ARGUMENTS AGAINST SOCRATES’ ATHEISM
Socrates was tried and sentenced to death by taking poison for “morally corrupting the youth” and for “impiety toward the Gods”.
With regard to religion, the exact charges reportedly were:
He does not believe in the gods the state believes in, but in other new spiritual beings (Pl. Apol. 24b-c)
His adversaries had charged him with not believing in the gods worshipped by the state and with the introduction of new deities in their stead (Xen. Apol. 10)
And Socrates’ own statement:
For he says I am a maker of gods; and because I make new gods (kainoi Theoi) and do not believe in the old ones (Pl. Euthyph. 3b)
Socrates’ main accusers were Anytus and Meletus who represented groups of people that held a grudge against Socrates. Anytus was a wealthy and powerful Athenian politician from a family of wealthy tanners, who had been angered by Socrates’ remarks about famous men being unable to teach virtue to their sons (
Meno 94e), and by Socrates’ advice not to let his son follow a career in the family trade (Xen.
Apol. 29).
Anytus is also said to have initiated the corruption of the judiciary by bribing the jury in a court case brought against him for a military fiasco in which he lost the city of Pylos (Aristot.
Ath. Pol. 27).
According to Hermogenes who was present at Socrates' trial:
The Athenian courts have often been carried away by an eloquent speech and have condemned innocent men to death, and often on the other hand the guilty have been acquitted either because their plea aroused compassion or because their speech was witty (Xen. Apol. 5)
It can be seen from this that the fact that Socrates was indicted, tried, and found guilty, does not necessarily mean that he was guilty as charged.
If Socrates had simply been a known atheist, then (a) he would not have been allowed to preach his views for many years (he was in fact taken to court late in his life and by people who clearly had a grudge against him), and (b) it would have been in the prosecution’s interest to make his alleged atheism part of their case.
In Xenophon’s Apology, Socrates himself states after the trial that “the witnesses were instructed that they must bear false witness against me, perjuring themselves to do so” (
24).
Socrates knew many people and likely had reliable information to make such a claim.
In addition, there seems to be no independent tradition according to which Socrates was an atheist.
This suggests that the charge of atheism may not be as credible as it seems.
Is there any positive evidence to indicate that he was not an atheist?
1. The accusation of “making new Gods” may itself be such an indication. Making Gods does not necessarily mean inventing non-existent entities. Artisans in Ancient Greece made images or statues of Gods in whom they actually believed. Following ceremonial dedication, a statue was treated as if living and was inhabited by the deity during epiphany. Similarly, when the Israelites made a gold image of a calf which they worshiped, as described in Exodus, they did not invent the deity, they simply made a religious representation of it (possibly under Canaanite or Egyptian influence). Socrates himself did not make concrete images but he made literary images in his speeches about demons, Cosmic Gods, and Forms, i.e., entities he apparently believed in.
In a speech about Socrates in Plato’s Symposium, Alcibiades compares him with a Silenius statue full of words that are like divine images that mesmerize the audience like the song of a Siren, Alcibiades himself feeling left “in a condition of a common slave”:
Whether anyone else has caught him in a serious moment and opened him, and seen the images inside, I know not; but I saw them one day, and thought them so divine and golden, so perfectly fair and wondrous, that I simply had to do as Socrates bade me (Sym. 216e-217a)
It is not difficult to see how speeches about Socrates’ Siren-like words being like “divine images” that captivated the minds of younger men, could inspire rumors of his “corrupting the youth by making new Gods”.
2. During trial, Meletus claims that Socrates does not believe in the Sun and Moon or any other deities.
However, Socrates first points out that (a) the claim that the Sun and Moon are stone and earth is Anaxagoras’, not his own and (b) that his alleged disbelief in any deities contradicts the original claim that he believes in new Gods:
I am glad that I have extracted that answer, by the assistance of the court; nevertheless you swear in the indictment that I teach and believe in divine or spiritual agencies (new or old, no matter for that); at any rate, I believe in spiritual agencies, as you say and swear in the affidavit; but if I believe in divine beings, I must believe in spirits or demigods; - is not that true? Yes, that is true, for I may assume that your silence gives assent to that. Now what are spirits or demigods? are they not either gods or the sons of gods? Is that true?
[Jury] Yes, that is true.
But this is just the ingenious riddle of which I was speaking: the demigods or spirits are gods, and you say first that I don't believe in gods, and then again that I do believe in gods; that is, if I believe in demigods.
Indeed, in the Phaedo, Socrates recounts to his friends how he had long distanced himself from Anaxagoras’ materialist teachings that he found unsatisfactory and disappointing (
Phaedo 98b-c).
He now says:
At any rate, I believe in spiritual agencies, as you say and swear in the affidavit; but if I believe in divine beings, I must believe in spirits or demigods; - is not that true?
[Jury] Yes, that is true (Apology)
3. Socrates’ statement that he believes in spiritual entities is consistent with numerous other statements in the Phaedo, Gorgias, Republic, etc. For example, he says that the soul is immortal and that those who believe this and care for their soul should take his account of afterlife or something like it as true (
Phaedo 114d). He says that he is convinced of divine judgement after death and urges all men to join him in this belief in order to save themselves in the other world (
Gorgias 526e). He repeats this in the Republic (
621c), etc.
4. According to his own statement at trial, Socrates took part in public sacrifices to the Gods:
One thing that I marvel at in Meletus, gentlemen, is what may be the basis of his assertion that I do not believe in the gods worshiped by the state; for all who have happened to be near at the time, as well as Meletus himself,—if he so desired, — have seen me sacrificing at the communal festivals and on the public altars … For it has not been shown that I have sacrificed to new deities in the stead of Zeus and Hera and the gods of their company, or that I have invoked ill oaths or mentioned other gods. (Xen. Apol. 11, 25)
In Memorabilia, Xenophon states that Socrates always offered sacrifices at home and at public temple altars (
1.1.2), suggesting that it is hard to believe that someone who devoutly performs religious rites does not believe in the Gods in whose honor he performs the rites.
5. This, and other instances throughout Plato’s dialogues seem to be inconsistent with atheism. For example:
Socrates tells Critias to carry on his discourse by invoking the aid of Apollo and the Muses (
108c).
Socrates prays to the Cosmos (as a God) to grant them the knowledge to provide a truthful account (
106b).
Socrates invokes the aid of the Muses in making his first speech on love (
Phaedr. 237a)
Socrates refers to the Sun as “one of the Gods in heaven” (
Rep. 508a).
Socrates is said to have prayed to the Sun at sunrise after a long contemplation (
Symp. 220d).
6. In Apology, Socrates concludes his address to the jury with the following statements:
But you also, judges, must regard death hopefully and must bear in mind this one truth, that no evil can come to a good man either in life or after death, and God does not neglect him (41c-d).
I go to die, and you to live; but which of us goes to the better lot, is known to none but God (42a).
On balance, Socrates seems to hold religious beliefs that are similar to those of Athens’ intellectual classes. Yes, he does advocate examination of one’s beliefs in general, which is only natural as he believes in intelligence and knowledge, but he does not seem to advocate that people discard all their religious beliefs.
In particular, Socrates does seem to connect wisdom with some spiritual or divine agency. Even his own quest for wisdom is said to have been prompted by a statement attributed to the God Apollo.
More generally, what we must not overlook is that religious beliefs were quite common among ancient philosophers, and it seems unwarranted to assume that they, and Socrates, were secret atheists.
Further reading:
Mark L. McPherran, The Religion of Socrates
Darrel Jackson, “The Prayers of Socrates”
James A. Notopoulos, “Socrates and the Sun”