Yes, I see. And that is the objection I've had to Pie's position from the outset - that the truth bearer, P, is not identical to the fact that P describes. So P is not identical with the world, otherwise we are still talking about a sentence. But if we maintain the distinction between sentence and world, and if P is equivalent to the world, then I don't see how that's different to correspondence.
— Luke
I see what you mean I think! Would like to see a discussion on how the RHS relates to the world, and how it differs to correspondence. — fdrake
Correspondence and disquotation
Some philosophers regard semantic notions as disquotational notions: a sentence enclosed in quotation marks has the property of being true iff this sentence, its quotation marks removed, holds (Ramsey 1927). Tarski, however, views the two analyses as equivalent:
"A characteristic feature of the semantical concepts is that they give expression to certain relations between the expressions of language and the objects about which these expressions speak, or that by means of such relations they characterize certain classes of expressions or other objects. We could also say (making use of the suppositio materialis) that these concepts serve to set up the correlation between the names of expressions and the expressions themselves." (Tarski 1933: 252)
We can explain Tarski's view as follows: There are two modes of speech, an objectual mode and a linguistic mode ('material' mode, in Medieval terminology). The correspondence idea can be expressed in both modes. It is expressed by:
'Snow is white' is true iff snow is white
as well as by:
' "Snow is white" is true' is equivalent to 'Snow is white.'
In the objectual mode we say that a sentence attributing the (physical) property of whiteness to the (physical) stuff snow is true iff the (physical) stuff snow has the (physical) property of whiteness; in the linguistic mode we say that a sentence attributing (the semantic property of) truth to a sentence attributing whiteness to snow is equivalent to a sentence attributing whiteness to snow. — Truth, The Liar, and Tarski's Semantics - Gila Sher (from Blackwell's A Companion to Philosophical Logic)
I do want to say though that I think there's something a little funny going on in imagining judging a sort of canonical case of knowing. (Of the "Well I seen it, didn't I!" variety.) — Srap Tasmaner
I don't think it's a matter of doubt, just a matter of admitting fallibility. I would say that I know that my housemate is a bachelor, but I also accept that he could be lying to me and have a secret wife that he ran away from. Implausible, perhaps, but not unheard of. Does admitting of this possibility (and not just in the "there is a possible world" sense) somehow entail that I don't know that my housemate is a bachelor (assuming he isn't lying to me)? I don't think so. That I might be mistaken is simply an admission that I am not certain, not an admission of doubt.
So in such a scenario I would say that I know (and perhaps I do), but I'd also say that I might be wrong. Both claims are warranted. — Michael
One might fear that such arguments would prove too much. After all, something is wrong even with the assertion ‘A and I cannot be certain that A’. Does that not suggest that only something more than knowledge warrants assertion? What seems to be at work here is a reluctance to allow the contextually set standards for knowledge and certainty to diverge. Many people are not very happy to say things like ‘She knew that A, but she could not be certain that A’. However, we can to some extent effect such a separation, and then assertibility goes with knowledge, not with the highest possible standards of certainty. For example, one may have warrant to assert ‘A and by Descartes's standards I cannot be absolutely certain that A’, where the reference to Descartes holds those standards apart from the present context. Again, it would often be inappropriate to respond to the assertion ‘A’ by asking ‘How can you be so certain that A?’. The word ‘so’ flags the invocation of unusually high standards of certainty. By ordinary standards you may have had warrant to assert that A even if you could not be so certain that A. — Knowledge and Its Limits, p. 254 - Timothy Williamson
Knowledge can attach to discrete, one-off events in a way that many things just don't. — Srap Tasmaner
I think, as a general matter, we should preserve both sides of the coin here, not just our fallibility -- the cases where we think we know and we're wrong about that -- but also where we have misplaced doubt, and do know something despite thinking we don't. Even forgetting and remembering has a place here: you can claim, honestly, not to know where Mike is today, and then remember that he has work -- that is, remember that you do know where he is. — Srap Tasmaner
Maybe omniscience can just keep climbing that ladder, knowing that p, knowing that you know it, knowing that you know that you know it, ad nauseam. — Srap Tasmaner
But it's too strict, isn't it? I can ask someone to remember a telephone number for me, and they needn't understand which part is the (American) area code, which the exchange, and so on. They needn't even know it's a telephone number or what a telephone number might be. They either know the digits by heart or they don't. As long as there's no guessing, they know it. They need to be able to recite it back to me, or to reconstruct it if they chose some odd mnemonic, so there's a still an ability-style test, but it's nothing so broad as really "getting" telephones and their numbers. — Srap Tasmaner
We know perfectly well that the sort of person who tends to know stuff, and the sort of procedure that tends to produce knowledge, can fail. (Hence this thread.) And we know just as well that an unreliable person who has an unreliable approach to knowledge is sometimes dead right. We might reasonably prefer the former as an approach to rationality, but we'll miss the boat on what knowledge is. — Srap Tasmaner
Then knowledge requires certainty. If we are not certain that John is a bachelor then we do not know that John is a bachelor.
