is late in the game. Symbols are parasitic.Marchesk

    Indeed. Michael earlier remarked that we teach children how to respond appropriately to linguistic inputs. He meant to analogize this with the action of programming a computer. But your remark here illustrates why this analogy is misleading.

    Before children come to master appropriate rules of grammar and grasp semantical world-word connections, they already have desires, sensations, yearnings, bodily skills and social relationships. Proper linguistic performance isn't taught to them by means of explicit instructions; the teaching of language rather consists in a further re-shaping of an already actualized embodied form of life. This immature (i.e. pre-linguistic) form of human behavior sustains the ascription of meaningful (albeit merely proto-conceptual) mental states. The mode of teaching is broadly proleptical (anticipative) rather than explicit. That is, there is no need to assume that the child understands what it is shown to him/her that s/he ought to do and say in response to determinate circumstances or verbal instructions. The child's (proto-)linguistic behavior is shaped holistically in a way that sustains intentional ascriptions to him/her of determinate (conceptual) thought contents only very approximately at first, and then, gradually, more determinately, as the meanings of the terms that he/she uses progressively dawn of him/her (as a constitutive result of his/her ability to use them properly in wider ranges of circumstances).
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Second, simply because we do not relate to a computer as well as we do to other humans doesn't mean a computer doesn't feel. The recent movie Ex Machina explores this. To treat humans above computers simply because we don't have an emotional attachment to the latter is to have an anthropic bias.darthbarracuda

    One response to Searle's Chinese Room thought experiment is the system reply. Another one is the robot reply. Those two responses are quite different in character. That's because Searle's original contention was that however our brains "generate" understanding -- as they allegedly can, according to him -- can't be something that occurs in virtue of computation alone. All the system does still merely consists in manipulation of input symbol strings in accordance with syntactic rules. A robot does other things. It can actively gather data (not restricted to symbols provided to it) and behave in the world.

    It seems to me that Searle ought to be able to consistently accept that the robot can manifest understanding while still denying that its "brain" understands anything. Searle's rejoinder to the system reply still validly applies to claims that the robot's brain (i.e. its central controlling system) understands. Searle ought to grant that, if the robot manifests understanding of Chinese (and of its surroundings) in its public behavior, then this understanding may be enabled by its brain functions but isn't constituted by those functions.

    Of course Searle actually reject the robot reply. But that's because he is an internalist about intentional content. As I phrased it above, he believes that human brains "generate" understanding on their own quite appart from their embedding ("embeddedness"?) in animate bodies, and the embedding of our living bodies in our social and natural world. He defends a view of intrinsic intentionality according to which meaning and understanding (and reference) are produced by some irreducible and emergent property of biological brains -- irreducible, that is, to computations or syntactic manipulation of symbols. If we dispense with Searle's intentional internalism (i.e. the idea that mental states supervene narrowly on brain states, and depend only on them) then we ought to be happy to deny, with him, that computers understand anything. But we can also accept, unlike him, that sophisticated robots could conceivably understand, and yet deny, unlike him, that our own brains understand anything.
  • Martha the Symbol Transformer
    Seems to amount to symbol manipulation.Michael

    Yes, but does this competence with symbol manipulation constitute understanding? That you are able to manipulate the symbols in accordance with rules immediately shows, at most, that you understand the rules; that is, that you understand what it is permissible or mandatory for you to do in order to correctly apply them in particular cases. This, however, isn't the understanding that is at issue in the debate regarding functionalism, or computationalism, in the philosophy of mind.

    The understanding at issue rather is the understanding of the meaning of linguistic symbols (and hence also the understanding that grounds intentionality -- e.g. reference to extra linguistic items in the general case). Functionalists claim that competence in following the syntactic and/or logical (i.e inferential) rules that govern the use of the symbols is sufficient for constituting an understanding of their meanings. Searle disputes this. Hence, for him, an ability to "understanding" the rules (i.e. display an ability to comply with them) falls short from understanding the language.
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    Well, I think this may be as muddled as I am but the muddle is about Haugeland's core principle: what is rationality when she's at home? Why does it have to be specified separately in thinking about patterning?mcdoodle

    If anything ought to be called Haugelans' core principle, in relation to the thesis defended in Pattern and Being, it seems to me that it might be the idea that recognizing objects in an empirical domain requires existential commitments directed simultaneously to those objects (i.e. sub-patterns) and to the normative standards that govern their behaviors (i.e. super-ordinate patterns) -- and this dual commitment both enables and presupposes an understanding of those objects. Surely, such an understanding of objects also presupposes that whoever understands them (and their empirical domain) is rational. But rationality as such isn't quite thematized as itself being the constitutive principle of objective perception. (Though such a more demanding thesis may be defended in the more explicitly developed neo-Kantian account of objective truth telling found in Haugeland's later Truth and Rule Following paper.

