Comments

  • Quine: Reference and Modality
    Then how are you supposed to update your ignorance when you encounter new evidence?Apustimelogist

    Knowledge is represented in terms of

    1) A deductive system, that apart from the logical connectives is comprised only of constants, sets, types and functions, e.g such as a model of a road network.

    2) Statistics that report how the deductive system is used, e.g traffic statistics.

    It makes no sense to represent ignorance. To me that's a contradiction in terms.

    Structural Equation Models are another reasonable example, provided one steers clear of non-informative priors and sticks to making deductions rather than making inductive inferences; Personally, I think Bayes rule should only be used when inferring a conditional distribution of a known multivariate distribution, for what does it mean to say that " Hypothesis A is inductively twice as probable as Hypothesis B when conditioning on an observation"?

    It doesn't, at least not in the Principle of Indifference as described by Leplace, Keynes, etc. It's the simplest non-informative prior. Obviously, it cannot be applied to all cases, rather a special set of them. But the general reasoning used here tends to be at work in more complex non-informative priors.Count Timothy von Icarus

    The Principle of Indifference is supposed to be a normative principle for assigning probabilities on the basis of ignorance. As soon as a non-informative prior is used, posterior probabilities are epistemically meaningless in general, even if their distributions are useful for convergent machine learning.

    The way i interpret non-informative priors is in terms of the following analogy:

    Imagine using a net to catch a fish in a lake. Using a big net that covers the entire surface of the lake is analogous to using a non-informative prior. Reeling in the net to obtain the fish is then analogous to Bayesian updating. But would you really want to say that the net represents your indifference as to where the fish is? rather, isn't the net simply part of a mechanical procedure for ensuring the fish is caught, irrespective of your state of mind?

    - Perhaps a Bayesian will remark that the net represents the fisherman's credence as to where the fish is. I think my reply would be to say that the meaning of "the fisherman's credence" should be given in terms of where the net is, rather than the meaning of the net being in terms of "the fisherman's credence" which I have no prior understanding of.

    Also, why choose the simplest prior? Occams Razor? what justifies the use of that?
    In fact, if one isn't interested in asymptotic Bayesian convergence and has no frequency information, then why use a prior at all? Why not just stick to saying what one knows or assumes, and gamble without saying anything else?
  • Quine: Reference and Modality
    Kolmogorov's axioms effectively define probability in terms of a collection of sets of possible worlds, together with a probability function that maps those sets of possible worlds to values in the unit interval, where the accessibility relation between worlds is implicitly represented by one's design choices. As for whether the probability function denotes logical or frequential probability, this depends on how the probability function is defined.

    If the probability function is defined so as to quantify the mathematical proportion of possible worlds having a particular property, then we are dealing with logical probability, but not necessarily frequential probability. For example, if there are three possible worlds of different colours, then why should the existence of these three distinct possibilities automatically imply that each colour is equally likely or frequent? In my opinion, the fallacy that logical probability implies frequential or even epistemic probability is what gave rise to the controversial and frankly embarrassing Principle of Indifference.

    On the other hand if the probability function is chosen to represent non-mathematical facts concerning observational frequencies, then we have frequentialist probability but not logical probability.

    In my opinion, there is no such thing as epistemic probability or propensity probability, because I think that the belief-interpretation of probability consist of a poorly articulated muddle of logical probability, frequential probability, and unarticulated subjective bias that at best expresses the mental state of the analyst rather then the phenomena he is predicting; of course mental states and reality are sometimes correlated but not always.

    The best way of expressing ignorance with regards to the likelihood of a possible outcome is simply to refrain from assigning a probability, and the best way of using Bayesian methods is to interpret them as inferring frequency information from logical information expressed in the design of the sigma algebra over the sample space, plus observational frequency information expressed in the probability measure.
  • "Underlying Reality" for Husserl
    I would regard the presumption that other beings are like myself as apodictic. I wouldn’t be so egotistical as to believe otherwise. And real life is not a hypothetical exercise.Wayfarer

    It depends what you mean by apodictic. Anti-realism doesn't necessarily deny the possibility of logical certainty with regards to the existence of other minds - on the contrary, if 'other' minds are considered to refer to a psychological aspect of the observer who interprets phenomena , then anti-realism could provide a more compelling account than Cartesian minded realism as to why the existence of other minds cannot be denied. On the other hand, such apodicity would be relative to the observer, perhaps with one observer insisting that a chat bot is conscious and the other insisting otherwise, without there existing an observer-transcendent matter of fact to settle the issue.
  • "Underlying Reality" for Husserl
    Anyway it makes perfect intuitive sense to me. Even though I don't know other people in the same way I know myself, I know they are persons like myself. 'Husserl explores this through the concept of empathy (Einfühlung). He suggests that we "appresent" or co-present the other’s mind: we perceive another body as similar to our own and, by analogy, attribute to it a consciousness like ours.' I've often opined that empathy is the natural antidote to solipsism.Wayfarer

    Certainly empathy is an antidote to psychological solipsism. But does empathy refer to other minds 'in themselves' that possess an existence that is independent of one's experiences of empathy? Didn't Husserl appreciate that methodological solipsism cannot establish the metaphysical realism of other minds?

    If we consider borderline cases in the animal kingdom or in AI, the public make wildly different judgements as to the sentience that they ascribe to the entities concerned. Suppose that Alice and Bob are two equally brilliant and informed cognitive scientists who nevertheless disagree as to the sentience they each ascribe to a borderline case 'X'. Are they disagreeing about the same thing? Or is their disagreement akin to an aesthetic disagreement about X that isn't expected to have an objective answer?
    According to the anti-realist, Alice and Bob's disagreement as to the sentience of X is only an objective disagreement in so far that their disagreement is the product of different scientific understandings of X. So if Bob and Alice are assumed to have a full and equal scientific understanding of X but nevertheless disagree as to its sentience, then the anti-realist considers their disagreement to be a subjective disagreement that only expresses the fact that Alice and Bob are in different psychological relationships to X. The anti-realist can consider disagreements over the sentience of X to be ethically important, without considering the disagreements to have epistemological or metaphysical significance, at least not from a public perspective.
  • "Underlying Reality" for Husserl
    Does Husserl believe in the existence of other minds in the literal sense of other?

