• Why Was Rich Banned?
    I don't think it was his viewpoints that actually got him bannedfdrake

    I for one would be happier if someone said it definitely wasn't his viewpoints, all of which i disagreed with.
  • Picking beliefs
    the presumed choice still seems to appear out of thin air without explanationSapientia

    Just going off the the idea that "should" here is normative, that you should conclude such-and-such in the same sense that you should respect your elders or that you should eat your vegetables. Norms are usually something you get to choose to conform to or not, and there are consequences either way.

    If my reasoning doesn't match theirs, then that's that. What's the choice supposed to be? The only choice that I see would be the choice to conform disingenuously or stand by my reasoning. That's no choice at all for someone like me.Sapientia

    This is an excellent point. Most of the time, we no more choose to reason as we do than we choose to speak our native language as we do. We've learned, we've been trained, we've developed habits, and so on.

    But I've been in the position, on this very forum, of arguing that if you say A then you should say B, and it sure feels like I'm saying that this is the right way to reason, that I'm invoking a real norm.

    The conundrum stands...
  • Picking beliefs

    I'm not sure your example is the same though. Yours I hear as a subjunctive, acknowledging gravity as an hypothesis.

    I took my "should" as normative: if you reason the way we do around here, this is what you'll conclude. Not an expectation in the predictive sense, but in the "it's mandatory" sense. (Every one of these words tries to be ambiguous in the same way...)
  • Queued for moderation?

    I thought that likely, as a matter of fact, this being a phone, and me hating writing on it, but the flag button doesn't show up at all until it's posted... Not gonna worry about it.
  • Queued for moderation?

    Cool. But how could it get flagged without ever being posted?

    It was immediate.
  • Picking beliefs
    You can attempt to hold two opposites in your mind as true, or at least equally uncertain, but at the end of the day, you must act as if one is true.AlmostOutlier

    I think this is exactly what we do all the time, except without the "equally" bit. It's highly likely the ground you walk on will support your weight, so you walk on it as if it will, as if you know it will. But you know no such thing, and the occasional sinkhole makes this point forcefully.

    The analogy I always reach for is wagering: you may figure the Cubs have a 62% chance of winning tonight, but you have to bet as if they will or won't. Confidence may fall along a gradient, but action is binary: you can kinda think the Cubs will win tonight, but you can't kinda bet.

    The notion of picking beliefs strikes me as oxymoronic and disingenuous, like picking where you were born, your age, or who you'll bump into today.Sapientia

    I'm very sympathetic to this view. It does leave me with a bit of a puzzle though. If we do not choose our beliefs, should we say they are caused? In some scenarios that seems okay; perception seems like this.

    But what about reasoning? Suppose A being the case makes it that B is. Then we would customarily say that believing A is a reason for believing B, that if you think A likely, for instance, then you should think B likely.

    What do we mean by "should" there? That suggests you could choose to reason this way or not. Does that leave us saying you cannot choose simpliciter to believe B, but you can choose to conclude B by reasoning? Would you then be choosing to cause yourself to believe that B?
  • On 'rule-following'
    a strange time zoneBitter Crank

    Saw what you did there.
  • On 'rule-following'
    Are they indoctrinated (in some negative sense) to an individual through repetition and training? Would this be the primary function of 'schools' and 'education'?Posty McPostface

    Is teaching my daughter how to use a hammer indoctrinating her?
  • Predicates, Smehdicates

    That's a nice summary. Chance and necessity make a nice pair of terms in which to explain everything, but I would imagine you could tell a similar story with other pairs (or mores) of fundamental somethings. They all make me uncomfortable, but that's my problem.

    Pierce is interesting, on the one hand, for giving Chance a seat on the dais, right? And then you realize that if we are honest, and serious, about our model-building, it too will have a place for chance, at least as whatever it is our theory doesn't account for, the noise accompanying the precious signal. Now we get to match up the epistemic and ontological, as you've noted, and we can be indifferent to questions like, "Is chance real?" We can posit it, or not, but it will always be in the model either way. And this would be Peirce's pragmatism, yes?