    Rather, in Pattern and Being, Haugeland merely invokes the specific constitutive standard of rationality, and the corresponding empirical domain disclosed by intentional state ascriptions to rational beings (i.e. to Dennett's "intentional systems"), as just one example among many potentially discloseable empirical domains of objects. Being able to recognize super-ordinate "patterns" of rationality in the behavior of "intentional systems", and being able to objectively ascribe to them beliefs, desires and intentions, etc., go hand in hand. The recognitions of the former (i.e. of the constitutive standards of rationality) and recognition of the latter (i.e. particular beliefs and desires ascribable to individuals, etc.) make up a unitary understanding of two levels of patterns that are co-constituted -- that is, such that each one of them can be intelligibly recognized to exist only in relations to the other. The level of objects (sub-patterns) isn't thus basic in relation to the super-ordinate level of constitutive standards (higher level patterns) governing them. Both levels are equally basic.

    It is a bit of a distraction that the only sort of entity that can understand an empirical domain of "intentional systems" itself must belong to such a domain and therefore be rational. Nevertheless, the subset of our "actions" that aren't fully, or not at all, "rational", and that may more closely resemble the instinctual, learned or conditioned behaviors of most of our animal relatives, also are phenomena that belong to a specific empirical domain (a proper object of study for ethology, perhaps) that would have its own constitutive standards, according to Haugeland, and those standard -- e.g. the demand that behaviors be seen as adaptive, make ecological sense, etc. -- will no doubt fall short from demanding the subsumption of those behaviors under demanding norms of rationality.
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    This is a followup to this post in which I was intending to show that laws** purportedly governing "things-in-themselves" are unintelligible, unlike the laws* that govern the objects ("patterns") that show up in empirical domains constituted by those laws* (i.e. normative standard) as they are potentially understood by us when we commit to them. The demonstration of this thesis, and the explanation of what it means, though, is a bit more difficult than I had anticipated. I had conjectured that the fundamental laws that govern Conway's Game of Life, which are the rules that determine from one 'time step' to the next one the state (on/off) of each individual pixels as a function of the states of the 8 neighboring pixels, would be unintelligible and unknowable to (eventual) intelligent 'inhabitants' of such a Life Plane. That conclusion likely is too strong and not quite what I needed in order to show (or, at least, suggest) that objects can't exist apart from the normative standards that we hold them answerable to.

    My initial idea was that if we were to run a computer simulation of such a 'world' (i.e. an artificial life simulation) then the temporal evolution of the simulation would be quite divorced from the 'time' 'experienced' by the simulated 'creatures' who 'inhabit' the simulated 'world'. That's because such an experienced 'time' is part of the content (or, more properly, the form) of their intentional states and those states are disclosed by our adopting an intentional stance towards their 'behaviors'. (I am using single-scare-quotes to refer to all the phenomena that are, from our own perspective, merely simulated and a matter of our interpretation of the regular features -- the patterns -- that emerge in our interpretation of the computer output).

    If we were to interrupt the simulation and resume it at a later time, then, this obviously would have no impact whatsoever on the 'experiences' of the simulated 'creatures'. This only shows, though, that our own experienced (and measured) time is divorced from the 'time' that marks the progress of the simulation (e.g. the discrete time steps in the Game of Life). It is only to the latter that the 'experiences' of the simulated 'creatures' are pegged. But this also highlights the fact that whatever those 'creatures' 'experience' (or 'think') doesn't even depend on our running the simulation at all. Destroying the computer doesn't destroy their 'world' any more than it would destroy the decimal development of the number Pi if this were what the computer was computing at the time when is was destroyed. Simulating a world just is exploring the features of a "logically possible world" (if that much) and falls short from creating one; or so I would be prepared to argue. From such considerations I had thought that I could easily infer that the simulated 'creatures' can't, by 'observational' and/or 'theoretical' means, or by any other means, discover the basic laws (i.e. the rules of the Game of Life) that govern the evolution of their 'world'. That's because those laws mirror the rules codified in the algorithm being executed by our computer, and this computer needn't even exist for their 'world' (and the 'objects' within it) to 'exist' for them.