    I posed that question to Grok, which returned the following slop(?)

    "Husserl didn’t deny the existence of other minds outright; rather, he approached the issue phenomenologically, focusing on how we experience and constitute the "other" within consciousness. He argued that we cannot directly access another person’s mind as we do our own—our own consciousness is given to us immediately through self-awareness. However, he posited that we encounter others indirectly through their bodies, which appear in our perceptual field as more than mere physical objects. This is what he called the experience of "alterity" (otherness).
    In the Fifth Meditation, Husserl explores this through the concept of empathy (Einfühlung). He suggests that we "appresent" or co-present the other’s mind: we perceive another body as similar to our own and, by analogy, attribute to it a consciousness like ours. This isn’t a naive belief or a logical inference but a fundamental structure of experience. For Husserl, the other is not just a theoretical construct; the other’s existence as a minded being is given in a unique, indirect way within our intentional acts.
    So, yes, Husserl did believe in the existence of other minds in a literal sense—as distinct, conscious entities separate from oneself—but he reframed this belief within the limits of phenomenological evidence. He didn’t take it as an unexamined assumption (as in everyday realism) but sought to show how this "otherness" is constituted in our subjective experience without stepping outside his transcendental method."

    I'm not sure that I follow... In my opinion, "other" minds are a misnomer, because i consider my conception of "other" minds to logically reduce to my personal thoughts, feelings and observations. So I accept that "other minds" exist in a manner of speaking, but i am an anti-realist with respect to their existence. Therefore I am not troubled by disagreements or uncertainty with regards to whether a given machine, animal, vegetable or mineral is conscious or not, and I feel no compulsion to settle the matter one way or another. As I understand it, if Bob questions whether Alice has experiences, he is ultimately questioning the course of his experiences, for Bob doesn't possess a concept of Alice's experiences that is distinct from his own.

    Is that what Husserl thought?
  • The Distinct and Inconsistent Reality of a Dream
    How is it possible for me to believe, when I am asleep, that something is real, which is completely distinct from, and inconsistent with, what I believe is real when I am awake?Metaphysician Undercover

    A simple explanation is amnesia; ordinarily, you cannot remember your waking life when dreaming. Hence the reason why wannabe lucid dreamers habitually question whether they are dreaming during their waking lives, in the hope that their habitual questioning will continue when they are dreaming.

    I think an interesting philosophical question is whether lucid dreams should be regarded as being a distinct category of dreams, or whether lucid-dreams should be considered to be an oxymoron that consists of tradeoff between awareness and dreaming, or even whether lucid dreams should be regarded as ordinary dreams in which one merely dreams that one is lucid.

    As Stephen LaBerge famously established, there is at least a behavioural distinction between lucid dreamers and ordinary dreamers, in that dreamers who are lucid can communicate with the outside world during REM sleep. This is coherent with the idea that lucid dreams are a trade-off between dreamfull sleep and wakefulness. Certainly my own lucid dreams are never as creative or as believable as my non-lucid dreams, and I much prefer a creative and inspiring non-lucid dream in which I have no awareness that I am dreaming, over a boring and predictable lucid dream in which I am vigilantly aware that I am dreaming. (Doesn't the "dream AI" always suck in a lucid dream in comparison to an ordinary non lucid dream?)

    However, this behavioural distinction isn't available to the dreamer himself, for the dreamer doesn't have external access to his own physical body from the outside - whether asleep or awake. So in spite of the lucid/non-lucid dream distinction having objective scientific validity, this does not in itself imply that the lucid dreaming/non-lucid dreaming distinction has subjective validity. For all that is available to the dreamer is dream content. So upon waking up from a lucid dream, one is right to ask whether their lucid dream involved actual wakefulness when dreaming, or whether their lucid dream was merely a dream of wakefulness.
  • Ontology of Time
    It isn’t necessary to use a notion of flow to address the necessity of the inclusion of past in the experience of the punctual now. Regardless of whether we attend to a discrete ‘state’ vs a flowing continuum, in either case the ‘now’ we experience includes within it the just past.Joshs

    Sure, but if the psychological past is part of a mutable mental state, then you presumably mean the "just past" in a manner of speaking, in the same way that we might say that a copy of yesterday's newspaper is about the past and Old Moore's Almanac is about the future. In both cases, we are at liberty to provide a definition as to what it means to treat an object as a 'past-referring' record or as a 'future-referring' prediction, that in the final analysis makes no mention of a B series and that reduces to observations and actions that as a matter of tautology can be said to be only of the present.
  • Ontology of Time
    Without awareness of time there is no awareness of the continuity of the flow of experience.Joshs

    I can experience a gradual change of pitch played on a violin (portamento), but I cannot make empirical sense of a flow of "experience" unless the word "experience" is substituted for a given phenomenon, such as the portamento.

    Hypothetically, I think that if I were to fully attend to the portamento, I would no longer have the impression that the portamento consisted of a sequence of particular notes. Conversely, if I were to pay full attention to the notes played, I think that I would no longer hear a portamento but a glissando consisting of a broken sequence of tones.

    The intuition that a phenomenon flows is in conflict with the intuition that the phenomenon is comprised of a sequence of states, as per Zeno's Paradox. So if talk about experience deflates to talk about phenomena, and if the nature of phenomena is relative to how it is attended and phenomena doesn't always flow, then must the existence of phenomena necessitate the a priori existence of a psychological time series?
  • Ontology of Time
    One should always start by mentioning Mctaggart on these sort of topics.

