Comments

  • What are people here's views on the self?
    Other than the specifics of the mechanics, is there anything particularly different about the scenario to object to? Physically, you are differently constituted than you once were. As for your sense of identity, if there is a process of transforming yourself at time 1 to yourself at time 2 such that you experience a continuity of identity at time 2, does it matter much what that process is?
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Moral claims aren’t in the business of trying to predict anything, so it’s not clear what you would even want from them to be the equivalent of “able to do so predictively”.Pfhorrest

    It is not that I want them to be predictive. It's that this quality is what makes theoretical models compelling contenders for (partial, with limited accuracy) approximations of an objective reality, which necessitates the existence of objective reality. You compare the methodology of science and moral philosophy as if the methodology was the crucial thing. It isn't: it's the predictive power of an assumed objective reality.

    Scientifically minded people, religious fundamentalists, and postmodernist social constructivists all disagree on how to judge truths about what is real.Pfhorrest

    Precisely. And the difference between the first and the second is that the understanding of the first is evidence-dependent, whereas the beliefs of the second are evidence-independent. If one's moral beliefs aren't affected by further evidence about morality, they are analogues of the second. The metaphysical thesis does not care about mechanisms, therefore is stoic in the face of evidence. A naturalist formulation of moral theory, on the other hand, ought to be evidence-driven.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    But every single datapoint matters, and all we have access to are a bunch if single datapoints.Pfhorrest

    But it would not be reasonable to deduce from this that a) we can therefore generalise from a single data point (or biased subset of data points) or b) that the veracity of that generalisation is data-independent. Again, the compelling argument for assuming an objective existence to gravity is not that we can make observations and gather testimony from others and generalise to other phenomena. It is that we can do so predictively. The assumption of objective moral truths has no equivalent reassurance.

    There is if they agree on a methodology by which to judge what is or isn’t moral.
    ...
    You do if you both agree on what counts as evidence, which is not a moral question but a more general philosophical one.
    Pfhorrest

    But you recognise that this isn't in any way objective? As in, this would not be something presumed to hold irrespective of the thoughts of those exact people agreeing. This would be two people defining and occupying a common frame of reference, if indeed they do reach agreement. Nothing has changed but their particular beliefs.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    But you can collaborate such that progress is achieved mutually, improving both your perspectives on charity and as a consequence the practical approaches that arise from them.Enrique

    Certainly. Via discussion, two people can synthesise their independent conceptions to progress the beliefs of both. But that progress is still per person, and is manifest in them each.

    That's all fact-based objectivity is in any sphere, inanimate, behavioral or whatever, the constructive convergence and equilibrating of theoretical viewpoints attained by a united front of revisionary, synthesizing experimental processes. Objectivity isn't "out there" to be irresolvably disputed depending on your point of view, it is a kind of cultural paradigm that creates joint truth by human sharing.Enrique

    I don't think this is a meaningful definition of objectivity then. If all of it is contained within the subjectivities of each mind, that is still plural subjectivities, not one objectivity. If you're considering some net measure of plural subjective knowledge, history and belief to be objectivity, e.g. statistics, then that is not mind-independent and we have no disagreement except on terminology. I think I've been clear that my objection is to the belief in mind-independent moral objectivity by which a proposition can be deemed objectively true or false. Your definition of objectivity does not have this character.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    If there's a universal core of oughts that applies to everyone - a privileged flavour derived from necessities of human functioning by an intellectual synthesis, it seems Pfhorrest wants to say these are true since they describe the deep structure of our oughts, and they are binding because they are actually occurrent. @Kenosha Kid comes in at this point and says because they are descriptions, you can't get behind the map of our oughts to get at the territory of any universal principles of morality without it ceasing to be a map.fdrake

    They're not even descriptions, but illogical abstractions. A description ought to be of something, but the only moral subjects are minds and, says the moral objectivist, these are unimportant. Minds are reduced to entities that can make true or false claims, or have true or false claims made about them.

    There are two maps in my view: a map between potentially unknowable genetic and cultural is-statements and subjective ought-statements, and a map between subjective ought-statements and objective ought-statements. The first is characterised by a severe loss of information, as the rational mind builds conceptions about itself as a moral agent in the world to answer non-moral ought-statements and, latterly, moral ones. This is a loss because necessarily the agent has no information about why they are compelled to answer such questions. We rationally answer them, but we do not rationally decide that such questions are asked, rather we are compelled physiologically and neurologically on the basis of natures and nurtures that we are not typically knowledgeable about. The OP largely concerns this, and descriptions here are relevant at both ends.

