• Was Schopenhauer right?
    If noumena are instances of direct reality, why is it there is never an example of a noumenal object?Mww

    You know that Schopenhauer criticized Kant's use of the term 'noumenal', right? According to a passage in World as Will and Idea:

    The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [phainomena] and νοούμενα [nooumena]; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the Eleatics, in Plato's doctrine of Ideas, in the dialectic of the Megarics, and later in the scholastics, in the conflict between nominalism and realism. This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and Aristotle. But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations of things in themselves and their appearances.

    The Wikipedia entry on Noumenon, from which that is copied, also says

    The Greek word νοούμενoν, nooúmenon (plural νοούμενα, nooúmena) is the neuter middle-passive present participle of νοεῖν, noeîn, 'to think, to mean', which in turn originates from the word νοῦς, noûs, an Attic contracted form of νόος, nóos, 'perception, understanding, mind'. A rough equivalent in English would be "that which is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".

    So, from that, I would have surmised that the ideas, in the Platonic and Aristotelian sense, might be regarded as 'noumenal objects' insofar as they're apprehended directly by intellect. Lloyd Gerson says in his essay Platonism and Naturalism:

    in thinking, the intelligible object or form is present in the intellect, and thinking itself is the identification of the intellect with this intelligible. ...Thinking is not something that is, in principle, like sensing or perceiving; this is because thinking is a universalising activity. This is what this means: when you think, you see - mentally see - a form which could not, in principle, be identical with a particular - including a particular neurological element, a circuit, or a state of a circuit, or a synapse, and so on. This is so because the object of thinking is universal, or the mind is operating universally.

    A related comment from Ed Feser:

    Consider that when you think about triangularity, as you might when proving a geometrical theorem, it is necessarily perfect triangularity that you are contemplating, not some mere approximation of it. Triangularity as your intellect grasps it is entirely determinate or exact; for example, what you grasp is the notion of a closed plane figure with three perfectly straight sides, rather than that of something which may or may not have straight sides or which may or may not be closed. Of course, your mental image of a triangle might not be exact, but rather indeterminate and fuzzy. But to grasp something with the intellect is not the same as to form a mental image of it. For any mental image of a triangle is necessarily going to be of an isosceles triangle specifically, or of a scalene one, or an equilateral one; but the concept of triangularity that your intellect grasps applies to all triangles alike. Any mental image of a triangle is going to have certain features, such as a particular color, that are no part of the concept of triangularity in general. A mental image is something private and subjective, while the concept of triangularity is objective and grasped by many minds at once.Edward Feser

    Now, I know these are all very knotty philosophical problems, in no way am I trying to resolve them. It's just that it seems to me that 'noumenon' as 'intelligible objects' in the sense of those two quotations make sense to me, but that does not seem to be what Kant meant by the term, as Schopenhauer said. I sometimes wonder if Kant put too much emphasis on the necessity of empirical validation, as there are whole fields, such as pure mathematics, which seem to me to constitute real knowledge, but which are not empirically realised.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    I think that’s about right.
    //
    What I’ve read about Schopenhauer’s influence on Freud is that both he and Kant anticipated the discovery of the unconscious.
  • Currently Reading
    You’re welcome.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    If not Will for Schopenhauer, then what would he have "equated" with, say, Brahman or whatever stage of Buddhist translations' version of Tathagatagharba(?), or even Spinoza's Monism/God? What would Schopenhauer call that? Or is it utterly absent and there is only will and Representation, and will is not a being but a drive?ENOAH

    They're difficult questions, but I'd be careful about reification. Buddhanature is not any kind of entity or thing, but the latent capacity for enlightenment. Perhaps more like a 'principle'. Buddhism in particular is very sensitive to 'objectification'. So, 'will is not a being but a drive' is much nearer the mark.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    He's not saying this law is a feature of the universe, it's a feature of thought. We can't think beyond it, so it's like a signpost of the border of thought.frank

    That is along the same lines as the 'critical reflection' in the SEP entry that I mention above. But I'd say, it's deeper than a feature of thought, it is inextricably part of organic life, as all living things strive to survive (although only humans come along and ask why.)

    definitely he (Schop.) places suffering in the category of the real being, and unlike Buddhism, not in the category of Maya/Samsara/Karma. That is, suffering for S. is not restricted to the "illusions" but also Buddha Nature (if that and S's "will" are similarly the ground of real being).ENOAH

    I'd be very careful at this point. First, 'Buddhanature' was not something S. ever would have encountered even despite what knowledge of Buddhism he had, as it is part of a set of Buddhist doctrines that weren't translated until much later. Second, look again at the reply to S1 above, from the SEP entry on Schopenhauer. It suggests he's not really positing 'Will' as a philosophical absolute, as a kind of 'blind God' (which sounds more like H P Lovecraft :yikes: ) but more as an inevitable condition of existence, something that drives living beings to continually crave to exist and to continue, without their really understanding why.