    The Cartesian coordinate system represents movement, in the sense of remembered displacement spatially, in terms of a partial order on the space and time axes. Such pictures include the "Block Universe" that subsumes McTaggart's B series but does not represent any perspectival understanding of time in terms of McTaggart's A series which only makes mention of the indexicals "past" "present" and "future". This is a serious ontological limitation of pure B series reasoning, because any reasoning restricted to the B series which by assumption is an immutable series, cannot serve as a ground for present, past or future experiences, given the fact that the tenses are mutuble.

    McTaggart famously argued that the A series is "unreal", on the basis of what he thought to be logical inconsistency; how can any contingent empirical proposition, say "the cat is presently on the mat", be true when said now but false when said in the past or in the future? For such propositions make no explicit reference to any underlying series. In the end McTaggart failed to find a satisfactory temporal ontology to overcome the issues he raised, but he believed that the A series when taken together with some hypothetical C series that he only partially explicated, could reconstruct the so-called B-series in a non-contradictory fashion. In my primitive understanding, his conception of the C series seems to bear similarities to what are called domains in computer science, which can be thought of as a "growing block" model of accumulated and consistent information. On that interpretation, the B series might itself reduce to some more fundamental concept of consistent and accumulative information.


    In a nutshell, McTaggart meant that time was "unreal" in the Hegelian sense (i.e. still real, but in some other sense than the tenses suggest), as opposed to unreal in the Kantian sense of denying any objectivity with regards to a B series, even in the sense of rationally reconstructed noumenal object (which to many Kantians would amount to a contradiction of Kantian logic).

    As for Wittgenstein, IIRC he once considered the concept of time as being factorizable in terms of a 'subjective' component he called "memory time" and an 'objective' component he called "information time". My impression of the former is that it was a weaker concept than the A series that did not include the 'eternal present' of the Tractatus, and that also did not assume that a person's memories were ordered in the asymmetric and transitive fashion assumed by McTaggart. As for Witty's conception of "information time" it also did not include the eternal present, but seemed to refer to the instrumental usage of concurrency and synchronization, as per a physicist's usage of "time".

    The challenge for the presentist who prioritises the reality of phenomena to the point of denying the reality of the B series, is to reconstruct the B series 'as use', in terms of temporal cognition from the perspective of a solitary individual.
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    Anselm's ontological argument presents a few riddles for cognitive science, and presents a problem for Realism in general.

    Suppose you are a self avowed Realist who is currently in America, and you want to justify making a conceptual distinction between your thoughts about Paris on the one hand, and the actual place called Paris on the other, that you like to think of as 'transcending' your personal experiences. How can you justify your a priori distinction to yourself without appealing to Anselm-like ontological arguments?

    Similarly, when anxious we often like to remind ourselves that our feared imagined future isn't the same thing as the actual future. One way we might convince ourselves of this distinction is by imaging the 'actual future' more vividly and 'realistically' than our feared future. This cognitive therapy, which essentially involves replacing one delusion with another, is the same as the 'step' as in Anselm's ontological argument.

    I would hazard a guess that although people neither need nor use 'reality' in the sense of an all-encompassing and absolute concept in their everyday lives, when pushed into a corner to provide a definition of 'reality' they will offer a circular definition of "reality" very much like the average philosopher, that more or less amounts to the most realistic thing they can conceive, that must 'exist' because nothing greater can be conceived.
  • What does Quine mean by Inscrutability of Reference
    Beliefs are curiously foundational in regard to actions. That I went to the tap to get a glass of water is explained by my belief that the tap was a suitable place to obtain water together with my desire for water. That I believe the tap a source of water is sufficient, regardless of of whether the tap works or not. While it makes sense to ask why I believe the tap a source of water, it is somehow incoherent to ask if I believe the tap to be such a source, given my actions and assertions.Banno

    In computer science, the problem of inverse reinforcement learning can be thought of as the problem of determining what an agent believes on the basis of the regularity of its actions. It is for example used by retail store websites for predicting what consumers want on the basis of their browsing behavior.

    There is a chicken-and-egg problem; for any hypothesis as to what an agent believes is relative to a hypothesis as to what the agent is trying to achieve. And any hypothesis as to what an agent is trying to achieve is relative to a hypothesis as to what the agent believes. But in the end, the notions of beliefs and goal-states are only used for determining a causal model for predicting or controlling agent behavior that only employs the concepts of causation and behavioral conditioning; for once the causal model has been determined, beliefs and goals can be dispensed with entirely, along with the teleological illusion of future-directed behavior.

    So at least according to the algorithmics of machine learning, beliefs and goals aren't foundational when it comes to explaining behavior, rather they are concepts concerning model-fitting strategies for determining behavioural causes and behavioural conditioning.
  • What does Quine mean by Inscrutability of Reference
    I understand the inscrutability of reference, and more generally the indeterminancy of translation to be more or less equivalent to contextualism as opposed to relativism, because semantic indeterminancy is a theory (for want of a better word) of meta-semantics that in effect considers the meaning of a proposition to be relative to the context of the agent who asserts the proposition, and hence the public inability to know what the speaker is referring to - as opposed to relativism that is a theory of truth that considers truth to be relative to the speaker.

    To my understanding, relativism actually presupposes non-contextualism, because it must assumed by relativism that debating communicators are at least talking about the same referents if those referents are to be assigned conflicting properties or truth values by the debaters. On the other hand, if we do not assume that the debaters are referring to the same thing, then we have no basis for inferring that the debate is a disagreement about reality. In fact, I consider relativism to be self-inconsistent (for how can the truth be considered to be relative, either from an individual or collective perspective?). I think relativism is mainly motivated by a lack of appreciation for, or misunderstanding of, the logic of contextualism.

    E.g suppose Bob insists that "The Earth is Flat". Then it is natural to also suppose that at the very least, there exists external physical causes and internal psychological causes for Bob's assertion, but the chances are the topology of the Earth is a negligible causal factor with regards to Bob's assertion, especially if it is assumed that the Earth is Round. So an objective semantic analysis of Bob's assertion cannot use the topology of the Earth as the referent of Bob's assertion.

    Essentially, there is a conflict between

    1) Interpreting a proposition as referring to a given state of affairs, and
    2) Interpreting the proposition as being wrong about that state of affairs.