    The second map is where description gives way to imposition. It is pragmatic to agree a set of objective laws to limit edge case behaviour within a group, but these laws impose, rather than describe, moral truth values. Moral objectivity goes a step further and generalises individual or popular subjective conceptions to everyone ever according to some mysterious out-there law. There is no descriptive aspect to this. It might be advised by some descriptions about the person arguing for the rightness or wrongness of an act; it might be advised by some descriptions of consensus witnessed by that person, but the outputs are still proposals of imposition, not description. There are occasions when they might seem descriptive. I would predict that, while historically people have argued that the proposition 'slavery is good' is true, one could expect that almost no one would argue that 'it is good to be a slave' is true (hypocrisy) from which one might make Pfhorrest's case that the proposition is false with those attesting it to be true being either deceitful or in error. However, there are other reasons why the second statement is universally false. It is illogical to generalise from such consensus that a) the proposition is false uncontingently and b) all such values are similarly predictive, predictiveness being the reason for accepting other kinds of claims of objectivity (viz. science).

    The lack of justification in this generalisation from subjective to objective values is proportional to the lack of clarity in the metaphysical thesis itself which, unlike other claims to objectivity, has no interest in how such propositions can be objectively true, why they have the values they have, how they relate to -- let's remind ourselves -- the only moral subjects in existence, or how we can ask questions to infer what their properties are, which is precisely why comparison to objectivity in the hard sciences is bogus in my opinion.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    But we did. cultural practices varied enormously according the what little evidence we have from archaeology.Isaac

    Sure, but the timescales of that cultural variation are typically generational, maybe millennial. But 100,000 years of staying in group sizes of 20-50... that's a tall order for culture alone.

    We don't have historical data to confirm or deny this, but the thought experiment that keeps running through my head is this: A tribe of 20 or 30 people operates ultra-cooperatively, with fairly homogenous socialisation across two, three generations that reinforce the social biases we have. The group grows to the point where a) individuals cannot mentally manage networks that large and b) some non-negligible variation of culture can be sustained. This threatens the very basis of their social instincts, since no one can be sure that the person their dealing with is sufficiently like them to have the same values and react the same way. Disputes arise, confusion, aggression, stress, distrust, perhaps a polarisation of the group.

    Baboons handle this by the strong imposing hierarchical structures which keep the weak stressed and subordinate. Naturally, it seems, we don't. Our cooperativeness appears to be effectively an intolerance to diversity that separates social cultures as they occur, like a schism in a religion. Whether that schism is violent or peaceful, who knows? We seem to have filled up the globe, so I'm guessing we generally divided peacefully.

    The nature and consistency of this divisiveness seem very in line with those same inherent traits I discussed in the OP, which, to be selected for, required the likelihood of trust, accurate-enough empathy, and reciprocity. It is these things that would break down if social mores (from biases and mimesis) became plural and group sizes became cumbersome. It seems more reasonable to me that culture, if it gave rise to different socialisations, would have been divisive rather than unifying.

    I think instead that cultures that eventually did unify larger groups, such as specialisation, law and hierarchy, did so because individuals had or thought they had something to lose by striking out alone. Agriculture meant that particular individuals within a social group were food-providers. Individual skill, more than teamwork and accurate mimesis, suddenly mattered and, if you wanted to eat, you had to be a farmer or be in his favour. The law does this too: it gives you much to lose by disagreeing. The church does this best: earthly punishment plus promise of eternal punishment afterward. And hierarchical groups do this by having the strongest fighters enforce social roles with violence.

    In each case, the culture that unifies does so by having and asserting power. That sort of culture I can buy keeping us together for thousands of years, but these are largely variants of baboon culture. Deep down, we're small-town egalitarians. And I say this as a fervent multiculturalist myself.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Yes, I believe the God of Abraham religions are the chief cause of some of our most serious problems because Judaism, Christianity, and Islam mean living with false beliefs and not science.Athena

    Yes, religion in itself has terrible effects. I do think it is immoral to produce people who cannot discern between fantasy and reality. I consider that "harm". I merely meant that some of those things you see as effects of religion are more like effects with religion having common causes. There is an impressive correlation between religion, conservativism, prejudice, nationalism, anti-intellectualism and capitalism, but that doesn't necessarily mean one in particular causes the other. Historically, nationalism seems to stand out as the unifying force, although each will influence one another. But yes for an even more stark lesson in how religion can destroy societies, look east.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Every individual observation rules out some possibilities about what might be objectively real. An account of objective reality has to account for every single observation, otherwise it’s not actually objective.Pfhorrest

    And that's the point. Objective nature is inferred from generalisation, not a single data point.