The argument I offered was premised on the notion that we can know things even if we are not certain, and so I accept that a rejection of that premise allows one to reject the conclusion.
Whether or not we'd want to reject that premise is another matter, but I see that you are willing. — Michael
A related question, then, is what it takes for us to be certain that something is true. My initial view is that we can only be certain that something is true if that thing is necessarily true, and so I can only be certain that John is a bachelor if it is necessarily true that John is a bachelor, although perhaps that's a matter for another discussion. — Michael
And I again think of the shy schoolboy: I'm inclined to say that he knows the right answer, even if his lack of confidence in himself leads him to doubt that he knows what he does in fact know. — Srap Tasmaner
Even if you're right, certainty is a necessary but not sufficient condition for knowledge. We generally believe that knowledge must be arrived at "in the right way" to count, to rule out lucky guesses. And we seem to have the very same problem with certainty. Many people are certain Trump won the 2020 election, but their certainty was arrived at in the wrong sort of way. If we still have to give an analysis of the right kind of certainty to get anywhere, will that analysis differ significantly from an account of the right way to arrive at knowledge? Maybe, but it's not clear to me. — Srap Tasmaner
... there is generally “a reluctance to allow the contextually set standards for knowledge and certainty to diverge” (Williamson 2000, p. 254). That is, the standards for what counts as knowledge and as certainty typically match one another. Nevertheless, in some contexts we can pull them apart. — SEP - Certainty
p ⊬ □p — Michael
Therefore (b) is true if there is a possible world where John is not a bachelor. — Michael
And if fallibilism is true then knowledge does not require certainty, and so knowledge does not entail certainty. I can know and not be certain. Therefore (c) is true if I am not certain that John is a bachelor. — Michael
a) If I know that John is a bachelor then John might not be a bachelor — Michael
This can be interpreted as:
b) If I know that John is a bachelor then there is a possible world where John is not a bachelor
c) If I know that John is a bachelor then I am not certain that John is a bachelor
Do you believe that either of (b) and (c) is false? — Michael
e) I am not certain that the number 2 is even
Which may, in fact, be false.
How do you think this is resolved? — Michael
Yes, exactly that. Moore's paradox was the inspiration for this discussion. — Michael
No, because the number 2 is necessarily even. My examples are only ever where the truth of the claim is not necessarily true. — Michael
No, I'm saying that it is false that "the blue ball might be red", just as it is false that "The number 2 might be odd". There's a difference between conceptual and empirical claims. — Andrew M
a) The ball might be red
If you accept that a) is true even if the ball is blue then you accept that there is a possible world where the ball is blue and a) is true.
And then I don't see a difference between these phrasings:
1. The ball is blue and a) is true
2. The ball is blue and the ball might be red
3. The ball is blue and might be red
4. The blue ball might be red
Do these mean different things to you, and so have different truth-conditions? — Michael
There is a ball hidden in a box. That ball is either red or blue.
a) The ball might be red.
This proposition is true whatever the colour of the ball in the box. It is true if the ball is red and it is true if the ball is blue. — Michael
If you want to say that a) is false if the ball is blue — Michael
What does "could be false" mean? Either "there is a possible world where it is false" or "I am not certain that it is true". In both cases "My true belief could be false" can be true. — Michael
So, either "I might be wrong" can be true even if I have a true belief or "I might be wrong" is only true if I have a false belief. — Michael
Maybe the problem is with the interpretation of the English sentence. These two don’t mean the same thing:
a) It is possible that I know something and am wrong about that thing
b) I know something and it is possible that I am wrong about that thing
The former is false but the latter seems possible as the arguments show. — Michael
Well then I'm left with no idea who these 'direct realists' even are, let alone what they claim. I asked Michael for some examples of the direct realist claim and he pointed me to the SEP article on colour primitivism which listed Hacker as a proponent.