    For this reason, I suspect that the concept of belief states is inconsistent and that beliefs don't exist in the sense of mental states, such as propositional attitudes.
  • A -> not-A
    "I disagree with regards to ordinary language" I'm not quite getting it, what is the disagreement you have concerning ordinary language? You think someone would make an inference from A->not-A to therefore not-A in ordinary language?NotAristotle

    The formal meaning of negation in intuitionistic logic refers to the syntactical inconsistency of the negated sign, rather than to a purported semantic counterexample denoted by the negated sign. Classical logic inherits the same meaning of negation from intuitionistic logic, except for infinitary propositions that appeal to the Law of Excluded Middle, which have no scientific or commonsensical application. So we should stick to discussing negation in intuitionistic logic, before proceeding to other formal logics such as affine linear logic, whose concept of negation is closer to ordinary use. In such cases (A --> Not A) --> Not A is not derivable, corresponding to the fact that Not A obtains the same semantic status of A.

    But can we elucidate the meaning of (A --> Not A) --> Not A in the systems for which it is valid, by appealing to the mutually exclusive states of the weather? Suppose that a weather forecaster said "It is raining in Hampshire therefore it is not raining in Hampshire". Jokes about the english weather aside, wouldn't you assume that they were talking about anything apart from the weather in Hampshire? in which case your abstaining from assigning a meaning to their words would resonate with the formal meaning of negation in intuitionistic and classical logic.

    As for formalities,

    (A --> ~A) --> ~A is little more than the obvious identity relation ~A --> ~A, due to the fact that ~A is definitionally equal to A --> f , where f denotes absurdity. So we at least have

    (A --> f) --> ~A

    But the only means of obtaining f from A is via the principle of explosion (A And ~A) --> f. And so it is sufficient that A implies ~A.

    (A --> ~A) --> ~A

    And since the converse direction is immediately true, we could in fact define the negation of A to be the fixed point of the expression X => (A --> X) that Haskell programmers call a Reader Monad.

    ~A = A --> ~A
    ~A = (A --> (A --> (A --> ..... ) ))

    which serves to highlight the meaning of Negation As Failure (NAF); A proof of ~A amounts to a finite proof that the right hand side doesn't converge, which represents an infinite failure to prove A by random search. But if we haven't managed to prove either A or ~A using our available time and resources, then we are at liberty to declare ~A by decree and reason accordingly, in which case ~A serves to nullify any hypothesized A by turning it into ~A, so as to ensure consistency with our failure to decide the issue, at least for the time being...
  • A -> not-A
    So in common-sense Kripkean semantics,

    A --> NOT A says: all worlds that satisfy A also satisfy NOT A.

    But in Kripke semantics, a world satisfies NOT A if and only if it doesn't satisfy A. So the set of worlds S that satisfy this condition is empty. A forteriori, there aren't any worlds in S satisfying A. Therefore
    NOT A is true, and A refers to nothing.
  • A -> not-A
    So you would say that a reductio ad absurdum is not an inference in the proper sense?Leontiskos

    It is an inference in the syntactical sense of implication, but not in the semantical sense of implication as ordinarily used by scientists and legal practitioners who are in the business of inferring facts as opposed to uninterpretable sentences.

    In a consistent deductive system , If the sign "Not A" is either taken to be an axiom, or is inferred as a theorem, then it means that the sign "A" is non-referring and hence meaningless in that it fails to denote any element of any possible world among any set of possible worlds that constitutes a model of the axioms. By symmetry, the same could be said of the sign "Not A" being meaningless if A is taken as an axiom, but by model-theoretic traditional the sign A is said to not denote anything in a model if ~A is provable.

    For instance, let the sign "A" denote the proposition that the weather is wet in some possible world. If "A" is deductively assumed or proved, then A is a tautology, meaning that the logical interpretation of "A" is stronger than being a mere possibility and denotes the weather being wet in all possible worlds. On the other hand, if "~A" is provable, then no possible world is wet, in which case the sign "A" fails to refer.

    In conclusion, A and ~A can only both be meaningful if they both stand for possible but unnecessary states of affairs, in which case neither are provable. So the OP's problem isn't a problem, because the signs of the implication A --> ~A aren't simultaneously meaningful.
  • A -> not-A
    If I uttered: "If it is raining then it is not raining." ... If formal logic is "mappable" onto ordinary language, then you should be able to infer "oh okay, it's not raining." But no one speaks like that and no one would make such an inference. At least, no one would consider such an "argument" "valid." That being so, while I would prefer there not to be equivocal definitions of validity, it appears that there are, one formal, the other informal.NotAristotle

    I disagree with regards to ordinary language, because we ordinarily reject contradictory premises for sake of avoiding contradiction; we naturally reject A whenever A implies (B And Not B) for any proposition B.

    One isn't inferring Not A in such cases, rather one is establishing a consistent set of premises for subsequent inferencing. This is reflected by the fact that the case you find to be problematic, is actually an alternative axiom used in the definition of negation in intuitionistic logic.
  • Continuum does not exist
    I believe you should review the definition of Dedekind cuts. First, they can't be open sets, since (as Tones pointed out) L and R are sets of rationals.fishfry

    Yes, and that's what i meant. To explain myself clearer, I meant L and R to refer to open sets of rationals together with the entire set of rationals representing +Inf and the empty set of rationals representing -Inf. I'm not sure why people might have jumped to a different conclusion.

    It is right and necessary to point out as I think you are meaning to imply, that traditionally Dedekind cuts are understood as being objects derived from sets of rationals, in which the rationals are understood to be constructed, or simply to exist, prior to the creation of open sets of rationals, which are then used to define the cuts called "irrational numbers". That approach to understanding the reals is very "bottom up", and possibly in contradiction with Dedekind's own understanding of his cuts, which i suspect might have been "top down" (see the SEP for more discussion on his thoughts about the continuum in relation to actual infinity).