    Oddly, this matching up makes me even more uncomfortable than the Big Theories do on their own. If the big theories already seem to hang in the air (the way a brick doesn't) on the buoyancy of their own internal coherence, this version seems more like jumping and forgetting to hit the ground.

    Again, my problem. If I've understood, what most convinces you you're on the right track is what gives me the willies, which is curious. As always, I appreciate your patience with my questions.
  • Whole is greater than the sum of its parts
    Can we identify a case where the " The whole is LESS than the sum of the parts?"malcolm

    The United States Congress.

    Edit: possibly also the Los Angeles Dodgers.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    The "map" is of the very fact that accidents accumulate to form the regularity of habitsapokrisis

    This pattern I like very much, and I'm totally on board there.

    But since we're talking metaphysics, do you have any qualms about the word "fact" here? What kind of fact? Are we forced to call such accumulation itself either accidental or necessary?

    I would like to think this is where pragmatism slots into the story, but I don't quite get it. (Metaphysics just not my thing, as you know all too well.)
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    Sure history is full of accidents. But if these accidents can accumulate, then they become the constraints that act in the present to limit the accidents of the future.

    They are no longer accidents once they become part of the constraints that prevail
    apokrisis

    That makes nice sense. Yesterday's chance is today's necessity. I understood your project to be pushing back or outward to ever greater generality, to the "purely" necessary. I guess if that's only an ideal, you'll be mapping the ossified accidental just like the rest of us. I suppose that's the sense of mapping "from the inside", as you put it.

    So you are simply attempting to make an analogy the worst possible by abusing it in the worst way you can imagine.apokrisis

    Really not. Since what is essential depends on the purpose of the map, I couldn't see what a truly generic map could be. Since what today is a constraint might not have been, I couldn't see what a map of only the necessary would be. Your response helps. I still don't quite get the big picture, but I'm good for now.

    Carry on.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates

    My thought here was that the usefulness of a map is showing you what roads happen actually to exist connecting features you're interested in that also happen to exist, and it shows where the features and roads actually happen to be. You could abstract away location, distance, and so on, and just show the connections -- but this town and that city and the road that connects them are still matters of accidental history.

    Constraints would only show you what connections could exist, where they could be, etc. We need to know which ones actually obtain.

    Granted some features are considered essential to a map, in the sense that they're included when others aren't or needn't be, but it seemed to me those included features are still historical and accidental -- this town might not exist, there might not be a road between these two, etc.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    It is just like real maps - the kind you use to get around.apokrisis

    This is just a metaphor, so whatever, but there are other kinds of maps.

    the simplest map just tells you where are the obstacles, where are the pathsapokrisis

    And that might be simplest for the kind of map you're talking about. But your idea seems to be there is a purest sort of map, a perfectly general and generic map, and that's just goofy, since what you choose to include in your map is obviously driven by your purpose in drawing it. The stuff you talk about leaving out is the stuff other people want.

    In regards to the contrast between lived life and metaphysical maps, a map is created by abstracting away the accidental to arrive at the necessary.

    So actual life is rich because it it rich with a history of accidents, fluctuations, contingencies and particulars.
    apokrisis

    And right there -- if you want your analogy to be to "getting around" maps rather than some other kind, you want the current state of accidental history. Is that bridge still up? Does this surface street go under the new freeway or just dead end there?

    In fact I can't think of any kind of map that isn't based on selecting certain accidental states of affairs to mark and the rest to ignore. There's never any essential/accidental distinguishing such as you describe.

    Sorry -- this just seems like the worst analogy for what you're after.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates

    Now, see, that sounds largely reasonable, in the way that pragmatism always does, if a little empty. What I'm struggling to get across is the oddity of your position, and it's probably just the Peirce thing.