    Without getting into all the intricacies of Buddhist philosophy, which are considerable, one of the basic formulations is called the 'chain of dependent origination' (Pratītyasamutpāda), shared by all schools. The driving factors are ignorance, greed and hatred (depicted iconographically as a rooster, pig and snake chasing each other in a circle). So ignorance is what causes beings to be born in the realm of Saṃsāra (with the caveat that in Mahāyāna Buddhism, the bodhisattva may be voluntarily born out of compassion for the sake of suffering beings). But ignorance has no intrinsic reality. And that actually converges (oddly enough) with a religious teaching associated with Augustine, 'evil as privation of the good' - in the same way that illness is simply the absence of health, or a hole the absence of ground, evil or ignorance has no intrinsic being, although it appears totally real to those afflicted by it.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    Have another look at #7 of the SEP entry.. I think it addresses that question. The emphasis on will is 'less of an outlook derived from an absolute standpoint that transcends human nature and as more of an outlook expressive of human nature in its effort to achieve philosophical understanding .... It can be understood alternatively as an expression of the human perspective on the world, that, as an embodied individual, we typically cannot avoid. This tempered approach, though, does leave us with the decisive question of why the world would appear to be so violent, if the universe’s core is not thoroughly “Will,” but is also something mysterious beyond this.'

    Perhaps the gist is that his is a perspectival approach - from the human perspective, the world appears 'as will', but to those who have 'gone beyond', it is something else.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    In the Wikipedia entry on higher consciousness I belatedly linked to my last entry, there's this snippet:

    The better consciousness in me lifts me into a world where there is no longer personality and causality or subject or object. My hope and my belief is that this better (supersensible and extra-temporal) consciousness will become my only one, and for that reason I hope that it is not God. But if anyone wants to use the expression God symbolically for the better consciousness itself or for much that we are able to separate or name, so let it be, yet not among philosophers I would have thought. — Schopenhauer
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    This is getting very esoteric, but can it be argued that Schopenhauer's famous "denial of Will", is actually a sort of existence of unmediated existence?schopenhauer1

    This is where I think Schopenhauer was disadvantaged by not having encountered an adept or guru of the Eastern paths he admired (of course in his day and age that would have been very unlikely given geography and history.) I think Schopenhauer intuited that there was a state of the 'cessation of suffering', which he said was exemplified St Francis and other ascetics, but I don't know if he really reached those states (and who does?) In Urs App's book Schopenhauer's Compass, there's a whole chapter on what Schopenhauer describes as 'better consciousness' (apparently what we would call higher consciousness) so again, he was very much aware of that in a way that most later philosophers were not. But Zen teachers will demand going far beyond just a kind of theoretical grasp and it takes considerable training to truly integrate that understanding. Schopenhauer was a perceptive philosopher, but not, in Eastern parlance, a 'realised being'.

    See also
    Schopenhauer and Buddhism
    Peter Abelsen

    Philosophy East and West
    Vol. 43, No. 2 (Apr., 1993), pp. 255-278 (24 pages)
    Published By: University of Hawai'i Press
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    Where below am I naive or inconsistent?ENOAH

    Not necessarily either, but the subtleties of these subjects are such that they resist compression to a schematic. Understanding what exactly Plato intended by 'ideas' or 'forms' is quite a difficult task in its own right, and Kant is infamously difficult to read.

    One analogy I've found for Schopenhauer's 'will' is the Buddhist 'tannha' (craving or thirst). I got ChatGPT to summarize this comparison which can be viewed below:

    Reveal
    Schopenhauer's 'Will'
    For Schopenhauer, the 'will' is the fundamental reality, an irrational, blind force that manifests itself in all living beings. It is the source of all desires and actions, and it perpetuates the cycle of striving and suffering. Schopenhauer's 'will' is not a personal or individual will but a universal force that drives all phenomena. His pessimistic view holds that the endless striving of the will is the root of suffering, and liberation can be attained by negating the will through asceticism and denial of desires.

    Buddhist 'Tṛṣṇā' (or 'Taṇhā')
    In Buddhism, 'tṛṣṇā' or 'taṇhā' (Pāli) is often translated as 'thirst,' 'craving,' or 'desire.' It is identified as the second of the Four Noble Truths and is considered the origin of suffering (dukkha). 'Tṛṣṇā' refers to the insatiable craving for sensory pleasures, existence, and non-existence, which leads to the cycle of birth, death, and rebirth (saṃsāra). Overcoming 'tṛṣṇā' through the practice of the Noble Eightfold Path leads to the cessation of suffering (nirvāṇa).

    Comparative Analysis
    Similarities:

    Source of Suffering: Both Schopenhauer's 'will' and the Buddhist 'tṛṣṇā' are seen as the root causes of suffering and the continuous cycle of existence.
    Nature of Desire: Both concepts emphasize the relentless and insatiable nature of desire, leading to perpetual dissatisfaction and striving.
    Goal of Liberation: Schopenhauer and Buddhism both propose that liberation from suffering involves overcoming the driving force of desire. For Schopenhauer, this is through the negation of the will, while in Buddhism, it is through the elimination of craving and the attainment of nirvāṇa.

    Differences:

    Metaphysical Foundation: Schopenhauer's metaphysics is rooted in a form of philosophical idealism, where the 'will' is a metaphysical principle underlying all phenomena. Buddhism, on the other hand, does not posit a metaphysical will but focuses on the psychological and phenomenological aspects of craving and its cessation.