    It kind of sounds like you’re implying confirmationism here, that enough observations can prove something to be true, rather than the falsificationist view that anything might be true that has not yet been observed false.Pfhorrest

    I have repeatedly said quite the opposite of this, that the existence of an objective reality is the best and simplest explanation for empirical facts, but it is by no means proven, rather than a better or simpler explanation is not forthcoming. This is not the case for morality, where the existence of objective moral truths is an neither accurate of our experiences nor the simplest explanation for them.

    There being an objective reality means that something can be actually false, not just disbelieved; and there being an objective morality means that something can be actually bad, not just disliked.Pfhorrest

    Indeed, not just true or false for each person individually but "out there". And what is compelling about science is that laws hold as if they were true, not just believed ("The great thing about facts is...") That is, you can present empirical evidence to someone with a belief and show them that that belief is credible or not. You cannot do this with morality. If someone disagrees with me, there's no means by which I can refer to a fact that makes one of our beliefs incredible.

    If I believe it is better to give to charities in Africa than in Britain, and my friend believes that it is wrong to ignore misery on one's own doorstep in favour of classier 'TV' charities abroad, I might refer to facts of efficacy (my charity has achieved more change than his) or statistics, but I have no recourse to a piece of evidence that says one of us has a more compelling case. Assuming the existence of such inaccessible source of truth cannot be justified. Assuming the existence of, say, gravity can be, even if the objective truth about gravity is very different from our theories.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    No doubt. All that is the empirical mode of perception. That altruism, empathy, and good...justice, beauty, liberty, etc., are not detected by the senses, even if objects of them are, indicates some other mode of presence must be possible.Mww

    But my point was that something is present to my consciousness, just not anything like a priori knowledge. It is not a rational thing present, but emotions and attention biases. I am presented with a vision of a child in danger, and senses of panic, distress, focus, and urgency. I am not presented with some voice or inter-title: "One ought to help the child."

    And there it is. A different mode of presence. In addition to the empirical mode given to your senses by the person, the person also presents to your rational mode some activity of his that elicits a feeling in you not given by the person as an object, but by what the person is doing.Mww

    Of course! As per the OP, we are in an environment in which moral actions must be rationalised. But my consciousness being presented with moral drives is not the same thing as my reason having their essence.

    Dunno about a sense of qua feeling or emotion, but anything a priori is absent any and all matters of experience. From that, any cognition resulting from the conjoining of conceptions is thought only, hence a priori.Mww

    This is the old-fashioned rationalism I reject. There is a very real analogue to this in our physiological responses that can bias us in a given direction, and the empirically-verified existence of these negates the need for other sources of moral knowledge. But this is not "knowledge" in itself.

    Anyone can observe the object of my action. If that action has been determined by my lawfully deterministic will, it is a moral action. And indeed, possibly an immoral one.Mww

    I just knew you had a dark side :rofl: For sure, moral actions are objective. I either did it, or I didn't: that is a matter of fact rather than pathological. But those rational decisions are still based on not a priori knowledge but unconscious reactions to stimuli (whose results are inputs to our rational decisions). Good is pre-determined for the conscious mind: it is left with the question of whether to act on it, what the desired outcome is, and how that desired outcome is best realised. These are all issues of ambiguity based on an already-provided notion of good, or a real, social analogue to it.

    Not a contradiction, but a confusion of source: reason used to determine moral things, reason used to determine all things........unconscious decisions.Mww

    My first quote was wrong. Never mind. Point being if you accept that some decisions are not made rationally (and I think the current consensus is this is all but a few percent of human decisions), it cannot follow that a moral decision has to be rational. It may be, and is for most of us today, but needn't have been in the past.

    Are there different kinds of problems?Mww

    Sure.