    On the one hand, there is this sort of messianic quality to your system. From earlier in the post I responded to:

    I agreed that modelling is modelling. But then the larger Peircean story is that modelling constructs its own world. And so the actualised wholeness is itself an emergent from the core semiotic process that is the engine producing any reality.apokrisis

    That doesn't look like the sort of instrumentalist version of pragmatism that this does:

    Pragmatism says "wrongness" is to be expected. The question then becomes whether the wrongness observed as the general is advanced to explain the particular is a case of signal or noise. Is there something significant not being explained? Or are all the inevitable exceptions to the rule just meaningless noise?apokrisis

    The procedure by which we model our world is the same procedure the world is using to be.* Where is pragmatism here? Is reality also getting it wrong the way we do? In which case, the noise in our models is also signal, and what sense now can be given to "wrong"? If you put "wrongness" in scare-quotes, is this still pragmatism?


    * What's more, projecting this structure onto nature was the "leap of faith" that was said to work. Why does it all look a bit like Anselm's ontological argument?
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    I've said nature itself is irreducibly telic. There is always finality or a goal in play.apokrisis

    And that's just not enough to start talking about what "works".

    Here's the last part of the quote I started with:

    we are projecting a view of ourselves as rational beings on to the apparent rational structure we see in the world. That is quite a leap of faith.

    However - pragmatism again - suck it and see. Leaps of faith become justified to the extent they appear to work.
    apokrisis

    Work to do what? Are we talking about the cosmos's goal of observing itself, or maybe its goal of reducing free energy? Wouldn't not making this projection accelerate the heat death of the universe just as well as making it?

    You might have said such a leap is permitted -- no constraint prevents it -- so it's inevitable that we do. But instead you said it's justified insofar as it works. And again I ask: what's the goal here that grounds this talk of what works? And whose goal is it?
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    So in all your examples, there are laid out certain constraints - which presumably are meant to achieve some effective action. And yet the actions look to defy them. A "wrong" procedure is employed to reach the apparent goal.apokrisis

    Nope. In each of my examples, the agent tasked with a specific goal chose instead to pursue a different goal, and in each case the initial goal could be taken as a means for achieving the new goal. But since there were other means available too, the agent can achieve the new goal without achieving the one they were tasked with.

    The point was to show how the agent's judgment that what they did "works" could be faulty, unless some goal is taken as the goal relative to which a judgment of effectiveness is made.

    Yet another example: suppose I'm trying to prepare for an exam, but my roommate decides to have some friends over for a party. When I remind him I have a test and complain about the noise, he says, "Well, you could go to the library, or -- you could come to the party. Check it out! I bought a copy of the test so you wouldn't have to study tonight."

    See the difference here? The suggestion that I go to the library accepts my goal of studying effectively and suggests an alternative method of achieving that goal. The suggestion that I cheat substitutes the goal of getting a good grade, which admittedly was what I wanted to achieve by studying, but it bypasses what I have chosen to take as my immediate goal. If you want to judge what "works", you have to settle first what the goal is, and in many cases whose goal it is.

    That is what I've been asking you to clarify. How your occasional appeals to a pragmatic "this, because it works" slot into your system. Works to do what? To study effectively or to get a good grade? And whose goals are we talking about?
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    the strangeness of your scenarioapokrisis

    Here's another: A wedding planner tells one of the staff to put a certain flower arrangement on the dining table, and the ice sculpture on another table. The staff person decides to swap the indicated locations "because it looks better this way." Be that as it may, and whether the event planner agrees, the staff person cannot be said to have done what they were told.

    But if the father's constraint was to find paid labourapokrisis

    It clearly was. Leave aside the robbery. Suppose the son just doesn't get a job. When his father asks, here is his answer: "If by 'get a job', you mean, did I follow the principle of least action, the principle of locality, and the second law of thermodynamics, all with an eye to Salthe's basic triadic system -- then 'yes'; if you mean, do I now have gainful employment, then 'no'." The son may effectively be accelerating the heat death of the universe, but he cannot be said to have a job.