    Path to Liberation: Schopenhauer emphasizes asceticism and the denial of individual will as a path to liberation. Buddhism prescribes a specific ethical and meditative path (the Noble Eightfold Path) to eliminate craving and achieve enlightenment.
    Ultimate Reality: Schopenhauer's ultimate reality is the will, which one must negate, while in Buddhism, the ultimate reality is the cessation of suffering and the realization of the nature of existence (dependent origination and emptiness).

    Scholarly Exploration

    Scholars have delved into these comparisons in various works. For instance:

    Bryan Magee discusses the parallels between Schopenhauer and Eastern thought in his book "The Philosophy of Schopenhauer."

    Urs App explores Schopenhauer's engagement with Eastern texts and ideas in "Schopenhauer's Compass: An Introduction to Schopenhauer’s Philosophy and its Origins."

    D.T. Suzuki and other scholars of comparative philosophy have also noted the resonances between Schopenhauer's ideas and Buddhist thought, particularly in the context of suffering and desire.

    These comparisons underscore the significant cross-cultural philosophical dialogues that have shaped modern understandings of desire, suffering, and liberation.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    (There is a connection between Wittgenstein and the issue I mentioned earlier in the respect of the decline of scholastic realism and Aristotelian philosophy. As David Bentley Hart put it, the pre-modern Cosmos was viewed as an intrinsically purposeful and ordered whole comprising interconnected rational relationships. The Aristotelian aitia are commonly translated as "causes" but are quite different from the homogeneous material causes of the mechanistic philosophy, entailing a purpose for every particular (somewhat related to the later 'principle of sufficient reason'). Thus, it was believed that the natural order was already real and comparable to intelligence and that intellect was the most concentrated and brilliant reflection of nature's most fundamental essence rather than an odd resident of a foreign realm. Nominalism and theological voluntarism, which stressed the complete independence and unknowability of the Divine Will, dismantled this rationalist worldview and replaced it with a mechanical universe and a deist God. Not that Wittgenstein appealed to that directly, but that it provided the background, hence also his mysticism and the disconnection he diagnosed between facts and the transcendent realm of ethics and aesthetics.)
  • The Idea That Changed Europe
    ditto with the classics. But with this qualification: they are all long dead and long gone.tim wood

    One of the reasons they're still read is obviously because they were judged to have enduring value, and the fact that they have been preserved for millenia attests to that. (Presumably there were many minor and lesser writings that were not so preserved.) But I do get that to really understand (for example) Plato's corpus, you would have to read them in the original, so as to grasp all of the allusions and subtleties of the language. But then, it's a difficult field of scholarship, due both to the difficulties of the source texts, and also that they have been subject to centuries of commentary.

    I've been attracted to Lloyd Gerson's books, and also those of a classics scholar Katya Vogt, but their books are very hard to read. They contain very lengthy and detailed footnotes and devote a great deal of time to defending their interpretation against others, ancient and modern, which introduce many intricacies of interpretation and arcane arguments replete with passages in Greek which of course I don't understand.

    But, I do agree with the points you've made above, about assimilating the ideas from these texts, indeed that's why I made the remark at the outset. Also I've noticed this series from Princeton Press which makes available many classic texts.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    From the SEP entry:

    According to Schopenhauer, corresponding to the level of the universal subject-object distinction, Will is immediately objectified into a set of universal objects or Platonic Ideas. These constitute the timeless patterns for each of the individual things that we experience in space and time. There are different Platonic Ideas, and although this multiplicity of Ideas implies that some measure of individuation is present within this realm, each Idea nonetheless contains no plurality within itself and is said to be “one.” Since the Platonic Ideas are in neither space nor time, they lack the qualities of individuation that would follow from the introduction of spatial and temporal qualifications. In these respects, the Platonic Ideas are independent of the specific fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason, even though it would be misleading to say that there is no individuation whatsoever at this universal level, for there are many different Platonic Ideas. Schopenhauer refers to the Platonic Ideas as the direct objectifications of Will and as the immediate objectivity of Will.
    '
    I recall from Kastrup's discussion of the Ideas, that they are like modes of vibration, similar to the way that when a guitar string is plucked, it will emanate a specific note, due to the tension of the string etc. There's a sense in which the ideas as archetypes represent the possibilities of things - that if something is to exist, it has to take a certain form - but that 'form' is not something that exists separately in the supposed 'ethereal realm'. In that sense the ideas transcend existence. They are kind of like a combination of necessity and possibility (ref.) And in this respect there are continuities with neoplatonism and the 'grand tradition' generally i.e. The Ideas are like intermediaries between the One and the individual. However in Schopenhauer will is 'irrational and blind' whereas in neoplatonism the nature of the One is beneficient and purposive.