So...
1. Is Hacker not a colour primitivist, ... — Isaac
Rather, that we see is a consequence of the action of illuminated or luminous objects on our visual system, and what we see are those objects, colour and all. What we thus see, we see 'directly' (to see something 'indirectly' might be to see it through a periscope or in a mirror - not to look at the thing itself in full daylight with one's eyes). — Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience, 2nd Ed. - Bennett and Hacker, p143
One of the most prominent views of color is that color is an objective, i.e., mind-independent, intrinsic property, one possessed by many material objects (of different kinds) and light sources. ... colors are simple intrinsic, non-relational, non-reducible, qualitative properties. — 2.1 Primitivism: The Simple Objectivist View of Colors
2. Who the hell is a direct realist? Seems everybody quoted turns out not to be one. — Isaac
Fair enough. It seems like such a weak position shown false by the simplest of counterarguments that I find it very hard to believe I haven't simply misunderstood their position. I mean, one of the proponents listed in the article you cited was PMS Hacker. I don't agree with a lot of his philosophy, but he doesn't strike me as the sort of low caliber philosopher likely to make such an elementary error. — Isaac
That we can see an object to be red only when light is reflected off its surface and on to our retina does not show that the object 'in and of itself' is not really red. It merely shows that a condition for its colour being visible is that it be illuminated. Similarly, that photons reflected off the illuminated object cause changes to protein molecules in the retina, which in turn transmits electrical impulses to the fibres of the optic nerve, does not show that what we see is not really coloured, any more than it shows that we do not see what we see directly. What we see is not the effect of an object on us. The effect of an object on our nervous system is the stimulation of the cells of the retina, the effect of this on the optic nerve, the consequent excitation of the cells in the hypercolumns of the 'visual' striate cortex - but none of this is perceived either by the brain (which can perceive nothing) or by the person whose brain it is. Rather, that we see is a consequence of the action of illuminated or luminous objects on our visual system, and what we see are those objects, colour and all. What we thus see, we see 'directly' (to see something 'indirectly' might be to see it through a periscope or in a mirror - not to look at the thing itself in full daylight with one's eyes).
...
And it is no more necessary for my perceiving a red object that there be something red in me than it is necessary for me to perceive an explosion that something explode in me.
...
Human beings, when they perceive their environment, do not perceive representations of the world, straightforward or otherwise, since to perceive 'the world' (or, more accurately, some part of it) is not to perceive a representation. (To perceive a photograph or painting is to perceive a representation.) And in whatever legitimate sense there is to the supposition that there is a representation of what is seen in the brain, that representation is not what the owner of the brain sees. The 'representation' is a weed in the neuroscientific garden, not a tool - and the sooner it is uprooted the better. — Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience, 2nd Ed. - Bennett and Hacker, p143, p145, p154
Is the mind a single thing, or does it have parts? If it has parts, what are they? Are its parts tied to parts of the brain? — TiredThinker
Allow me to recommend The Concept of Mind by Gilbert Ryle. I only recently got around to this book, and it's just flamethrower for so many entrenched confusions concerning the mind. — Pie
So thinking of knowledge as a changing interpretation based on new good evidence resolves the issue. There can be right and wrong interpretations. A wrong interpretation is not no interpretation, just a different one based on the good evidence one had at the time. — Harry Hindu
The distinction between task verbs and achievement verbs or ‘try’ verbs and ‘got it’ verbs frees us from another theoretical nuisance. It has long been realised that verbs like ‘know’, ‘discover’, ‘solve’, ‘prove’, ‘perceive’, ‘see’ and ‘observe’ (at least in certain standard uses of ‘observe’) are in an important way incapable of being qualified by adverbs like ‘erroneously’ and ‘incorrectly’. ... — The Concept of Mind, p134 - Gilbert Ryle
Which is to say that the interpretation we had was valid given the reasons we had at the time. Our interpretation can change, but that doesn't mean that we never had an interpretation in the past. — Harry Hindu
...which apparently would have one conclude that the Great Goat is not a goat! — Banno
We don't. But "every possible observation" is not the standard for making knowledge claims or forming beliefs. Good evidence is. If good counter-evidence emerges, then we should change our minds and retract the former claim.