    In my case, i am stressing the benefits of a "top down" approach, in which one uses lattice theory to define a lattice of abstract elements that is isomorphic to the open sets of the rationals extended by end points. The open sets of the rationals are only intended to serve as a model of this lattice, which is free to not assume the existence of points and other closed sets.
  • Continuum does not exist

    I agree with you, but i probably didn't make myself clear enough. I'm saying that if L| R is a Dedekind cut consisting of two open sets (as is the case when the cut defines an irrational number that isn't already contained in R), then the union of L, L|R and R is a disjoint partition of the continuum, which is semantically problematic in being disconnected (even if not "disconnected" according to the narrow topological definition of connectedness in terms of open sets only). The closed interval [r,r] is what I meant by writing [r].
  • Continuum does not exist
    Instead of points one works with lattices of open sets. I don't see this as improving the intuitive understanding of continua. Continuity in elementary topological spaces rests upon the idea of connectedness. The topology of the reals is fairly well established, so maybe start by studying this.jgill

    I'm tempted to think of Dedekind cuts as a mathematics joke, in the sense that when open sets L and R are used to define a Dedekind cut L|R for an irrational number r, the generated closed set [r] is disjoint from both L and R, and yet their union equated with the continuum. As I understand it, this disjointed representation of the continuum is in semantic conflict with the continuum's connected topology , which is ultimately the cause of the continuum being empirically uninterpretable and practically useless in real life without abuse of notation.

    I think the interesting thing about the open-sets of the extended continuum (with -Inf and +Inf introduced as end points), is that they can be interpreted as representing propositions, due to the fact that they form a distributive lattice with a top element (-Inf,+Inf), whose join operation is set union representing logical disjunction, and whose meet operation is set intersection representing logical disjunction, in spite of this lattice lacking a bottom element (since the empty set isn't an open set).

    Likewise, the closed-sets of the extended continuum can be interpreted as representing negated propositions, due to the fact that the intersection of an open set (-Inf, x) with a closed-set [x,y] is the empty set representing falsity. More specifically, any point [x] represents a false proposition under this interpretation, i.e. p[x] := NOT { p(-Inf,x) OR p(x,+Inf)}, where p denotes a predicate that maps open sets to propositions of some sort. This interpretation refrains from asserting the existence of a point x for which p is true, but it doesn't deny the existence of such points either. (To deny the existence of such points is to go from a pointfree topology to a pointless topology).

    In short, the open sets of the extended rational numbers can represent propositions derived by coinduction with respect to a 'top' proposition that is continuous in the sense that it isn't isomorphic to any union of propositions whose domains are disjoint. This top proposition is empirically meaningful. For example, we generally don't consider a priceless Ming vase to be the same after smashing it and gluing the pieces back together. By going point-free with our continuous topology, at least initially, allows us to consider "points" as being defects that are introduced when damaging a continuum to produce a non-continuum, such as in the destructive testing of a smooth object.
  • Empiricism, potentiality, and the infinite
    Consider the operational meaning of "infinity" that refers to circular control flow that lacks a termination condition. That is what the lemniscate symbol represents. So there is at least a pictorial, operational and geometric meaning of infinity. Such flows generate infinite processes that often produce observable data on each iteration, so there is also empirical meaning with regards to the execution of an infinite process. And the controllers of the execution of the process get to decide when to terminate it once it has served its purpose, and so the ability to control such a process, as well as it's forced termination by the user, gives controlled infinite processes empirical meaning.

    Karl Popper's principle of falsification refers to the case in which an observer hypothesizes that an infinite process that the observer does not control, is responsible for producing a stream of observations.

    For example, suppose that an investigator conjectures that all swans are white and that he will terminate his investigation upon observing the first non-white swan. Here, the only empirical meaning that the investigator can be ascribe to his conjecture are the conditions under which his infinite process conjecture is refuted by observation of a counter-example. For Popper, such potential refutation is enough for the investigators hypothesis to be considered as scientifically meaningful. However, suppose that the investigator considered his infinite process hypothesis to be true. As a true hypothesis, it would have no empirical implications, since if it were true then the investigator will never exhaust his stream of observations so as to know that it is true. So I interpret Popper's falsification criteria as implying that infinite process hypotheses are empirically and scientifically meaningful in the sense of the criteria that falsify them, but that such hypotheses cannot be interpreted as true hypotheses, since such interpretations are meaningless.
  • Continuum does not exist
    I am however puzzled how all the members of the natural number set are finite yet it has aleph_0 members.MoK

    Semantic puzzlement at the fact that one cannot finitely bound the natural numbers is understandable, even when having no syntactical puzzlement with regards to a formal definition of the naturals.

    Firstly, there is presumably no semantic puzzlement about the situation in which one constructs the naturals one by one by counting upwards from zero, for in that case one assumes full control of the number generation process that one never finishes, for which at any time one has only constructed naturals that are a constructively finite distance from zero.

    So i think that semantic puzzlement is in relation to arbitrarily large natural numbers that one assumes to exist but which aren't constructively defined.

    For example, consider a guessing game between Alice and Bob, in which Alice privately thinks of a natural number which Bob then has to guess. Suppose that Bob is given an unlimited number of chances for guessing Alice's number. If Alice doesn't cheat by changing her number in response to Bob's guesses, then Bob has a winning strategy that will eventually terminate, such as guessing each natural number in turn by counting upwards from zero. But then suppose Alice does cheat to ensure that Bob will lose. How could Bob ever know it? Alice could for example secretly define her number to be one greater than Bob's largest guess. In which case her natural number isn't constructively finite in relation to Bob's strategy, in spite of being constructively finite in relation to Alice's strategy in the situation where Bob eventually gives up.
  • Relativism vs. Objectivism: What is the Real Nature of Truth?
    Semantic contextualism needs to be distinguished from truth relativism. According to the former position, differences of opinion are not interpreted as reflecting differences in truth assessment with respect to the same set of facts, but as reflecting differences in the contextual meaning of what each opinion is asserting.

