Proofs are sufficient, but not necessary, for justification.Proof does not establish truth, it establishes justification. — aletheist
Justification can be based on the absence of counterexamples.... lack of counter-examples constitute a reason believe that something is true, or justified in belief. — god must be atheist
No, a proof is sufficient but NOT necessary. A true proposition is true regardless of whether humans ever construct a proof for it. One more time: a proof pertains to justification, not truth.A given proof is a sufficient condition to establish truth AND it's necessary too. I'm concerned about the latter aspect viz. necessity. — TheMadFool
If God is an agent, why can't he change his mind? — Bartricks
you saying being all powerful involves being able to do 'less' than I can do? — Bartricks
You have the internet. Do some research. — Bartricks
It is intuitively obvious that no mind values anything or prescribes anything of necessity. — Bartricks
It appears self-evident to the reason of most that moral truths are necessary, not contingent. — Bartricks
But just saying something doesn't make it so. — Bartricks
Right back at you.I ask you to read charitably. — Bartricks
How do you know that, if the ball was always on it? Maybe that is just the natural shape of the cushion, and the ball has nothing to do with it.There wouldn't be a dent there if the ball wasn't on it. — Bartricks
Indeed, immutability is one of the standard attributes of God in classical theism. Of course, treating God as a "subject" and a "mind" is rather anthropomorphic.So, by 'God' you mean a mind who, if he is valuing X, is incapable of valuing Y? A mind whose attitudes are fixed - whose attitudes the mind itself is incapable of changing? — Bartricks
That God always wills and acts in accordance with His eternal and immutable nature is perfectly consistent with what omnipotence means in classical theism.As well as appearing to be inconsistent with possessing omnipotence ... — Bartricks
If the cushion has always been indented, then it is not being indented, it simply is indented.The cushion is being indented. — Bartricks
No, not if I knew that the cushion had always been indented; then I would say, "Nothing caused the indent, it has always been that way."If we were to take the ball off the cushion, and someone asked us the cause of the indent on it, we would say "there was a ball on it" - yes? — Bartricks
I honestly thought that we were addressing the question, "What caused the cushion to be indented in the first place?" I am not seeing how this other question is relevant to the OP.What, right now, is causing the cushion to be indented? — Bartricks
I always try to do so, but admittedly do not always succeed. My point was simply that the argument does not require an uncaused event; i.e., I was (gently) trying to correct the mistake in the OP.I ask you to read charitably. — Bartricks
if there can be no infinite regress of causes, then there must be an event that is uncaused. — ModernPAS
No, this would imply that every event is caused by another event, which is not what the first premiss asserts. The conclusion is that there must be a first cause that is uncaused, not a first event that is uncaused. — aletheist
if I showed you the ball on the cushion and asked you the cause of the indentation, you - and everyone else possessed of reason and not in the grips of a theory - would agree that the cause was the ball. — Bartricks
The OP is correct in what they say. There must be an event - so, an occurrence, a happening - that is uncaused. — Bartricks
Which argument? The one in the OP? I agree with that premiss, and even offered a supporting argument for it.Premise 2 of the argument is highly intuitively. — Bartricks
My worldview has nothing to do with it. If the indentation has always been present, then nothing caused it.Rejecting it becusae it doesn't fit with one's favourite worldview is incompetent. — Bartricks
Right, the result of a cause is just what an event is. An "uncaused event" is a self-contradiction.That's just what an event is — Bartricks
Lots of true propositions, especially in philosophy, are counterintuitive.That's counter-intuitive. — Bartricks
On the contrary, it entails that nothing caused the indentation, since there was no event of changing its shape.Finding out that the ball has always been on the cushion does not call that into question. — Bartricks
That is an unwarranted assumption that is not even part of the argument as presented in the OP. In fact, it directly contradicts its very first premiss--"Every event has a cause."There must be an event - so, an occurrence, a happening - that is uncaused. — Bartricks
No, you did not. If the indentation has always existed, then nothing caused it--not the ball, not the cushion, and certainly not the indentation itself.I showed that the assumption that all causation requires a cause that is prior to its effect is false. — Bartricks
Right, I was instead addressing the problem named in the thread title. And the original was about "the pious" and "the gods," so the common version that I presented simply updates the terminology for a monotheistic context.So, not addressing the problem in the OP. — Bartricks
The first one, obviously. If moral values are the values of God, then they are necessary, not contingent, since they must be consistent with His eternal and unchanging nature.make that subject God and tell me which premise you're denying. — Bartricks