    But then as the SEP also notes in respect of Schop's ethics, 'Moral consciousness and virtue thus give way to the voluntary poverty and chastity of the ascetic. St. Francis of Assisi (WWR, Section 68) and Jesus (WWR, Section 70) subsequently emerge as Schopenhauer’s prototypes for the most enlightened lifestyle, in conjunction with the ascetics from every religious tradition.' I find this paradoxical, not to say contradictory, aspect of Schopenhauer a bit confounding. On the one hand, he wrote ascerbic diatribes against all religion, but on the other, he seems to recognise the Upaniṣads and the 'life of Jesus' as kind of ideals. I think he had some kind of conflict around these issues - which I well understand, given the highly conflicted nature of religion in European history.

    All in all, his writing on 'representation' and the ideas, I find highly amenable, but not so much his conception of the all-powerful will. I'm still dubious about those aspects of Schopenhauer, but as we all agree, he's a substantial figure in philosophy, and I'll continue to think it over.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    It turns out to be more like a book. It's related to the theme I keep returning to. See this chat.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    As you know, I generally look to Buddhist principles as a source of guidance, and they proclaim that there is indeed 'an end to suffering', even if it's not something we're likely able to grasp in this life. I concede that is something like religious faith, but one that Schopenhauer himself expressed, even despite his distaste for mainstream religions and rejection of the idea of God. In other words, it's not suffering all the way down - suffering has a cause and an end. I wouldn't look to Nietzsche for insight on that, however.

    If we deny-the-will to the point of getting beyond our own subject-object nature, we can perhaps escape.schopenhauer1

    hence the motif of divine union, merging with the divine, etc. There's a theme I'm exploring in medieval philosophy, 'the union of knower and known'. Too large a digression for this thread.
  • The Idea That Changed Europe
    in the second half of my life, I've come to regret not having been educated in 'the Classics', although I console myself with the thought that had I been part of an earlier generation, I probably would have had them beaten into me with a cane, and would have hated them for it. Nevertheless, I think the want of knowledge of The Classics is a real want, it's a real cultural heritage, and we're the worse nowadays for not knowing about them.
  • The Idea That Changed Europe
    Greek and Roman classics are not part of anybody's culture except the people who speak their languages — that doesn't apply to most here —, and the reason for that is exactly ScholasticsLionino

    So, the 'scholastics', who were avid readers and propogators of 'the Classics', were responsible for the snuffing out of classical education?
  • Why The Simulation Argument is Wrong
    LLMs are not conscious or intelligent, they're just "stochastic parrots."fishfry

    I put this to ChatGPT4. Have a look at what it said.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    First, apologies to both of you.ENOAH

    I think you need to slow down a bit. You make many rapid-fire comments, very much stream of consciousness - which is fine, it's part of the appeal of this medium, one of the reasons I've now made 21k entries here :yikes: . But philosophers like Schopenhauer are deep and hard to understand (speaking as a student, not as an authority!) Read, digest, and contemplate.

    Myself, I like to believe that Schop. was 'the last great philosopher'. But then, there's Wittgenstein and Heidegger, also great, so it doesn't quite work. But he was the last great idealist philosopher, and as such deserves a special place in the pantheon (spoken as an advocate for idealism). But take time to take it in - I'm not wanting to idolize him, but he's a really substantial philosopher, material you can read for a lifetime. There's time, at least, for that.
  • The essence of religion
    I presented an argument in response to your gnomic aphorism. If you think it 'makes your point', what is that point, and how did I help make it?
  • The essence of religion
    You did ask me to comment, and I tried to respond in good faith, although I ought to know by now what to expect from you.
  • The essence of religion
    'What did you do to the cat, Erwin? It looks half dead!' ~ Ms Schrodinger.
  • The essence of religion
    It simply cannot be that that cat over there is independent and localized as normal perception tells us.Constance

    Maybe it's Schrodinger's :-)
  • The essence of religion
    I've referred to the Eastern Gatehouse Sutta before. It's a dialogue between the Buddha and Sariputta (who is the figure in the dialogues associated with wisdom teachings.) The relevant passage is as follows:

    "Sariputta, do you take it on conviction that the faculty of conviction, when developed & pursued, gains a footing in the Deathless, has the Deathless as its goal & consummation? Do you take it on conviction that the faculty of persistence... mindfulness... concentration... discernment, when developed & pursued, gains a footing in the Deathless, has the Deathless as its goal & consummation?"

    "Lord, it's not that I take it on conviction in the Blessed One that the faculty of conviction... persistence... mindfulness... concentration... discernment, when developed & pursued, gains a footing in the Deathless, has the Deathless as its goal & consummation. Those who have not known, seen, penetrated, realized, or attained it by means of discernment would have to take it on conviction in others that the faculty of conviction... persistence... mindfulness... concentration... discernment, when developed & pursued, gains a footing in the Deathless, has the Deathless as its goal & consummation; whereas those who have known, seen, penetrated, realized, & attained it by means of discernment would have no doubt or uncertainty that the faculty of conviction... persistence... mindfulness... concentration... discernment, when developed & pursued, gains a footing in the Deathless, has the Deathless as its goal & consummation.....

    ('The Deathless' is a synonym for Nibbana.) Sariputta says "It's not that *I* take it on conviction" - presumably because he has 'known, seen, penetrated, realised and attained it'. Whereas those who have not known, seen, etc, would have to take it on conviction.