    Semantic contexualism when pushed to the extreme as a dogma, interprets all assertions as being necessarily true when contextually understood and trivialism ensues, which raises the question as to whether all of the problems of epistemology reduce to the trivialities of semantics.
  • Continuum does not exist
    Formally, the classical continuum "exists" in the sense that that it is possible to axiomatically define connected and compact sets of dimensionless points that possesses a model that is unique up to isomorphism thanks to the categoricity of second order logic.

    But the definition isn't constructive and is extensionally unintelligible for some of the reasons you pointed out in the OP. Notably, Dedekind didn't believe in the reality of cuts of the continuum at irrational numbers and only in the completeness of the uninterpreted formal definition of a cut. Furthermore, Weyl, Brouwer, Poincare and Peirce all objected to discrete conceptions of the continuum that attempted to derive continuity from discreteness. For those mathematicians and philosophers, the meaning of "continuum" cannot be represented by the modern definition that is in terms of connected and compact sets of dimensionless points. E.g, Peirce thought that there shouldn't be an upper bound on the number of points that a continuum can be said to divide into, whereas for Brouwer the continuum referred not to a set of ideal points, but to a linearly ordered set of potentially infinite but empirically meaningful choice sequences that can never be finished.

    The classical continuum is unredeemable, in that weakening the definition of the reals to allow infinitesimals by removing the second-order least-upper bound principle, does not help if the underlying first-order logic remains classical, since it leads to the same paradoxes of continuity appearing at the level of infinitesimals, resulting in the need for infinitesimal infinitesimals and so on, ad infinitum.... whatever model of the axioms is chosen.
    Alternatively, allowing points to have positions that are undecidable, resolves, or rather dissolves, the problem of 'gaps' existing between dimensionless points, in that it is no longer generally the case that points are either separated or not separated, meaning that most of the constructively valid cuts of the continuum occur at imprecise locations for which meta-mathematical extensional antimonies cannot be derived.
    Nevertheless this constructively valid subset of the classical continuum remains extensionally uninterpretable, for when cut at any location with a decidable value, we still end up with a standard Dedekind Cut such as (-Inf,0) | [0,Inf) , in which all and only the real numbers less than 0 belong to the left fragment, and with all and only the real numbers equal or greater than 0 belonging to the right fragment, which illustrates that a decidable cut isn't located at any real valued position on the continuum. Ultimately it is this inability of the classical continuum to represent the location of a decidable cut, that is referred to when saying that the volume of a point has "Lebesgue measure zero". And so it is tempting to introduce infinitesimals so that points can have infinitesimal non-zero volume, with their associated cuts located infinitesimally close to the location of a real number.

    The cheapest way to allow new locations for cuts is to axiomatize a new infinitesimal directly, that is defined to be non-zero but smaller in magnitude than every real number and whose square equals 0, as is done in smooth infinitesimal analysis, whose resulting continuum behaves much nicer than the classical continuum for purposes of analysis, even if the infinitesimal isn't extensionally meaningful. The resulting smooth continuum at least enforces that every function and its derivatives at every order is continuous, meaning that the continuum is geometrically much better behaved than the classical continuum that allows pathological functions on its domain that are discontinuous, as well as being geometrically better behaved than Brouwer's intuitionistic continuum that in any case is only supposed to be a model of temporal intuition rather than of spatial intuition, which only enforces functions to have uniform continuity.

    The most straightforward way of getting an extensionally meaningful continuum such as a one dimensional line, is to define it directly in terms of a point-free topology, in an analogous manner to Dedekind's approach, but without demanding that it has enough cuts to be a model of the classical continuum. E.g, one can simply define a "line" as referring to a filter, so as to ensure that a line can never be divided an absolutely infinite number of times into lines of zero length, and conversely, one can define a collection of "points" as referring to an ideal, so as to ensure that a union of points can never be grown for an absolutely infinite amount of time into having a volume equaling that of the smallest line. This way, lines and points can be kept apart without either being definable in terms of the other, so that one never arrives at the antimonies you raised above.
  • Communism's Appeal
    Usually these sorts of discussions begin on the wrong foot by conflating communism with state capitalism under a ruling party, that is a situation resembling modern day corporate America in many respects, which is ironically reinforced by "communist" hating conservatives refusing to support progressive taxation.

    I'm no Marx expert, but understand that he viewed communism descriptively as an inevitable outcome of capitalism, as much as he did as a moral imperative. With modern society's inevitable transition to universal income in the coming years, the appeal of communism seems besides the point.
  • The Liar Paradox - Is it even a valid statement?
    Suppose y = sin(cos(x)). Which (sin or cos) would you say is inside, and which outside?bongo fury

    Quine was presumably referring to the stratification of types originally proposed by Russell, which ensures that the a map between type universes resides in a universe that is higher than both of the input and output universes. We might recall the fact that each universe contains a subclass that is isomorphic to the previous universe, as represented by the quotation marks in the liar sentence. So if we start with the highest level universe that we say contains everything we regard to be true, and use it to build in stepwise fashion an infinitely descending chain of so-called object languages that are each the meta-language of their predecessor, the liar sentence can be interpreted as stream of fluctuating truth values with respect to isomorphic, but non-identical terms of different types.

    By contrast, both Sin and Cos are maps of type Real --> Real, i.e maps between terms of Reals, where the type Real --> Real resides in the same universe as the type Real, as does any function of functions of ... functions of reals; for they all reside in the universe definable in terms of second order logic. Following their example, we could alternatively interpret the liar sentence as directly referring to a stream of fluctuating values, where the stream and its values all exist in the same universe as a binary approximation to those trigonometric functions.
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    The identification of anything is subjective and relative to convention. E.g, we don't get hung up about whether or not today's chair is said to be same as tomorrows chair, so why should we treat persons as having objective haecceity ?