    I wouldn’t call those factors of problems. Factored into problem solving, perhaps?Mww

    Yeah, 'twas what I meant.

    That still leaves rationality fully in charge of that of which we are conscious.Mww

    Yes, except the conscious mind is also a very bad quality-checker of unconscious decisions, as per the (typical reaction to the) bat & ball problem. So not everything the rational mind thinks it is in charge of either.

    My unconscious mind is not the me I know, so if it causes errors in me, then the rational mind I know should be the boss.Mww

    According to the conscious mind, which does think it's the boss. It's a scary thought, isn't it: we are mostly not the thing we think of as 'I'. This is why psychology is illuminating: we learn things about ourselves, otherwise no one would bother with psychologists.

    And that's just the brain. Don't even start thinking about how we are colonies of bacteria in an awesome self-aware organic landcraft. :joke:
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    The interesting bit of morality is the culturally mediated bit. That, I think, would have been less the case in pre-agricultural times, not because they relied more on the defaults, but because there was only one culture to learn from, there was a strong line of non-pedagogic influence (mixed ages), a relatively stable environment, small group sizes (minimising Chinese whisper effects), no strong advantage to selfishness, no virtual social groups (which are too easy to manipulate).Isaac

    Yes, I agree: homogenous socialisation is a necessary condition for unambiguous social behaviour, and small group sizes is a necessary condition for homogenous socialisation. Historically, since we were small tribes, it is possible for nature to select on the basis of that, even if homogenous socialisation itself were an emergent effect rather than a genetic bias in its own right.

    However we do have to factor in that small social groups appears to have been preferred through our history, prior to the advent of agriculture. Unlike baboons, we did not naturally expand in group size. As with the all of these matters, the real question is: why the uniformity?

    For me the only key elements I have as my foundation are that it has to be pre-human (Frans deWaal's work on primates and Sapolsky's peaceful baboons seem compelling evidence to me that pro-social behaviour is pre-human), and it has to be largely culturally mediated - by which I mean learnt through childhood, with perhaps some limits and constraints set by evolved predispositions.Isaac

    Yes, I think most of our individual social drives are pre-human. Like I said in the OP, we inherit from our social ancestors... and our presocial ones. But humans are still uniquely ultracooperative (unique among mammals). There is, either by combination, circumstance, cultural innovation, or genetic innovation, something longstanding within us that makes us more inclined to high levels of cooperation within social groups. Having a single joint goal, such as in hunting, between so many individuals is unique. Part of this is likely mental capacity, but part must come from a higher confidence that members of your group think as you do, and members who do not are identifiable on the whole -- i.e. greater empathy. This goes well beyond the social behaviours of primates for me.

    The more I think about it, while I do think culture is extremely important, 100,000 years of seemingly stable, small group sizes seems too long to have a generic cultural explanation. Cultural timescales are expected to be much, much smaller. The point of Chinese whispers is that it changes, but we didn't seem to change in this respect until 12,000 years ago. It begs the question: what kept those aspects of culture constant and uniform over so much time and so many different, disparate social groups?

    When someone says that a cold-blooded murder is morally good, the appropriate response is "No, you're not using the words correctly, that's not the sort of thing we call 'morally good'".Isaac

    Yes, that is a logical error. The person in question is already speaking of objective moral truths not their own feelings ("I like hurting people" -- Mary Bell). While a belief that murder is objectively bad is understandable, a belief that it is objectively good makes no sense.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    It's a bunch of small pieces of the one big objective "ought", in the same way that individual observations are only small pieces of the one big objective "is".Pfhorrest

    Individual observations do not speak to the efficacy of a belief in an objective reality. Is the the regularity, the predictability that suggests such a thing. There is no equivalent thing in morality.

    You have "no access to any objective reality" either by those standards. You only have the small pieces you can subjectively experience, and your trust in other people's reports of their experiences (that what they say is looks true, looks true). Similarly, you only have the small pieces of "objective morality" you can subjectively experience, and your trust in other people's reports of their experiences (that what they say feels good, goods good). In both cases, objectivity just means accounting for all of those experiences together without bias.Pfhorrest

    I can learn about my ideas of an objective reality by checking (observing the same phenomenon again), by consensus (observing agreement or disagreement with others), and by generalising (observing new phenomena). Doing this iteratively reinforces the assumption of an objective reality without truly necessitating one.