    So, in this framework, faith has a role, but it's not the deciding factor, which is a hard-won insight (and the requirements of the Buddhist monastic orders are known to be exacting.) It is nearer to a form of gnosticism, in fact there's a Pali/Sanskrit word 'Jñāna' which is from the common Indo-Eruopean root jn- or gn- associated with 'higher knowledge'. But the overall point is that of a kind of 'saving insight' - in the early Buddhist texts this is stated again and again, in almost every thread, to be insight into the chain of dependent origination which is the causal factor that causes repeated birth in saṃsāra (whether in this life or in future lives). But faith is still indispensable, as one has to have the conviction that there is a purpose to undertaking the arduous path of discipleship.

    So, as for 'whatever is real does not require faith', from the Buddhist perspective, it is quite true, with the caveat that us putthajjana (untrained worldlings) do not comprehend or see what is real as we're basically unprepared and corrupted by attachment to the sensory data.

    But then look at advanced scientific knowledge. That also requires extensive training and preparation, fluency in mathematical and statistical techniques, a grasp of theory, and also exposure to very specific kinds of experience that can only be replicated under highly specific conditions. In many regards, lay readers like ourselves have to 'take it on faith' that the hypotheses and observations are valid as we're often not able to validate those in the first person.

    Traditional Western philosophy had a similar attitude:

    For Hadot...the means for the philosophical student to achieve the “complete reversal of our usual ways of looking at things” epitomized by the Sage were a series of spiritual exercises. These exercises encompassed all of those practices still associated with philosophical teaching and study: reading, listening, dialogue, inquiry, and research. However, they also included practices deliberately aimed at addressing the student’s larger way of life, and demanding daily or continuous repetition: practices of attention (prosoche), meditations (meletai), memorizations of dogmata, self-mastery (enkrateia), the therapy of the passions, the remembrance of good things, the accomplishment of duties, and the cultivation of indifference towards indifferent things (Philosophy as a Way of Life 84). Hadot acknowledges his use of the term “spiritual exercises” may create anxieties, by associating philosophical practices more closely with religious devotion than typically done. Hadot’s use of the adjective “spiritual” (or sometimes “existential”) indeed aims to capture how these practices, like devotional practices in the religious traditions are aimed at generating and reactivating a constant way of living and perceiving in prokopta, despite the distractions, temptations, and difficulties of life. For this reason, they call upon far more than “reason alone.” — Pierre Hadot, IEP

    It's not enough to say that any and all of us have an innate insight into or grasp of the nature of reality by default, so to speak. Otherwise what would be the need of philosophy or science or any other kind of training?
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    I have never been able to get on board with his Debbie Downer*1 "wanh, wanh, wah" Pessimism and Roseanne Rosannadana "it's always something"Gnomon

    Grow up mate. Schopenhauer is for Big School, not kindy.
  • The essence of religion
    But it shows that concepts are not empty things. They are palpable errors. As I see it, when we talk about the world, we are using categories of understanding. These are concepts, so when I see a dog, the particular dog in front of me is known because I have this schematic in my head about dogs in general, the universal that subsumes the particular.Constance

    I think there are two rather divergent themes in play here. First you referenced the ‘rope-snake’ illusion, attributed to Sankara (although really common currency for all the schools of Indian philosophy). The thrust of that is that we impute attributes to things because of mistaken attachment to them, imputing a value to them they don’t really possess, due to avidya/ignorance. That is the ‘error in consciousness’ in that context. It is comparable in some respects to the Christian ‘original sin’, with the caveat that the Indian conception is more cognitive (corruption of the understanding) than volitional (corruption of the will.) In Indian systems of philosophy ( ‘darshana’) this condition of avidya/ignorance is primeval, i.e. beginningless in time (whereas in Christianity it is assigned to the mythology of the Fall.) It is that condition of avidya/ignorance from which mokṣa (liberation) is to be sought over aeons of life-times.

    But when you talk of ‘categories of the understanding’, I take that to be a reference to universals. Universals are not much stressed in Vedanta (and denied altogether in formal Buddhist logic, although it is upheld in other schools such as Mimamsa and Nyaya. A useful resource on universals in Western philosophy is an essay by Jacques Maritain.) But I don’t see the role of universals as necessarily inimical to awakening in the sense the Buddhists or Hindus understand it.

    //please forgive the pedantic tone of the above, it’s a subject I studied at university//
  • The essence of religion
    It is the same world, but all along there has been this fundamental mistake at the perceptual level.Constance

    An error in consciousness, it has been said.
  • The essence of religion
    I realise my reference to ‘feeling what you cannot know’ is open to a variety of interpretations (to say the least). But what I was trying to drive at, was becoming internally aware of the limitation or shortcomings of what can be put in a propositional form. The language-processing faculty of the mind is obviously a central aspect of knowledge, but there’s another, intuitive faculty which is broader, deeper and more ancient. And there’s a kind of boundary between them that you can become aware of, and I feel it’s something I have become at least somewhat aware of. I suppose I might be referring to the unconscious, and that this is something like what Jung said about the role of symbols in mediating the unconscious. As to how ‘reliable’ it is, obviously anyone is liable to self-delusion, but nevertheless grappling with that existence is an essential part of the philosophical quest.