    You are relying on a highly artificial demarcation that seeks to stop us saying anything else about the situation.apokrisis

    "Did you get a job?" is a yes-or-no question. Humans do highly artificial stuff.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    You've lost me. How could that have been the gist of your argument?apokrisis

    I posted it twice:

    Whatever the merits of that view, and they may be considerable, it cannot be said that he succeeded at getting a job.Srap Tasmaner

    And thus the gist of my argument was:

    did the son follow a procedure that is effective in achieving the goal of getting a job.Srap Tasmaner

    And the answer is "no", no matter what else we say about the situation.

    ***

    My point was that effectiveness at achieving a goal at one level may not always count as effectiveness at achieving a goal on another level. It's a question about how exactly you attach the pragmatist appeal to the effectiveness of a procedure to the hierarchical/holistic/systems science analysis. I'm still not clear on that, which may be my fault.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    Bonus example: I tell Sid to put his tools away; half an hour later I find little sister Hannah putting the tools away (no doubt because Sid threatened to decapitate her favorite doll unless she did). Sid's defence is "What does it matter who does it, so long as the tools get put away?" But it was his task to perform himself, not simply to make it that the task was performed. That kid's never going to learn how to be responsible ...
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    On your version - when forced to provide an intelligible rationale of the context in play - the son says it is all about the least action path to get that money. Jobs and robbery are not meaningfully distinct ... despite social norms that exist because of a larger scale social effectiveness. In the son's view, the father's attempt to draw a distinction is a quite arbitrary one on his own personal scale of being. Jobs or robbery is being claimed as a difference that should make no difference.apokrisis

    Then the "we" that should apply in your example becomes the social norms in play. A son that robs convenience stores is far more likely to come from a family and neighbourhood that robs convenience stores. The choice of a least action path to a goal would not really need much further justification.

    But given your scenario, the father would be asserting some larger social norm as the "we" with the view on what is effective for that "we". We are law abiding and employed as that is a desire embedded at a cultural level, representing whatever happens to be functionally effective as a generalised habit.
    apokrisis

    Nope.

    Whatever the merits of that view, and they may be considerable, it cannot be said that he succeeded at getting a job.Srap Tasmaner

    Full stop. I said nothing about norms, and gave no broader justification for the father's view. I thought of all that, because duh, but none of it is relevant to this single question: did the son follow a procedure that is effective in achieving the goal of getting a job. The answer to that is quite clearly, I submit, "no".

    So I see no reason to give up the idea that effectiveness is tied to the achievement of specific goals, or carrying out specific tasks, and that even if those goals can be subsumed under other goals, effectiveness at achieving the higher goal does not pass through to the lower.

    I heard a story once about an overnight shelving crew at a grocery store that knew the president of the company was visiting the next day: they weren't going to be able to finish getting the truck worked, so to avoid getting in trouble they threw a pallet of groceries in the big trash compactor.

    The pattern here is similar: reinterpret the instruction to shelve everything as an instruction to leave nothing in the back. Reinterpret the instruction to get a job as an instruction to get money.

    In some cases, that's fine. Maybe the instruction was unnecessarily specific. In the cases at hand, it's clearly a self-serving dodge. But none of this matters at all. Even in the acceptable cases, you'd be renegotiating the instruction; there's still no question at all about whether you did in fact achieve the goal you were directed to -- you didn't. Whether that's okay is another matter entirely.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    The Cosmos only appears to be solidly there because it is - in some literal sense - observing itself. It exists as a globalised matrix of constraints on undirected local possibility.

    Now the rejoinder is obvious. Quantum mechanics doesn't account for human feelings.

    But I made the argument there too. Semiotics originated in phenomenology. It is rooted in the mechanics of human intelligibility. So it doesn't exactly leave the phenomenal out of it. Instead it accepts the full Kantian force of that and then builds back out so as to recover the noumenal - rescuing it via this idea of a core relational structure that acconts for intelligibility itself.

    I can see the vulnerability that creates. Yes, we are projecting a view of ourselves as rational beings on to the apparent rational structure we see in the world. That is quite a leap of faith.