    But this inference involves a confusion. What depends contingently on the existence of the computer, the laws that govern its functioning, and the norms determining that it is functioning correctly (i.e. that it is running the algorithm that we want it to run) just is the simulation process, not the 'world' being simulated. Hence, there isn't any reason a priori, so far as I can see, why the 'creatures' that 'inhabit' some 'world' (which we may or may not want to, or be able to, run a simulation of) wouldn't 'discover' its 'fundamental laws' irrespective of the laws that govern the simulation process. It is those latter laws that are unknowable to them. But, if the simulation is running correctly, then the computer algorithm just happens to mirror the 'laws' of their world -- something that whey could come to 'know' as their 'fundamental physics'. (What I mean for them to be 'discovering' such 'laws' just is that such formal laws would be (part of) the content of the intentional states that we would ascribe them (or to those among them who are 'physicists') if we were to adopt the intentional stance toward them in the context of a simulation of their 'world' -- and of their 'scientific activity'.

    My original question nevertheless remains, regarding the ontological status of the fundamental 'objects', the individual pixels in the Life Plane of Conway's Game of Life, from the pont of view of its 'inhabitants'. Assuming that they would correspond to theoretical entities knowable to potential 'inhabitants' of the Life World: are such 'objects' existing in themselves appart from the 'laws' governing them? (I conceive of them as simple objects that have the property of being either on or off, in addition to having relational topological and spatial properties) But I think what I originally intended to show can still be shown. It is only through adopting an intentional stance towards potential 'inhabitants' of the Life World that we have come to conceive of those pixels as objects at all, as opposed to them being uninterpreted symbols potentially churned out by a meaningless computer algorithm. Those 'objects' only have intelligible being qua theoretical entities that have some degree of explanatory value either for the of potential 'inhabitants' of the Life World, or, as re-identifiable patterns that are interesting to us (even in the case where no 'life' emerges in the Life World). Those objects, therefore, as Haugeland surmised, don't exist apart from the laws that govern them, and those laws only are intelligible as part of some set of constitutive standards that we (or Life World 'inhabitants') commit to when investigating them. The argument may not be quite complete yet, but I may have bitten more than I can easily chew.
  • Feature requests
    The interlining within the message paragraphs seem cramped to me. I am usure if this is related to paragraph style or the default font, but the interlining seems to be just a bit too narrow for confortable reading, and it is also unaesthetic to my eyes -- the text doesn't breathe. I am unsure if this can easily be fixed. It is a rather minor complaint, though. (I also notice that the interlining is fine in the edit box, though not in the preview window box, where it appears to be the same as in the posted messages.)
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    I've got an area I'd like to explore but will wait until Pierre-Normand has made his further case. Very rewarding essay to bounce off.mcdoodle

    Please go on! I'm rather busy at the moment but will try to complete my followup later today. My argument also is harder to articulate than it had seemed to me when I rehearsed the argument mentally. In any case, I don't mind this being a peripheral sub-thread.
  • Reading for Feburary: Pattern and Being (John Haugeland)
    Let me jump in right away and elaborate on a specific but rather central point Haugeland makes in Pattern and Being. To perceive an object in the world is to get hold of a "pattern", and such a pattern is objectively perceived inasmuch as it, together with other objects in the same empirical domain, is governed by constitutive standards (e.g. governing rules, norms, and/or enabling material/ecological/social conditions) in such a way that it (e.g. the purported object or phenomenon perceived) could conceivably fail to accord with some of those standards, and hence signal a case of misperception of the object, or misunderstanding of the purported empirical domain. Hence the objective perception of an object involves some degree of understanding of the laws (or norms) that objects of this sort obey (or are held up to, in the case of objects that belong to socially instituted domains and practices). And perceptual acts can't count as objective -- in the sense Haugeland seeks to explain -- unless the observer also has, at the very least, a tacit understanding of, and commitment to, the constitutive standards governing the empirical domain this object belongs to.