    On Wittgenstein again: an article by Ray Monk, his biographer, said:

    His work is opposed, as he once put it, to "the spirit which informs the vast stream of European and American civilisation in which all of us stand." Nearly 50 years after his death, we can see, more clearly than ever, that the feeling that he was swimming against the tide was justified. If we wanted a label to describe this tide, we might call it "scientism," the view that every intelligible question has either a scientific solution or no solution at all. It is against this view that Wittgenstein set his face. …

    There are many questions to which we do not have scientific answers, not because they are deep, impenetrable mysteries, but simply because they are not scientific questions. These include questions about love, art, history, culture, music-all questions, in fact, that relate to the attempt to understand ourselves better. There is a widespread feeling today that the great scandal of our times is that we lack a scientific theory of consciousness. And so there is a great interdisciplinary effort, involving physicists, computer scientists, cognitive psychologists and philosophers, to come up with tenable scientific answers to the questions: what is consciousness? What is the self? One of the leading competitors in this crowded field is the theory advanced by the mathematician Roger Penrose, that a stream of consciousness is an orchestrated sequence of quantum physical events taking place in the brain. Penrose's theory is that a moment of consciousness is produced by a sub-protein in the brain called a tubulin. The theory is, on Penrose's own admission, speculative, and it strikes many as being bizarrely implausible. But suppose we discovered that Penrose's theory was correct, would we, as a result, understand ourselves any better? Is a scientific theory the only kind of understanding?

    Well, you might ask, what other kind is there? Wittgenstein's answer to that, I think, is his greatest, and most neglected, achievement. Although Wittgenstein's thought underwent changes between his early and his later work, his opposition to scientism was constant. Philosophy, he writes, "is not a theory but an activity." It strives, not after scientific truth, but after conceptual clarity.

    When I read that, I feel perfectly in alignment with it. But it seems very different from the way Wittgenstein is often interpreted, including on this forum.
  • The essence of religion
    And yet when I tell you I think it all comes down to faith and feeling and that nothing discursive can be known via meditation, intuition or enlightenment you disagree and label me a positivistJanus

    Learning to feel what can't be known is actually a very difficult skill, I believe, and I don't make any claim to have mastered it, but at least I'm aware of it, as something that matters, and something that I know that I don't know. Having an insight into the limitations of discursive knowledge is an insight - I referenced the 'analogy of the divided line' in that respect, as it appears Plato recognises different levels or kinds of knowledge, discursive, and types that are higher than that. What he regarded as higher knowledge, noesis, or insight into the ideas, was very much also a matter of aesthetics, and therefore of feeling (or 'qualia' in that horrible philosophical jargon). But you have told me on multiple occasions that there can be no such thing as higher knowledge, nor a vertical or qualitative dimension of existence, and that anything that is said along those lines must be considered 'matter of faith'. It never seems to occur to you that maybe there is such a thing, and you don't understand it.

    There is an historical dimension to all these matters. I think classical metaphysics was grounded in a kind of vision, 'the unitive vision', also dismissed by you as 'faith'. There is something in it that can be known, but it has generally been rejected or occluded or dismissed by the modern conception of knowledge, as I try to explain to Banno, who likewise says it's simply 'hand-waving' (and also that it is something that ought not to be said). I try to support this contention with reference to citations, which you then also tell me 'have it all wrong'.

    From my perspective, I've made many sincere efforts to explain my arguments to you, over about ten years, which is often met with a mixture of incomprehension and indignation, along with frequent acusations that I've 'dodged the question' or 'changed the subject'. Last time I took a month out from posting, I seriously considered whether I should respond to your criticisms. I'm still considering it, but if I no longer respond, it's not out of defensiveness, it's out of a feeling you have no idea what I'm trying to convey.

    The one thing that comes out of it is that having to explain it over and over again does at least crystallize it for me, even if I feel I'm singing to the deaf.
  • The essence of religion
    I am wondering why I should care. It's just that we always seem to come back to quesions about what is true and how do we know it.Tom Storm

    You often ask 'why should I bother with this?' But something keeps drawing you back into these discussions.

    I think It’s essential that you learn to feel what you cannot know. Coming to think of it, this is a large part of what 'mindfulness meditation' comprises - learning that the verbal or discursive element of your being is only one facet of a much greater whole. That also comes out in artistic performance and art generally. But being aware of it is important - a kind of somatic or bodily awareness, not just on the conceptual level. That's what comes from 'zazen'. Also, for anyone that has done awareness training of the kind done at EST and the like, you're taught that ego resists this awareness, as ego's role is to incorporate everything under its gaze. That is what 'letting go' means in relation to contemplative awareness. (And I *think* this is related to the OP.)

    It's also related to the phenomenological epochē, the 'letting experience be' and seeing it as it is, rather than trying to interpret it. (There's an historical link between the Buddhist 'nirodha' (cessation) and the epochē of the early sceptics.)