— Andrew M
Which isn't any different than saying knowledge is an interpretation that changes with new evidence - not that you never had it. — Harry Hindu
What qualifies as good evidence? Isn't there a chance that good counter-evidence emerges later? If yes, then you can never say that you possess knowledge. You would never know that you know or you would know something unknowable. — Harry Hindu
Yet we asserted that we did know and were wrong, which is good evidence that you could be wrong again, and again, and again - hence no such thing as knowledge unless we define knowledge as an interpretation that changes - not that you never had it. So, using your "good evidence" definition, you have good evidence that you can't ever possess good evidence. Your argument defeats itself. — Harry Hindu
As I pointed out, it is very possible that your good reason or evidence isn't actually a good reason or evidence, and you only find that out after you get good reason or evidence, yet it is very possible that your good reason or evidence isn't actually good reason or evidence, and you only find that out...,etc. It's an infinite regress. — Harry Hindu
No. It is you that assumes a standard of infallibility or Cartesian certainty by saying that "good evidence" is what is needed to possess knowledge. I'm simply asking you to define what that means, if not that "good evidence" is a state of infallibility (knowing the truth). I already pointed out that looking out the window is not good evidence because your brother could be spraying the window with a hose. — Harry Hindu
To be clear, the difference with that to the knowability paradox is that "p & ~p" is a contradiction - it can never be true. Whereas "p & ~Kp" is not a contradiction. It can be true, but never known to be true.
— Andrew M
Yes, but for the exact same reason than you can't eat an uneaten chicken. Fitch says that one cannot know an unknown truth, because as soon as one knows it, it cease to be an unknown truth. Likewise the Olivier5 chicken paradox states that one cannot eat an uneaten chicken, because as soon as one eats it it ceases to be an uneaten chicken. — Olivier5
The alternative, that the Great Goat eats itself, is unpalatable. — Banno
Indeed, and that's the point. When we discover that a former knowledge claim was mistaken, we retroactively downgrade its status from knowledge to belief. We say that they didn't know it after all, since we no longer believe that it was true then.
— Andrew M
But this misses the point that what we used to call knowledge wasn't knowledge in light of new observations, but observations is what allowed us to assert knowledge that we didn't have in the first place. So how do we know that we've made every possible observation to assert we possess knowledge? — Harry Hindu
You can look out the window at the moment your trickster brother sprays the window with a hose. — Harry Hindu
Is it possible to believe a truth? How would that be different than to know a truth? — Harry Hindu
How do we ever know that we have all the evidence necessary to assert knowledge over belief? — Harry Hindu
Specifically, it says that an uneaten chicken cannot be eaten without ceasing to be an uneaten chicken, so we cannot logically speaking eat an uneaten chicken.
Note that we also cannot eat a chicken that has already been eaten. And since a chicken is either eaten or not eaten, it follows that logically speaking, we cannot eat any chicken. — Olivier5
Similarly, it can be shown that, contrary to popular belief, not all chicken can be eaten. Take a live, not yet eaten chicken. Can one eat it one say? Yes but then it would immediately cease to be an uneaten chicken. So an uneaten chicken cannot be eaten. — Olivier5
B(p & ~Bp) - someone at some time has the belief that 'p is true and nobody believes that p is true'. Is this Moore's paradox?
— Luke
I was hoping someone would have responded to this point. Did anyone else note this connection between the two paradoxes? Does anyone agree or disagree that these are similar or the same type of paradox? — Luke
Frederic Fitch (1963) reports that in 1945 he first learned of this proof of unknowable truths from a referee report on a manuscript he never published. Thanks to Joe Salerno’s (2009) archival research, we now know that referee was Alonzo Church.
...
Church’s referee report was composed in 1945. The timing and structure of his argument for unknowables suggests that Church may have been inspired by G. E. Moore’s (1942, 543) sentence:
(M) I went to the pictures last Tuesday, but I don’t believe that I did. — Epistemic Paradoxes - SEP
But back then, they wouldn't say "we believe that the sun orbits the earth". They would rather have said: "we know that the sun orbits the earth". And there was plenty of evidence for it, mind you, though we now understand that this evidence was interpreted incorrectly. — Olivier5
The distinction between task verbs and achievement verbs or ‘try’ verbs and ‘got it’ verbs frees us from another theoretical nuisance. It has long been realised that verbs like ‘know’, ‘discover’, ‘solve’, ‘prove’, ‘perceive’, ‘see’ and ‘observe’ (at least in certain standard uses of ‘observe’) are in an important way incapable of being qualified by adverbs like ‘erroneously’ and ‘incorrectly’. ... — The Concept of Mind, p134 - Gilbert Ryle
Since we don't have access to the registry of things that are, how is one to ascertain that "P is known", as opposed to "persons A, B and C believe that P is true, while person D may disagree"? — Olivier5
If there is milk in the fridge and no-one knows there is, is the statement "there is milk in the fridge and no-one knows there is" true?