    One paradigmatic example of such an empirical domain is the domain of "intentional" (in Brentano's sense) mental "states" such as belief, desires and intentions. Ascribing such states to persons only is possible, and only makes sense, when effected against the background of a larger pattern of rational behaviors (including speech acts) that justifies a large set of broadly consistent such ascriptions. This constitutive standard of rationality can be assimilated to Davidson's constitutive ideal of rationality (making possible the "radical interpretation" of the linguistic performances of an individual), and to Dennett's insistance that the intentional stance towards intentional systems only can succeed trough treating such systems as suitably "rational".

    In this post (and the following one), I am going to take for granted Haugeland's accounts of objects, or "objecthood", and of the objectivity of judgment/perception. Other participants are free, of course, to question them. I rather want to explore an interesting consequence of Haugeland's thesis, defended in Pattern and Being, that objects can be identified with patterns that are objective (i.e. that are real objects, though not necessarily material "things") only inasmuch as they are constituted by standards governing broader empirical domains those objects are "sub-patterns" of. This thesis might by regarded as the ontological counterpart of the epistemological thesis of the theory-ladenness of experience/observation. There doesn't exist "raw data" of either sensory experience, or scientific observation, uncontaminated by theory and, likewise, there aren't any "raw objects", as it were, that would be the objects that they are quite appart from the "laws" governing them. The laws that govern the objects found in an empirical domain make up broad patterns -- patterns of conformity with coherent sets of constitutive standards -- within which alone those objets are, not only discernible by us, but can so much as exist as the sorts of objects that they are.

    I now come to the consequence of this thesis that I wanted to highlight. Conway's Game of Life, as well as the idea of a universe governed by universal laws, such that the "temporal-evolution" of such a universe could be simulated on a digital computer, suggests the possibility -- seemingly ruled out by Haugeland -- that the fundamental entities making up our universe have ontological primacy in the sense that they exist in themselves appart from the super-ordinate patterns that they make up, or (equivalently) appart from the laws (deterministic or not) that govern their interactions and "temporal" evolution. We can thus imagine that the "inhabitant/scientists" who might have evolved into, and "inhabit", a "universe" thus simulated could, by means of "observation" of the empirical phenomena that occur in their "world" (and that we can also discern in the printout or display of the computer simulation), together with suitable theorizing, come to disclose the "laws" that govern their own simulation. Those "laws" just would be the rules of the Game of Life, or of whatever set of fundamental physical laws govern the temporal-evolution of universe we have chosen to simulate and in which those "intelligent creatures" "evolved".

    This is just a thought experiment, and it may be the case that the laws of quantum field theory (or whatever fundamental physical theory can be held to subsumes them) preclude our own universe being simulated in any kind of digital computer imaginable, even with the provision of infinite resources. This will not affect my main point since I am merely using the thought experiment as a loose metaphor to highlight two distinct conceptions of natural laws. There are, first, laws* as Haugeland understands them, which fall under the generalized concept of constitutive standards of an empirical domain. Those laws can, indeed, be disclosed empirically and/or imposed conventionally, in the case of socially instituted domains such as the the domains of chess, or economic markets and currencies, etc.

    (Let me note, as my previous "and/or" suggests, that Haugeland doesn't hold to a dichotomy here between laws of nature and laws of men (or customs or whatever). It can be a matter of empirical discovery for a field anthropologist to find out that members of some foreign tribe are playing a game such as chess in an unfamiliar medium. Instituted domains also obey internal constraints, may have a higher degree of contingency than the domains of the natural sciences, but still be suitable objects of empirical, and objective, discovery. The patterns at issue may be natural patterns, social patterns, mathematical patterns, etc., though, maybe, the applicability of the idea of empirical discovery could be quibbled with in the third case.)