    In a different register - much of the hostility that is directed towards religion and/or mysticism on this forum is an unconscious response to the dogmatic authority that presided over it in earlier centuries. I recall reading an excerpt from the founding charter of The Royal Society, which stated in no uncertain terms that 'metaphysik', being the province of 'churchmen', in no way must be considered in the reckonings of the Society. And when you consider the bloody history of that time, the slaughter of the 'religious wars', that was an extremely prudent consideration. Venture a wrong opinion about matters of dogma, and goodness knows what might happen to you.
  • The essence of religion
    When you consider the transcendental, what frame do you find helpful? It strikes me that your form of idealism (as articulated in your article) has some commonalities with Husserl and phenomenology.Tom Storm

    One way of thinking about it is that the transcendent is 'always already the case'. In discovering it, or rather realising it, we are coming to understand something that has always been so (and I think this is connected with Plato's 'unforgetting'). I agree with the relevance of the distinction of 'transcendent' and 'transcendental' noted above, but the latter is in some ways just as difficult to understand - it to is connected with the concept of the 'a priori' which also is a form of 'always already so'.

    This is inexorably connected with what is nowadays (usually dismissively) described as mysticism. But then Wittgenstein also said, not far from those other passages I quoted 'There is indeed the inexpressible. This shows itself; it is the mystical'.

    However that apophatic (cannot be stated) element of Wittgenstein is not especially helpful, or rather it is easily misinterpreted. Recall, as has been touched on already, that the positivists understood Wittgenstein to support their anti-metphysics, which he never did. He recognised that the domain of value, so to speak, transcends the realm of facts. He also says somewhere 'even if all scientific problems were solved it wouldn't touch the problems of life.' So if you make it the subject of propositional knowledge, then you're not really saying anything. You have to walk the walk. ('Do not tell! Display!’, said Oscar Wilde.)

    The only way I've been able to frame all of this is to try and zoom out to a perspective encompassing the history of ideas and the dialectics of modernity. As I've often said, I hold to a form of the 'forgotten wisdom' school of thought, that the ancients had insights into a higher understanding that has nowadays been forgotten (e.g. Huston Smith and others). Because of the particular background of Western thought, there is a kind of unstated barrier demarcating what secular philosophy is able to acknowledge. That is the subject of John Vervaeke's lecture series on The Meaning Crisis. But it's also beginning to surface with the re-kindling of interest in Stoicism and ancient philosophy generally (there's a lot of material now on Substack and Medium, for instance.)

    With apologists it always comes down to "you must not understand" if you disagree with them and/or present arguments they can't cope withJanus

    'Apologists' being anyone who questions naive scientific realism, right?
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    Dirac's derivation is no more than that.Banno

    Perhaps you can use a couple of sticks to learn to make a fire. It might be more in line with your proclivities.
  • The essence of religion
    I found an interesting essay on Wittgenstein's philosophy of religion - Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Religion, John Cottingham (.pdf).

    Thomas Nagel remarks in a footnote to his essay Secular Philosophy and the Religious Temperament:

    The religious temperament is not common among analytic philosophers, but it is not absent. A number of prominent analytic philosophers are protestant, catholic, or jewish, and others, such as Wittgenstein and Rawls, clearly had a religious attitude to life without adhering to a particular religion. But I believe nothing of the kind is present in the makeup of Russell, Moore, Ryle, Austin, Carnap, Quine, Davidson, Strawson, or most of the current professoriate.
  • The essence of religion
    I simply quoted that in support of @Constance who has expressed similar ideas.
  • The Idea That Changed Europe
    The Theological Origins of Modernity, Michael Gillespietim wood

    I second that, extremely important book, one I read when I first joined forums and which underlies a lot of what I've been exploring since. There's a good review and synopsis here.
  • Quantifier Variance, Ontological Pluralism, and Other Fun Stuff
    Our issue was, what sort of things are numbers? And one answer is that they are real, like trees, sticks and rocks, but that they are in a special world that makes them unavailable for examination in the way that trees and sticks are available. Roughly, Plato's world of forms.Banno

    There is implicit reification in this statement (and please forgive me for flogging what is probably a dead horse.) This is based around the instinctive conviction that only objects are real, or that the scope of what constitutes real things is entirely exhausted by what exists as objects or collections of objects. This is what leads to the erroneous idea of 'ethereal realms' or 'Platonic worlds'. Is 'the set of natural numbers' a real realm in an objective sense? Not at all - but there is nevertheless 'the domain of natural numbers', which are discerned by reason, as distinct from sense.

    The following excerpt pertains to Plato's forms, generally, although it's not difficult to extrapolate it to the understanding of number also.