    However - pragmatism again - suck it and see. Leaps of faith become justified to the extent they appear to work.
    apokrisis

    One question I'd like to raise regards this sense of effectiveness. Effectiveness is task-relative, to start with; there's no such thing as generic effectiveness. What's more, even if a given task slots into some hierarchy, effectiveness doesn't automatically cross those boundaries.

    Example: father tells his son he needs to get a job; son goes out and robs a convenience store. When the father objects, the son's defence is that the whole point of getting a job was to get money, so he just got money a different way. Whatever the merits of that view, and they may be considerable, it cannot be said that he succeeded at getting a job.

    So I'm wondering what task you have in mind when you reference this pragmatic sense of effectiveness, and whose task it is. Does this task belong to the "we" you reference, or to the cosmos?
  • In what sense do languages evolve?

    Linguistic evolution appears to be at least partially Lamarckian, and that's interesting. I doubt that it is entirely so, but who knows.
  • In what sense do languages evolve?
    Evolution connotes some kind of progression towards a goalTheMadFool

    Ick.

    - adapting to the pressures of the language environment.TheMadFool

    I deliberately said nothing about adaptation.

    Adaptation comes into biological evolution because there is an expectation that individuals better adapted to their environment are more likely to survive and (therefore) more likely to reproduce. That's not an exclusive deal, because sexual selection is a thing. But the point is always reproduction and surviving by being "fit" is just a means to an end. Natural selection predicts adaptation, for this very reason, but doesn't actually care. All that matters is that some individuals out-compete other individuals of their species in having their genes represented in the next generation. Reproduce more and you win. If adaptation helps, then that explains adaptation.

    It's not clear to me that there is a similar story to tell about linguistic evolution. Reproduction in language, like talk -- because it is just talk -- is cheap. Almost preposterously cheap.

    Of course there are selection pressures -- @frank gave a reasonable example of what that looks like, and that stuff is interesting. In nature, the penalty for a mutation that doesn't pan out is pretty harsh -- you die and you take all your genes with you, making it a little less likely that even the non-mutants will win in the next generation. In language, if a new usage (or whatever) doesn't catch on, oh well. It dies on the vine and the vine can keep churning out new grapes.
  • In what sense do languages evolve?

    We're there? Sweet.

    Btw, I live in the bible belt and a friend of mine who's a linguistics PhD has had encounters with people who accept linguistic but not biological evolution! He was in the position of arguing, "But you accept this with language, why ... ?"

    It's a strange world.
  • In what sense do languages evolve?

    It does seem more natural to say that my idiolect today is a descendant of, to start with, my idiolect, say, twenty years ago. At what point did I learn the word "idiolect", for instance?

    What's clear though is that we're talking about differential reproduction, exactly as we do in biological evolution by natural selection, and that these changes in idiolects "sum" to changes in their species over time, and perhaps also to speciation. (The last being a can of worms I don't care to open right now.)
  • In what sense do languages evolve?
    If it's the same process, then we would have to say that natural selection isn't too significant in language evolution (due to low population size).frank

    Except that it's obviously mainly natural selection. And you can see other stuff like drift when a population is geographically isolated, etc.

    There are going to be some differences between biological evolution and linguistic evolution. Because the method of reproduction is so different, there isn't quite the same genotype/phenotype issue there is in biology, for instance. There's some stuff there I guess but that's linguistics I'm none too confident about.

    To your specific point: I think you're matching things up wrong. A language is a species, not an individual organism. The counterpoint to an individual organism would be an idiolect, and maybe even a snapshot of an idiolect. In either case, you're not talking about small populations at all.

    Some guy says to his friend, "That girl you were out with last night was 14-karat." Maybe he just saw a jewelry ad. His friend might like this expression and use it now & then. It could catch on in their circle and spread. Or maybe not. What's reproducing here is an idiolect that includes this usage of "14-karat". If nobody likes it, it could immediately go extinct. The idiolect is a member of the species English.