    And then let me come to a second conception of "laws", let me label them 'laws**', that describe patterns of subsumability such as the "rules" that govern the evolution of the "life plane" in Conway's Game of Life. This second conception of the "laws of nature" dovetails with "metaphysical realism" (as Hilary Punam uses the term critically in Representation and Reality), and with the idea that our world (or "universe") is as it is, at a fundamental level, and temporally evolves as it does (in accordance with laws**), independently of whatever our contingent interests might be. The common belief among physicists, possibly shared with some "realist" philosophers (though by all means not all, since Haugeland himself was an avowed realist), is that such "fundamental" laws**, just like Haugeland's own laws* (e.g. the constitutive standards of specific empirical domains) can be discovered empirically. I would like to question this. And indeed, I would like to suggest that, inasmuch as laws** can't be disclosed empirically at all (as I purport to show), and can't make any difference to the nature and structure of our experiences, they are unintelligible.

    I'll make my case, which I take to be continuous with Haugeland's thinking, in a followup to this post.
  • Reading for Feburary: Poll
    Note to readers of Haugeland's Pattern and Being:

    Haugeland discusses briefly Conway's Game of Life, which had been used by Dennett to illustrate patterns, their recognition, and ontological status. There is a nice wikipedia page on Conway's Game of Life, and one can easily find online simulators just in case some readers aren't familiar with it.
  • Reading for December: Concepts and Objects (Ray Brassier)
    before homo sapiens, via radiocarbonmcdoodle

    I hope you don't mind an inconsequential quibble, but radiocarbon dating relies on carbon-14, which has a rather short half-live (5,730 years), and isn't reliable past 62,000 years. A variety of other isotopes enable radiometric dating all the way back (with ever coarser resolutions) to several billion years in the past.
  • Reading for December: Concepts and Objects (Ray Brassier)
    Hi csalisbuty,

    Thanks for raising up the problem of ancestrality. I wasn't acquainted with it -- at least not under this guise. I gave it some thought and still need to give it some more. Incidentally, I had likened your 'lol-planet' concept to Goodman's 'grue' concept. Maybe a closer analogue would be Dennett's lost sock center!
  • Reading for December: Concepts and Objects (Ray Brassier)
    You are missing that, in that instance, the statue is named. You began by pointing at a statue. The object you were thinking of has been there all along. Similarity, Brassier begins by talking about Saturn. What object someone is pointing at is always, assuming a coherent claim about the world is made, given in talking about some state of the world (statue, Saturn, etc.,etc.).TheWillowOfDarkness

    Hi Willow,

    I apologize for the long delay. Brassier's example of people pointing at Saturn, while not knowing what it is, is supposed to problematize the idea that "Saturn's existence -- that it is -- is a function of what it is -- that Saturn [the concept] is indissociable from Saturn..." (Concept and Object, p.62)

    It could be argued that for an object (e.g. Saturn) to exist, or not, doesn't depend on our ever having acquired, uncovered, or created the concept under which it falls. This concept (e.g. the concept of a planet) is the referent of some word that expresses our conception of what it is, on my Wiggins/neo-Fregean account. Saturn itself is the referent of its proper name (or of some definite description, or some deictic act of reference such as pointing), and any such act of reference in thought or speech is enabled by our having some grasp of the concept.

    What is more difficult to conceive, and this was my main objection, is that there might be anything out there that answers to the description "the object pointed at by people who didn't know what it is". This could be sensibly said if what was meant was "the object pointed at by people who still only had at that time an indistinct conception of what it is". But that can't be what Brassier meant since he wants to divorce the idea of the object's existing by itself from the concept of what it is.

    Another way to convey the point of my 'lump-of-bonze / statue' example is that someone who didn't have possessions of any one of those two concepts (or any other relevant concept of a definite sort of material object under which the object pointed at falls) and who nevertheless pointed her finger in direction of the statue (thereby also pointing it in direction of the lump of bronze, and countless other things) would not thereby make *any* deictic act of reference since she wouldn't have any normative standard on the basis of which to determine if any part of the "object" is indeed a part of it (rather than, say, something extraneous accidentally attached to it, or touching it) or under what conditions the object could be said to have been destroyed and/or ceased to exist.

    So, the alleged possibility of an act of "pointing" to Saturn by people who don't know what Saturn is at all seems to fall short from showing that Saturn's existence -- that it is -- can be separated from the concept of what it is.
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    Haugeland's Pattern and Being was first published in the volume Dennett and His Critics, before it was reprinted in Haugeland's Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. But it really stands on its own. Dennett was dubious at first, if I remember, but then, when he reviewed Haugeland's volume of essays, and saw the paper in a broader context, he commented approvingly, on the lines of: 'I now see what you mean, this is indeed what I always have been recommending myself -- objective perception is an achievement'. Haugeland's core original insights didn't seem to leave a discernible mark on Dennett's subsequent thinking about the mind, though.