if there can be no infinite regress of causes, then there must be an event that is uncaused. — ModernPAS
No, this would imply that every event is caused by another event, which is not what the first premiss asserts. — aletheist
Okay, but it still does not demonstrate that something can cause itself. Besides, if the ball and cushion "have always existed in that arrangement," then nothing caused the indentation, since the cushion was never in any other shape.The example shows that one thing can cause another without preceding it. — Bartricks
The Euthyphro is usually posed as a question: Is something good because God wills it, or does God will it because it is good? The first option makes goodness an arbitrary choice by God, while the second subordinates God to an external principle of goodness. Like many philosophical dilemmas, it sets up a false dichotomy; something is good because it is consistent with the eternal and unchanging nature of God, and everything that God wills is consistent with His eternal and unchanging nature.And it is the Euthyphro problem that I am interested in here. — Bartricks
More accurately, every series of events has a first uncaused cause.What we can conclude is that every event has a first uncaused cause or causes. — Bartricks
Which is exactly what I said; please read more carefully.The whole point of the argument is to establish that not all causation can be by events. — Bartricks
already addressed that--"then it would have to exist prior to itself and this is impossible.”What I do not understand is why something cannot be the cause of itself. — Bartricks
This is not a counterexample, because the indentation is not causing itself.Well, it is still true that the ball is causing the indentation, even though there was no time prior to the indentation when it was caused. — Bartricks
No, this would imply that every event is caused by another event, which is not what the first premiss asserts. The conclusion is that there must be a first cause that is uncaused, not a first event that is uncaused. The overall claim, of course, is that God caused the first event.if there can be no infinite regress of causes, then there must be an event that is uncaused. — ModernPAS
As I understand it, the supporting argument is that there cannot have been an actual infinite series of causes, because it never would have been completed by reaching the present.Thus, the claim in the second premise the there can be no infinite regress of causes is simply an unsupported assumption. — ModernPAS
Transliterated from the actual Greek work αλήθεια.Transliterated or translated? — god must be atheist
Thanks; but then, the denial that there is such a thing as (absolute) truth is self-refuting.Noble conviction you have. — god must be atheist
Thanks for asking. The Greek word for "truth" is transliterated aletheia, so I call myself "aletheist" because I believe that there is such a thing as (absolute) truth.By-the-by: what does your moniker mean? — god must be atheist
No, it is called a theorem because Gödel provided a proof; otherwise, it would be called a hypothesis or conjecture. Fermat's conjecture came to be known as a theorem because he claimed to have a proof, which no one ever found; Andrew Wiles finally came up with one in 1994.@TheMadFool (et al) this is a theorem by Godel, not a proof. — god must be atheist
Proof does not establish truth, it establishes justification. However, since mathematics is the science of drawing necessary conclusions about hypothetical states of affairs (Peirce), there is a sense in which mathematical justification is equivalent to mathematical truth. A sentence is "true" within a consistent formal system as long as it does not contradict the underlying assumptions (axioms). A sentence is "undecidable" within that same system if it can neither be proved nor disproved on the basis of those particular axioms.I sensed that there wasn't the required level of correspondence between Godel's incompleteness theorems (GIT) and the justified true belief (JTB) of philosophy. The shared characteristic between the two I was hoping to emphasize was the need for proof to establish truth. — TheMadFool
That would be Gödel's proof of his incompleteness theorem, and the correct term is not "unprovable" but undecidable.What was the sufficient proof for the Godel statement "this statement is true but unprovable"? — TheMadFool
In this context, I am not so much denying it as pointing out that it does not apply to all systems of formal logic. Informally, the claim is obviously false, since lots of propositions are true without ever having a formal proof. It seems like you may be confusing truth with justification.Also, it seems that you're denying my claim: truth of a proposition necessarily requires proof. — TheMadFool
Can you provide a proof that the truth of a proposition necessarily requires proof? If not, why do you claim that?That means it's possible for a proposition to be true and without proof. Can you name one such truth? — TheMadFool
No, the two Wikipedia quotes are not contradictory. The second one only affirms that a proof is sufficient for the truth of a proposition; it does not state that a proof is necessary for the truth of a proposition.On one hand mathematicians are of the view that truth requires proof and on the other they're claiming, through Godel, that some truths are unprovable. Isn't that a contradiction? — TheMadFool