    Is this making sense? It was my understanding that this isn't remotely controversial within linguistics, but I haven't done any googling since this thread started.
  • In what sense do languages evolve?

    There's a structural isomorphism between the two processes, biological and linguistic evolution, so it's more than an analogy.

    Look at how Latin (or camp Latin) speciates into the romance languages. You're looking at an accumulation of changes in frequency of pronunciations, meanings, spellings, etc.

    Where biology relies on biological reproduction, languages have something else, this is true. But usages and pronunciations and the rest do get reproduced or not within a community. Some words catch on. Some meanings, etc. Some don't. And over time the language changes. Languages have descendants, go extinct, all the rest.
  • In what sense do languages evolve?

    There are multiple phenomena you can look at: changes in pronunciation, in meaning, in whatever the word is for degree of "elevatedness", etc. All of these follow a similar pattern. Changes in the frequency with which a community is using an allophone, for example, slots into the math where biology would have changes in the frequency of an allele. And that's why languages form family trees much like species. A hypothetical language like proto-indo-european is a most recent common ancestor just like biologists talk about.
  • Communicating with the world
    We start with raw interaction.frank

    Well that's a question, right?

    Your OP was based in part on the idea that this is something we do, that we're wired to do, to structure our experience as conversation. That leaves room for the idea that we more or less project this structure onto the rest of the world (or our experience of it). Projecting structure in this way is a mainstream issue for epistemology, most especially from Kant forward. And in this particular version, there are people we can point to who do project voices onto the rest of the world: we call them schizophrenics. That leaves a choice for how you proceed: do you propose a view that encompasses "hearing voices" as a variation of some kind on what we all do?
  • Communicating with the world
    I want to focus on negotiationfrank

    So start there. One way of thinking about a person's interaction with the rest of the world, is to note that the rest of world resists and surprises. If you falsely believe that boulder will never roll down the hill onto your house, when it does your belief becomes untenable.

    So to keep with your approach, you tell the world what you're thinking and it might agree, disagree, or say nothing. Or something else. It has some input, and you revise your belief to take that input into account.

    David Berkowitz believed his neighbor's dog told him to kill. Something has gone wrong in the negotiation here.
  • Communicating with the world

    I think you'll also want to be able to distinguish between your dog telling you she wants to go out and your dog telling you to kill the president.
  • Communicating with the world
    Could you say more about this?frank

    For an easy example, languages actually, literally evolve. No metaphor.

    Do you have a Grice reading recommendation?frank

    Studies in the Way of Words.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    Thinking of them in terms of equivalence classes adds an extra layer of complexity for little gainfdrake

    Maybe so, but it's a structure I'm fond of, and it gets close to my intuition of classifying as taking a shortcut. You see that this rock is similar to that one in ways that matter to you, so maybe what worked for moving that one will work for moving this one. (But maybe not for lots of reasons.)

    It's a learned behavior. When kids are just starting to read (already knowing their letters and how to talk) they treat each word as a unique challenge to be sounded out or guessed at, even if they've already read that word several times, even on the same page. Learning to see words as tokens of types is learning how to take a shortcut -- say what you said last time and see if dad corrects you or makes you try again. (The move from attention to habit.)

    Eventually we learn, one can hope, how to be careful with how we classify, with the cognitive shortcuts we take.
  • Communicating with the world

    I'm on board. I think this could be a really fruitful idea to explore. Couple points:

    1. Sometimes you can find that a metaphor or an analogy works because the things compared share an underlying mechanism that is literally, not figuratively, the same. This is always worth investigating.

    2. From the other direction, there is Grice's theory that grounds "non-natural meaning", the way the English word "cloud" means [[cloud]], in "natural meaning", the way dark clouds mean it's going to rain. Most folks shy away from connecting those directly as he does.

    3. Some of us do speak to things regularly. (When I find something where it shouldn't be, there's a fair chance I'll speak to it --"You're not supposed to be there," "What are you doing here?" -- that sort of thing.) Why do we do that?