    There is one standalone piece by Dennett that is both available online and that is quite recommendable. This is his sharp critique of Harris' Free Will.
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    Michel Bitbol - "Ontology, Matter and Emergence" (on emergence and causation): http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4006/1/Emergence1.pdfStreetlightX

    I would likely endorse that too ;-)
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    It's intentionally provocational but still quality stuff (kinda like the philosophical equivalent of a Lars Von Trier film.)csalisbury

    Off topic (and spoiler): I only saw Von Trier's Dogville, and watched it two or three times. I was quite moved by it, emotionally, but also intellectually. The final pitch from Grace's father to her, in his car, about "arrogance" seemed to me, in light of the previous unfolding of events that furnished context to it, thought provoking and pregnant with philosophical implications about freedom, determinism (of the social conditioning sort) and moral responsibility. Maybe I'll start a thread on that eventually.
  • Reading for December: Concepts and Objects (Ray Brassier)
    Let me apologize again for putting you on the back burner. I'll likely be back to you before the next 48h.
  • Reading for December: Concepts and Objects (Ray Brassier)
    (Fwiw, your view strikes me as Heidegger in Fregean Clothing)csalisbury

    Yes, that's a fair characterization. You can also say that it's a form of strong correlationism.

    Your main question to me concerns the the 'existence' of sortal concepts in time, and whether those concepts pre-exist the objets that instantiate them. One might ask the same question regarding secondary quality concepts and the answer would be similar. (I'll single out relevant differences in the last paragraph below). For something to be red just is for it to look red to us in standard conditions. "Look" is here understood dispospositionally, as a passive power that red objects have to affect our sensibility in a specific way. Hence an object currently not looked at (or never looked at) still is red because it still has the relevant power. Even though optical properties of surface reflectance may be part of the explanation of this power, the concept of redness is nevertheless inseparable from the structure of our sensibity since only some specific (to us) features of reflectance spectra are visually salient to us (owing to both physiology and culture). When we conjecture that Triceratops might have been red this means that, for instance, had we been around before they went extinct, then they would have have looked red to us.

    There is a pseudo-problem generated by the question whether red objects still would be red in a universe where there are no observers. This is a pseudo-problem because there is no such thing as "a universe" that we can refer to from the outside, as it were. As regard the question whether red objects still would exist in our universe if we became extinct, or never came about, the answer is simply yes. Bus then this is just a simple counterfactual modal claim similar to the claim about currently unobserved or far away red objects. It still refers to *our* universe and *our* concept of redness. (Kripke's possible-world model for modal logic -- as used in Naming and Necessity -- unlike Lewis' own counterpart theory, respects this point, I believe -- See Gregory McCulloch, The Game of the Name, a book worth its price for the title alone). We are thus merely inquiring about the hypothetical causal impact of our specific extinction, and not any 'impact' from stripping away, as it were, our conceptual scheme from the world.

    The 'lol-planet' pseudo-sortal concept is pointless, as is Nelson Goodman's 'grue' pseudo-secondary quality concept, because it resists being integrated into a conceptual scheme intelligible to us. A conceptual scheme intelligible to us isn't an arbitrary formal construction, but rather is a way of talking (shaped by the specific human form of our embodiment and enculturation) that enables us to disclose objets in the world that answer to our interests and rationally justified existential commitments (from the point of view, ultimately, of practical reason). The existential commitments of the scientific community, for instance, ground the justification for some definition of a 'planet' over another because this definition enables the scientists to sustain or increase the intelligibility of the empirical domain of astronomy. The domain itself isn't circumscribed independently from the interests of the community, so long a the historically situated scientific practice has a point, and responds to some pragmatic interests including the fulfillment of explanatory, predictive and/or technical aspirations. This leaves room for some amount of contingency and arbitrariness (hence the occasional need for a vote).