    Tibetan monks might have their politico-cultural reasons for objecting to the Chinese government choosing the next Dalai Lama, but do they really have a metaphysical leg to stand on?
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    So the idea of persons as real and local spatial-temporal objects with objective physical boundaries is fundamentally incompatible with the idea that persons can be reincarnated. — sime


    Beings are not only objects, they are also subjects of experience, and the nature of subjective experience is not necessarily describable in those terms.
    Wayfarer

    Are subjects of experience observable and identifiable or not?


    Also consider the discovery of tulkus in Tibetan Buddhism. They are sought out by various means and subjected to examination and are said to be clearly discerned as incarnations of previously-existing figures. As already mentioned, Buddhist culture assumes the reality of rebirth as a matter of course, even despite the tension with the no-self principle.
    Wayfarer

    So Tulkas are observable subjects of experience who are interpretable in terms of types of objects?
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    In respect of the question of identity, Buddhists will respond, if you ask them, ‘are you the same person you were as a child?’ ‘No’. ‘Then are you a different person?’ Also, ‘no’. There is a continuity, but also change. I don’t think Buddhism has a difficulty with that. Overall, I find the Buddhist attitude congenial in these matters.

    So I’m not really seeing your philosophical objection at this point.
    Wayfarer

    I'm not objecting to Buddhist sentiment to the extent that they understand that identity relations are arbitrary psycho-linguistic constructs that necessitate their semantic conclusions. In the case of the no-soul rebirth paradox, if concepts related to personhood aren't part of one's fundamental ontology, for example because one considers concepts of personhood to be unreal because one considers persons to be semantically reducible to impersonal forces of nature, then rebirth follows as a tautological conclusions, since the personhood concepts of life and death are both eliminated in the final analysis of of reality. In which case empirical evidence for rebirth is meaningless.

    By contrast, if one conceives of persons as being fundamentally real and local token-objects whose existence is ontologically fundamental, then permanent death without reincarnation follows as a matter of tautology, and there cannot exist evidence to the contrary - for even allegedly successful past-life regressions must be discounted as illusory if one holds ones concept of persons as tokens as sacrosanct.


    So the idea of persons as real and local spatial-temporal objects with objective physical boundaries is fundamentally incompatible with the idea that persons can be reincarnated. One of the concepts must give way to the other, and the question cannot be settled by appealing to empirical evidence, for the very meaning of "empirical evidence" lies downstream of this ontological decision.
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    You may not be familiar with the research. It wasn’t based on 'past-life regression'. The cases Stevenson sought out were those where children claimed to be someone other than who they were known to be e.g. would start saying 'your not my family' or 'this is not my home, I live in (some other place)' etc. Then the researchers would look for evidence of that claimed previous identity, trying to identify death notices, locations, and other details to corroborate the infant's story.Wayfarer

    Yes, I wasn't questioning the veracity of anecdotes such as the one you mention, rather I'm pointing out that to interpret such cases as being "evidence for reincarnation" is relative to a convention that defines personal identity in terms of memories, by which the person is said to be reincarnated. Which is why I do not take such cases with special seriousness - not because I am assuming that such reported cases cannot be happen as described, but because I consider the identity of persons to be arbitrary and decided by convention, and ultimately grounded in either psychological habits and prejudice or in the utility of adopting the chosen identity criteria.

    For example, lets assume that the account you mention is accurate and defies mundane natural explanations. Then unless one has defined personhood in terms of personal memories, one cannot conclude that the child is a reincarnation of the previous person he is said to remember. In which case all that one concludes is that the child presently has abnormal access to novel information of historical significance.

    Certainly, the child-as-token is not a previous person - by definition of "token". Compare this situation to a caterpillar-token that is said to become a butterfly-token. In that case, we don't insist that the butterfly remembers his life as a caterpillar in order for us to identify the caterpillar with the butterfly, rather we identify their tokens as being parts of a greater token on the basis of temporal continuity. Whereas in the case of the child, there is no apparent spatio-temporal continuity for us to say that the child was the becoming of the previous person, and instead we bridge their lives via a notion of "memory continuity", in spite of the fact that we rarely if ever employ such criteria in our own lives when we ordinarily identify ourselves and our loved ones over time.
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    As I mentioned to Philosophim, the point about the children with past-life recall is that there is at least the possibility of validating their statements against documentary and witness accounts, something which is obviously not possible with near-death experiences, as they are first-person by definition.Wayfarer

    Our memories are mutable. We continually create, delete and edit our memories in real time, including the memories that we interpret as being veridical. In general we don't interpret amnesia as constituting proof of personal absence during the past. So why should the possession of a veridical memory be interpreted as constituting proof of having witnessed the past? When it comes to conceptions of personal identity, why should ownership of memories be taken more seriously than ownership of a collection of disposable photographs?

    The idea that studies of past life regression can verify or refute reincarnation, is in relation to a convention that defines personal identity in terms of memory possession, together with a block-universe conception of the past that memories are considered to refer to in a manner analogous to time travel. So I don't interpret studies of past life regression as drawing deeper metaphysical conclusions, regardless of whether such conclusions are positive or negative, than our pragmatic judgements of object identification.
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    That’s all well and good if your criteria of reincarnation is as slack as a good impression of that person or just imitation. Personhood has a more strict definition of what a person is as it covers what that person has experienced in life their memories made, habits personality traits and just general character. The issue boils down to personal identity and what it means to be you.kindred

    I'm arguing that even a supposedly strict definition of personhood is slack. Slackness is an inexorable feature of identity criteria; any application of identity criteria to any problem of philosophy leads to superficial and incomplete conclusions that are products of linguistic convention. At best, one's conclusions are circular and merely reiterate the identity criteria that one employed.
  • Evidence of Consciousness Surviving the Body
    What conditions are required for the reincarnation of Elvis Presley?

    In my pragmatic view, a good Karaoke singer who does a reasonable impersonation of Elvis on stage, can be said to be of roughly the same "type" as Elvis, at least until the end of the impersonation.