— Andrew M
According to logic, if it is true and unknown that there is milk in the fridge, then it can never become known. — Luke
What’s the paradox? Timothy Williamson (2000b) says the knowability paradox is not a paradox; it’s an “embarrassment”––an embarrassment to various brands of antirealism that have long overlooked a simple counterexample. — Fitch’s Paradox of Knowability - SEP
What if one person knows the proposition as true and another knows it as false? Is it 'known' then? — Olivier5
Second, knowledge entails truth.
...
(B) Kp ⊢ p — 2. The Paradox of Knowability - SEP
Fitch is easily solved by noting that knowledge evolves over time. Lamest paradox ever. — Olivier5
Fitch’s paradox of knowability (aka the knowability paradox or Church-Fitch Paradox) concerns any theory committed to the thesis that all truths are knowable. — Fitch’s Paradox of Knowability - SEP
Since no-one would ever plausibly agree that "p & ~Kp" is true, does it follow that it is never true? Presumably not, and so the theory either needs to be rejected or else qualified in some way.
— Andrew M
Surely it is never true. — Luke
If a statement is known to be true, then it cannot also be unknown to be true ("by somebody at some time"). Which is what the independent result tells us. — Luke
It's a trick of logic. Every "p" remains knowable, but not when put into a conjunction with "~Kp". Therefore, it cannot be known both that p is true and p is unknown to be true. That's just word play (or logic play) which does not affect every (other) "p" being knowable. — Luke
Has someone explained what they mean by "knowing a proposition" yet? Does it mean just being aware of the proposition, or knowing it to be true? — Olivier5
If the latter, please note that in practice it is often extremely hard to prove that some proposition is true, beyond any doubt. We almost never 'know X to be positively true'. What we do instead is eliminate theories that are proven false.
So from a pure epistemic view point, the knowability principle is false because contradicted by day-to-day experience, and by our knowledge that we know very little. That'd be why most examples given on this thread are mathematical, as the only domain of knowledge where certainty applies. — Olivier5
No, that's just changing the subject. There are unknowable truths regardless of whether there's a proof about them.
— Andrew M
You want to disregard Fitch's proof, but I'm the one changing the subject? — Luke
It just seems counterintuitive to me that any unknown truths should be unknowable in priniciple. If the only unknowable truths are that 'p is true and no one knows that p is true', then that's merely a quirk of logic that has little effect on substantive knowability. It is still knowable that p is true. The only reason we cannot know 'p is true and no one knows that p is true' is because knowing the first conjunct would falsify the second. I don't see why this should be "of concern for verificationist or anti-realist accounts of truth", as the WIkipedia article states. — Luke
Then we can simply express the unknown truth in Fitch’s proof as “p” and the problem goes away: there are no unknowable truths. — Luke
EDIT: Does Fitch’s proof allow for some unknown truths to be expressed as “p” and others to be expressed as “p & ~Kp”? — Luke
How does that express that it is unknown? — Luke
So is there a way to express an unknown truth in logical notation without mentioning that it is unknown? — Luke
Aye, there's the rub. If a truth is knowable, then it can come to be known; that is, it can change from being unknown to being known. However, as you note, the statement "p & ~Kp" does not (and cannot) change from being unknown to being known. — Luke
Therefore, the starting suppositions make it impossible for an unknown truth to become a known truth. — Luke
But if "p & ~Kp" cannot possibly change from being unknown to being known, then of course it is unknowable: it's a rigged game from the outset. — Luke
You seem to be saying that the truth of the statement "It's true that there's milk in the fridge and no-one knows there is" is unknowable, which seems reasonable, since I don't know there's milk in the fridge unless I open it but then if I do that someone knows there is milk in the fridge. But when I open the fridge I know (excluding weirdness like the milk coming to be there only when I looked) that the statement was true before I looked. — Janus
So, again, there seems to be a time element involved.
If I go down the 'weirdness' rabbit hole and say that when I look and see the milk I still don't know that the milk had been there prior to my looking, then all bets are off. — Janus