    The main difference between general sortal concepts (that single out objects and incorporate our understanding of their conditions of persistence and criteria of individuation) and general property concepts (among whose secondary quality concepts are paradigmatic, and primary quality concepts (so called) are derivative abstractions) is that the general property concepts are valid across several empirical domains. There are red finches, red tables, and red planets. But there are no planet fruits or planet tables. Sortal concepts have more restricted scopes because they single out objects not just in respect of specific causal powers that those objects have to affect us (and their surroundings) but in respect of the way those objects are constitutively individuated in a manner essentially tied up to the empirical domains that they belong to (and hence also to the conceptual schemes within which those domains are disclosed). Individual pants and animals are conceptually tied up to the self-perpetuating life forms that they belong to (which determines their norms of health and behavior) while artifacts are tied up with the human practices within which they are brought into existence. Scientific objects are likewise tied up to scientific practices within which they serve explanatory purposes.

    There would be more to say regarding the relatively higher grade of autonomy (with respect to our conceptual practices) that belongs to life forms compared to the sortal concepts that single out human artifacts, socially constituted object (e.g. currencies) or 'scientific objects' such as planets or electrons.
  • On Wittgenstein's Quietism and the possibility of philosophical certainty
    Hi Pierre, I didn't think I was making an inductive argumentJohn

    No. I was charging you with trying to advance a deductive argument in support of the validity of inductive reasoning. I don't think just pointing out that we have no doubts that thing will go on in the future as they went in the past is a pragmatist argument in support of inductive reasoning. It seems more like a proclamation of faith (I am not saying this disrespectfully).
  • On Wittgenstein's Quietism and the possibility of philosophical certainty
    John, I think when you are trying to construct an argument to defend inductive reasoning, you may be involving yourself in a performative contradiction, as it were (though, I may be wrong. This is just a suggestion). An inductive argument, however it is defined, is supposed to be something different than a deductive argument.

    One should not, while defending inductive reasoning, offer some mutually accepted premises (of whatever nature) on the basis of which our interlocutor ought to be able to infer, deductively, that conclusions of inductive arguments (based on true premises) are true. That would be to misrepresent an inductive argument as a deductive argument!

    The defense of inductive reason ought rather be something like an account of the sort of embodied practice engaged in by subjects who thus reason; something that is bound to seem circular from the point of view of a skeptic who only has faith in deductive arguments and may doubt even the existence of the sensible body. Rather than portray the inductive argument as some sort of a risky generalization based on a finite set of experienced 'data', one could explain how the practice of inductive reasoning is, well, reasonable. And for the practice to be reasonable just is for it to be able to secure knowledge. Once the fallibility of our epistemic powers is acknowledged, then we can brush off the challenge offered to us by the skeptic who questions the epistemic status of our beliefs. The skeptic isn't merely challenging a particular belief on some specific rational ground, but our entitlement to any empirical belief whatsoever since such beliefs only are inductively justified (i.e. conceived as the upshot of ordinary, fallible albeit reliable, perceptual powers). The reason why we are entitled to brush her skeptical challenge off, is precisely because we aren't committed to prove everything deductively!
  • DARK MONEY - the Corrosive Koch Brothers
    Hi Agustino,

    Yes, your figures for coal (60%), gas (11%) and cement production (8%) match what I can find in the IPCC Special Report on Carbon Dioxide Capture and Storage. However fuel oil also accounts for 7.3%, while oil refineries account for 6%. So, the total for oil would be 13.3%, which would put it in second place. And then there is the issue of trends in consumption. The demand for oil might be expected to rise faster than the demand for coal in coming decades unless substitutes are found and promoted, I surmise (though I am not very knowledgeable about that).
  • Monthly Readings: Suggestions
    Some more suggestions (all available online):

    John McDowell, Avoiding the Myth of the Given
    John Haugeland, Pattern and Being
    Susan Hurley, Varieties of Externalism
    Andy Clark, The Twisted Matrix: Dream, Simulation or Hybrid?
    Michael Thompson, Apprehending Human Form

    Many earlier suggestions would also get my vote.
  • Reading for January: On What There Is
    Lots of critical comments to make, but this'll do for now.StreetlightX

    This post strikes me as an excellent summary, much better than I could have done myself. I thought for a second that you had misconstrued Quines' treatment of proper names because of your phrasing ("there is a something, X, of which we are speaking about"), which is a bit hard to parse as a definite description, but you cleared that up later on. I'm looking forward to reading your critical commentary.

Pierre-Normand

Start FollowingSend a Message