I mean exactly what I said, quoting the Stanford article--Gödel's incompleteness theorem only applies to formal systems "within which a certain amount of arithmetic can be carried out" (emphasis mine).You mean it's possible to create an axiomatic system that is complete and consistent as long as it doesn't involve arithmetic? — TheMadFool
Because there are minimum requirements for a formal system to be able to generate the kind of undecidable sentence that Gödel's incompleteness theorem requires. gave an example of a formal system that can do some arithmetic, but not enough for the theorem to apply.Do you know why this is the case? — TheMadFool
This sounds like an endorsement of constructivist logic, such as intuitionistic logic, which requires a positive proof in order to affirm any proposition and accordingly denies the Law of Excluded Middle (LEM, either A or not-A must be true). By contrast, classical logic affirms LEM, which is why it allows double negation elimination (not not-A implies A) and proof by contradiction (reductio ad absurdum).If a proposition P is true then necessarily that a proof must exist for P being true. — TheMadFool
As already noted, it depends on which system of logic you have in mind, since Gödel's incompleteness theorem only applies to formal systems "within which a certain amount of arithmetic can be carried out" (Stanford). For example, there are well-established proofs that the now-standard systems of first-order propositional and predicate logic are both (deductively) complete and consistent.One thing I'd like to know is whether logic - the entire system - is complete or not. I vaguely remember reading somewhere that logic is a complete system. — TheMadFool
Because the real numbers correspond to all the possible combinations of rational numbers, and therefore are necessarily of greater multitude than the rational numbers themselves--which are of the same multitude as the natural numbers, along with the even numbers, the odd numbers, the whole numbers, the integers, etc.If I can find all the even numbers but line all the odd numbers with all the whole numbers, why can't I do this with all the real numbers? — Gregory
"Countable" is defined as being of the same multitude as the natural numbers, and thus applies to the rational numbers, the even numbers, the odd numbers, the whole numbers, the integers, etc. "Uncountable" is defined as being of a multitude greater than that of the natural numbers, and thus applies to the real numbers.Nothing has been settled to be countable or uncountable at that point yet — Gregory
It depends on what you mean by "argument forms." As just pointed out, what you seem to be seeking is an axiomatization of classical logic, which typically involves a few primitives and an inference rule. The "existential graphs" of Charles Sanders Peirce are an innovative diagrammatic alternative.Is our list of valid argument forms complete? — TheMadFool
No, the collection of all combinations of the subjects of a collection--even an infinite collection--is always of greater multitude than that collection itself. The integers and the rational numbers can be put into one-to-one correspondence with each other, but not with the real numbers, because those are of the next greater multitude. There is another multitude greater than that, and another greater than that, and so on endlessly--which is why an infinite collection of any multitude can never be "large" enough to qualify as a continuum.You can put a one to one correspondence between any infinite set, because infinite sets have units. — Gregory
That depends on what you mean by "parts." The portions of a continuum are indefinite, unless and until they are deliberately marked off by limits of lower dimensionality to create actual parts. For a one-dimensional continuum like a line or time, those limits are discrete and indivisible points or instants that serve as immediate connections between portions, but the portions themselves remain continuous--which is why they can always be divided further by inserting additional limits of any multitude, or even exceeding all multitude.Likewise, unless you are speaking of process philosophy, an object must have parts. These can be divided endlessly, so it is neither discrete nor continuous. — Gregory
Indeed, mathematics is the science of drawing necessary conclusions about hypothetical states of things, which may or may not match up with any real states of things.The problem is that mathematics is a way that we think about relations. The world isn't required to match that. — Terrapin Station
Again, a continuous line or interval of time does not consist of discrete points or instants at all, but we can mark any multitude of points or instants along it to suit our purposes. In other words, contrary to Cantor, there is a fundamental difference between a continuum and a collection.If we take time to be on a number line how many points of time are there between 1976 and 2019? — TheMadFool
What Cantor got right is that there is likewise a fundamental difference between an infinite collection and a finite collection, such that we cannot reason about them in the same way. The multitude of real numbers between any two arbitrary values is the same, because they can be put into one-to-one correspondence with each other.there are infinite numbers between 0 and 1, but it is intrinsical that there are more numbers between 0 and 2 — Filipe