    I don't consider the questions of reincarnation to run deeper than that, because identity criteria are inexorably vague, conflicting and decided by convention or psychological prejudices. So why should it be assumed that the question of reincarnation has a definite and absolute answer that transcends our conventions?
  • Do (A implies B) and (A implies notB) contradict each other?
    The main problem for me is, why can we read a→(b∧¬b) as "a implies a contradiction" but not ¬(a→(b∧¬b)) as "a does not imply a contradiction?Lionino

    In general, the consistency of an axiomatic system isn't provable in an absolute sense due to Godel's second incompleteness theorem; the upshot being that consistency is a structural property of the entire system that isn't represented as a theorem by the system if it is sufficiently powerful.

    Suppose that the logic concerned is weaker than Peano arithmetic, such that it can prove its own consistency. Then in this case, a proof of ¬¬a metalogically implies that ¬a isn't provable, i.e that a does not imply a contradiction.

    But if the axiomatic system contains Peano arithmetic such that the second incompleteness theorem holds, then a proof of ¬¬a does not necessarily imply the absence of a proof of ¬a, since Peano arithmetic cannot prove its own consistency.
  • Do (A implies B) and (A implies notB) contradict each other?
    Sure, but that's not really what the example is there to assert, as is clear from the rest of the paragraph. They mentioned replacing the fact about dogs 2+2 = 4 in the next line. It's "if a statement is true, then that statement is implied by any statement whatever," which is straightforwardly counter intuitive.Count Timothy von Icarus

    That's true of classical logic, and more specifically it's fragment known as intuitionistic logic, due to the fact that the respective rule of implication is essentially the logic of functions (including those that ignore their arguments to produce a constant value), rather than the logic of causality - which is described by relevance logic and linear logic.

    As for "Modern Symbolic Logic", it doesn't have a well-defined meaning since it refers to a plurality of logics that are separately described in terms of different mathematical categories.
  • Even programs have free will
    But consider the fact that the halting behaviour of two identical algorithms stands and falls together. So although there does not exist an infallible universal halting tester, there exists an infallible special-case halting tester for any given algorithm, namely a copy of that very algorithm.

    Although an epistemic limitation falls short of a metaphysical proof, I am sympathetic to the idea of free will, because in my opinion the conceptual distinction between free will and determinism rests upon a belief in absolute infinity, which i reject.

    In my view, to say that "A => B is necessary true" in the sense of material causation, is to say that there exists a Z such that "A => Z is necessarily true" and "Z => B is necessarily true". If we reject the idea that this definition can appeal to actually infinite recursion, then the use-meaning of " A => B is necessarily true" in any given context must eventually bottom out to a finite chain of implicative reasoning, in which the meaning of "necessarily true" is left undefined.

    A simpler way of putting it, is to say that we make up the meaning of " A => B is necessarily true" as we go along. This proposition doesn't have precise a priori meaning, and so isn't contradicted by a future discovery that A => B fails to hold, rather the proposition meant by the sentence "A=> B is necessary true" changes on discovery that A => B fails to hold.
  • How do you interpret nominalism?
    Bertrand Russell's Principia Mathematica was nominalist; he treated sets as merely a means of referring to groups of particulars, partly in response to Set theoretic paradoxes, but the approach made it impossible to describe all of mathematics.

    This demonstrates an unconscious tendency of nominalism; why do nominalists have a tendency to appeal to an ontology based on the existence of particulars, as opposed to an ontology that starts from a united whole?

    In Bertrand Russell's case, it was in the hope of making analysis tractable in piecemeal fashion, in contrast to the British Idealists who might also be described as nominalist, but who considered reality to consist of a single holistically unified entity. But this makes analytics impossible, since it implies that a local material change to reality causes the meaning and hence definitions of the rest of reality to change.
  • Do (A implies B) and (A implies notB) contradict each other?
    A related example is Godel's trick in his ontological proof of God as discussed in the other thread, which was to define a property P so as to enforce the condition

    ¬(g → P(g) ∧ g → ¬P(g))

    i.e. ¬¬g, which is a classically acceptable proof of existence.
  • Probability Question
    Just because a set S is declared to be "infinite", doesn't imply that S possesses a literally non-finite number of elements, rather it only implies that a bijection between {0,1,2..n} and S isn't or cannot be specified a priori and that n cannot be bounded a priori.

    And even when a bijection between S and the set of natural numbers is specified, this only implies that S must be understood in terms of a monotonically increasing process rather than in terms of a completed basket of goods.

    In both cases, the use-meaning of "infinity" should be understood to mean "finitization is decided by circumstances that are external to the specification logic".

    So philosophical or practical questions about "infinite facts", as opposed to mathematical questions concerning the definition of mathematical infinity, should always be decided by elaborating assumptions until the facts concerned are "finitized". The presence of infinity in a non-mathematical question is only an indication that the question concerned isn't well-posed.
  • Gödel's ontological proof of God
    I don't see where that is implied in the argument.

    P(ψ)≡¬N(ψ) — sime


    If N is supposed to mean necessary existence, that is a rejection of axiom 5.
    Lionino

    N was supposed to mean the possibility modality (N standing for Negative Properties, in order to stand for the opposite of Positive Properties). The question here I was interested in, is how to give a syntactical definition of Positive Properties such that the resulting argument follows as a valid tautology in some modal logic. This was partly in order to help clarify the the definitions Godel provided, even his assumptions need to be altered slightly and the resulting argument and its conclusion aren't quite the same.

    For example, taking Positive properties to refer to what is necessarily true of all individuals in every possible world, turns Axiom A2 into the definition of a functor, which is rather tempting. It also makes the possibility of god follow as a matter of tautology.

    Also, Godel's definition of essences seems close to the definition of the Categorical Product. So why not take the essence of an individual to be the conjunction of his properties?

    One thing I overlooked was that God was defined as referring to the exact set of positive properties, which would mean that according to my definition of P, all individuals would be identical. But then supposing we weaken the definition of "Godliness" to refer to a set that contains all the positive properties and possibly some of the negative (i.e contigent) ones?

    I think there is quite a few pedagogically useful questions here.
  • Gödel's ontological proof of God
    It seems to me you are thoroughly confusedLionino

    about what?