    Forms...are radically distinct, and in that sense ‘apart,’ in that they are not themselves sensible things. With our eyes we can see large things, but not largeness itself; healthy things, but not health itself. The latter, in each case, is an idea, an intelligible content, something to be apprehended by thought rather than sense, a ‘look’ not for the eyes but for the mind. This is precisely the point Plato is making when he characterizes forms as the reality of all things. “Have you ever seen any of these with your eyes?—In no way … Or by any other sense, through the body, have you grasped them? I am speaking about all things such as largeness, health, strength, and, in one word, the reality [οὐσίας] of all other things, what each thing is” (Phd. 65d4–e1). Is there such a thing as health? Of course there is. Can you see it? Of course not. This does not mean that the forms are occult entities floating ‘somewhere else’ in ‘another world,’ a ‘Platonic heaven.’ It simply says that the intelligible identities which are the reality, the whatness, of things are not themselves physical things to be perceived by the senses, but must be grasped by thought. If, taking any of these examples—say, justice, health, or strength—we ask, “How big is it? What color is it? How much does it weigh?” we are obviously asking the wrong kind of question. Forms are ideas, not in the sense of concepts or abstractions, but in that they are realities apprehended by thought rather than by sense. They are thus ‘separate’ in that they are not additional members of the world of sensible things, but are known by a different mode of awareness. But this does not mean that they are ‘located elsewhere,’ or that they are not, as Plato says, the very intelligible contents, the truth and reality of sensible things. — Thinking Being - An Introduction to Metaphysics in the Classical Tradition, Eric D. Perl, p28

    And we build on this. "7" counts as seven, and with a few extras we can write "3+4=7". These count as numbers.Banno

    The attempt to reduce mathematics to 'speech acts' is inadequate to account for the 'unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences' (Eugene Wigner). It is the predictive power of mathematics and the synthetic a priori, which has given rise to many of the astonishing discoveries of mathematical physics in the last several centuries. That is exemplified by Dirac’s equations, which predicted the existence of antimatter based purely on the mathematical necessity of solutions to these equations. These solutions (positrons) were not derived from empirical data or observation but from the mathematical theory of quantum mechanics. This aligns with the notion of the synthetic a priori because it extends our knowledge in a substantive way, yet was not derived from empirical observation.

    So the idea that mathematical reasoning can be reduced to speech acts—verbal or written statements within particular contexts—is inadequate to capture instances like Dirac's prediction (and countless other examples from mathematical physics.) Speech acts emphasize the role of language and context in constructing meaning, but Dirac's work suggests that mathematical constructs can correspond to real physical entities, indicating a deeper, non-linguistic form of truth and reasoning. His prediction was based on the internal consistency and logical implications of quantum theory, not merely on the performative use of language.

    The successful experimental verification of antimatter substantially supports the idea that mathematical descriptions can unveil aspects of physical reality that are yet unseen. This challenges purely empirical or nominalist views of science and supports a more Platonist or realist view, where abstract mathematical forms have a real, albeit non-empirical, connection to the structure of the world.
  • The essence of religion
    Ask Wittgenstein how it is with value experiences.Constance

    Speaking of whom.....

    6.41The sense of the world must lie outside the world. In the world everything is as it is and happens as it does happen. In it there is no value—and if there were, it would be of no value.

    If there is a value which is of value, it must lie outside all happening and being-so. For all happening and being-so is accidental.

    What makes it non-accidental cannot lie in the world, for otherwise this would again be accidental.

    It must lie outside the world.


    6.42 Hence also there can be no ethical propositions.

    Propositions cannot express anything higher.


    6.421It is clear that ethics cannot be expressed.

    Ethics is transcendental.

    (Ethics and aesthetics are one.)
    Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
  • A poll regarding opinions of evolution
    It's an interesting area because it ties in with the radical transformation of views on freedom. Freedom goes from primarily being defined in terms of actuality (the ability to do the Good) to bring primarily defined in terms of potency (the ability to choose anything). This has ramifications throughout philosophy.Count Timothy von Icarus

    A fascinating insight and one I'd never thought of, although I suppose it ties in with the ascendancy of liberalism which understands freedom as freedom of choice.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    If a god created us did it have this chatter in mind? If we are organic beings formed by the evolution of cells, is the chatter a formation of cells?ENOAH

    Actually the sources I referred to, and I think Schopenhauer, don’t posit that dichotomy between naturalism vs Divine creation. That, I think, is very specific to (post) Christian culture.
  • Was Schopenhauer right?
    So I agree that humans have a running narrative of reasons and explanations and goals and emotional responses, etc. etc. that come from having a linguistic-based mind, and the dynamics of our brain. This indeed does make us distinct from other animals. However, I don't see how it could ever be different for the human animal.schopenhauer1

    Don't overlook the significance of trance states and sacred silence, which humans also 'have access to' (to express it in modern terminology). For example, in the yoga sutras, there are references to 'nirvikalpa samadhi'. 'Nirvikalpa' is derived from the negation (nir) of vikalpa (mentation, thought forms, vritti). So that state is one of complete abeyance of discursive thought. In Buddhism, there is a Pali term 'papañca' meaning 'conceptual proliferation' or 'mental elaboration'. Suffice to say that internal mental chatter is the default state of humanity, excacerbated by our media-saturated culture. It is the subject of the delightfully-named 'Honeyball Sutta' which explains how beings become enmeshed in never-ending chains of emotional reactivity and attachment, resulting in 'taking up rods & bladed weapons, of arguments, quarrels, disputes, accusations, divisive tale-bearing, & false speech.'

    So speech and discursive reason are indeed central to the human way of being in the world, but they are not the be-all and end-all of existence. And I think this was something Schopenhauer would have understood.