    4. There are lots of idioms that recognize what you're talking about: listen to what your body is telling you, numbers don't lie (i.e., they tell the truth), etc.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    If there is a type-token distinction that is parsed in some way and not another, it can only be with an eye to doing something with it; one fixes distinctions in place so as to be able to make intelligible moves in discourse.StreetlightX

    I keep circling around what I think of as a thoroughly naturalist and nominalist approach something like this: the difference between, say, a particular triangle and an "abstract" triangle is not that the latter is a different sort of object at all. The "abstract" triangle is still a particular, the one you imagine, the one printed in the book or drawn on the blackboard. The difference is in how you handle it. If you ignore none of its particularity, that might be taking it, say, as a work of art. But if you ignore many of its particular features -- its particular materiality, the thickness of its lines, etc. -- then you can treat it as an abstract triangle.

    @Nagase can answer this view though quite readily by pointing out that I am now relying on types or classes of actions to explain (away) types or classes of objects. Can I then try to explain these away following the same procedure? It looks like any attempt to avoid classes and types altogether is doomed to fail, even if we can avoid treating them as objects per se.

    And there's an analogy here, perhaps more than an analogy, to the problem of talking about concepts. Frege himself makes the point several times that when you talk about a concept, you're treating it as an object, so you're never talking about the concept as concept. That you cannot do; you can only show how it works. (I'm also convinced that no Fregean should think propositions are objects.)

    Where I want to end up is with an explanation of how the ideal actually comes to have a role in our lives. Grice speculates that maybe we never quite mean anything, in the strictest sense, but we approach the ideal of meaning something and deem that success. Lewis also, in Convention, reaches the surprising conclusion that maybe no one ever does speak a language in the Fregean sense -- again, we only approach this as an ideal. We huddle together in vaguely defined equivalence classes speaking languages that are near kin to each other. (And then there's Davidson: "We must give up the idea of a clearly defined shared structure which language-users acquire and then apply to cases. And we should try again to say how convention in any important sense is involved in language; or, as I think, we should give up the attempt to illuminate how we communicate by appeal to conventions." My bias is showing but how do you get away with that last clause in a paper that doesn't so much as mention David Lewis?)

    That appeal to equivalence classes again looks like it demands something we've just said we can't have, real ideals, real types to ground the equivalence, and that backing off to our practices instead is no help. My suspicion is that it does help because the project of communal living gives you a choice: provisionally deem someone to be speaking a language you can understand or give up.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    So if we say speakers of a shared language with a shared neurologyapokrisis

    Should have addressed that. The full version is: "If you don't know that's red, either you don't speak English or there's something wrong with you."
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    And the actual story is that both levels of semiosis are constraints on our habits of interpretance.apokrisis

    That's the lines I was thinking along, but it's hard to say "When you talk about concepts you're also talking about how we use words" (details to be filled in) without it coming off as "When you talk about concepts you're only talking about how we use words." (And to top it off: when you talk about things, you're only talking about "our" concepts of things. Yuck.)

    This tangent is strangely on-topic.
  • Predicates, Smehdicates
    Not if you just assert that the apple is red to speakers with a shared neurology. No need to take things to the Whorfian extreme on colour perception.apokrisis

    I just can't get on board with the Whorf-Sapir thing. I know there's still controversy, but I like to think of it as refuted for color perception.

    I think LW had a bit about "Because I speak English" being a perfectly good answer to "How do you know that's red?" A little like Austin answering "How do you know that tree is real?" with "Well, it's not fake."

    In one sense this is just annoying, a sort of pretended obtuseness. So my reasonable sentence above ("This is red to speakers of English") turns out to be an explanation of how the word "red" is used, not an explanation of how perception works.

    But I have some residual affection for this move, and I think it might be because it is sort of anti-Whorfian. There's a presumption that whoever you are and wherever you're from, you can't really be struggling with the concept of [red], so you must need help with the word "red". (There's something else here but I can't quite put my finger on it. Will mull ...)