    To generalise this to morality, it is insufficient to simply say: "Objective reality of external phenomena has been well justified, so we're safe to apply the same assumptions to morality." You need to infer an objective moral reality in the same way. But when I check my moral values, I do not see the same consistency. I do not react the same way in similar situations each time. I do not find that I generally agree with others who have been in the same situations. And I do not find that learning not to hit people gives me an automatic knowledge of the morality of horn-tooting douchebags. It seems in all respects a subjective, irregular phenomenon, and the assumption of objectivity is not supported.

    That just evidences the confusion I'm trying to clear up here. You seem to place "objective reality" in the same category: that objective reality isn't the unbiased total of all possible empirical experiences, but it's some thing out there somewhere that causes all those experiences.Pfhorrest

    That is accurate, and I believe it is justified for the above reason. By "out there somewhere", I mean independent of our observations of and beliefs about it, i.e. independent of subjective experience. I think this is an uncontroversial definition of "objective" but I can see that we have meant different things by "objective reality".

    If it is your belief in your objectivism that, had no conscious entities every existed in the universe then the universe would not exist, then yes we are defining "objective" and "transcendental" in opposite and incompatible ways. If you believe that the universe pre-existed conscious experience of it, then you too believe that the universe has an objective (independent of subjective experience) existence. There is an analogue here in the OP: the non-teleological natural selection of characteristics that underlie our moral conceptions also pre-existed them. They are the objective (independent of those conceptions) reality of those conceptions. To the extent that the latter are not good approximations of the former, those conceptions do not themselves have an objective existence.

    I do not consider the objective universe to be defined by the sum total of our experiences of it, but rather the latter is merely our best knowledge of the former. As I have said before, models, including mental models, merely approximate aspects of reality. You cannot derive the objective thing itself from those models.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    That the human has qualities is irrefutable, so what does it matter where they come from as long as it is tacitly acknowledged they are present?Mww

    I acknowledge that something is present (the banging at the door). When I see an apple, feel an apple, taste an apple, even though these are all indirect ideas of an apple, I happily acknowledge that something is present. However I don't have this sense of a priori moral knowledge or of moral objective existence. I feel pain when I see someone suffering -- that pain is present. I feel glad when I help them -- that gladness is present. And the things I suggest in the OP are consistent with that.

    What I reject are beliefs about where these things come from, where they exist, what values they can have, what values they must have, what qualities they have, that proceed from no data but one person's sensations and a lot of imagination. The artefacts of moral metaphysics (and I don't just mean Kant's Metaphysics of Morals, but any metaphysical origin story for my moral values) are not present like an apple is present. My feelings are.

    There is no intrinsic contradiction is supposing the quality of good is every bit as present as the quality of altruism or empathy.
    ...
    Altruism is represented by selfless acts, empathy is represented by your “emotions and insights”, good is represented by my “moral dispositions”.
    Mww

    An assumption of the OP is that this is not justified. The social imperatives of each individual human (bar exceptions) explain too much of why certain broad classes of acts (those that cause suffering) cause us pain and another broad class (those that reduce suffering) cause us pleasure for a separate, independent quality of good or bad to coexist. Occam's razor again: one of these things is superfluous, and by no coincidence one of these things has no empirical evidence.

    If we have this social biology and we independently have a priori notions of good and evil, then there's been some crazy double-counting. We ought to be exceptionally moral with all this moral guidance. So I feel it really is a choice: follow the evidence, or stay true to beliefs.

    Also, is altruism represented by selfless acts? If I think altruistic thoughts but, say, I cannot act upon them, am I no longer an altruist? Another position of the OP is that one cannot act on all possible altruistic impulses. There are too many people in our world now. I don't feel this makes people non-altruistic, just realistic and pragmatic.

    System 1 is a problem-solver. There's all sorts of problems it solves that I have no consciousness of.
    — Kenosha Kid

    Agreed, in principle...

    on moral issues, reason must be used to determine an intended behaviour because there is ambiguity.
    — Kenosha Kid

    I submit that reason must be used to determine anything of which determination is possible.
    Mww

    These are contradictory. If one accepts that human decisions are sometimes made unconsciously, one cannot hold that reason must be involved in every human determination.

    Ambiguity merely regulates the certainty of the determination.Mww

    Prior to a determination, the correct course is necessarily ambiguous, else no determination would be necessary. There would be no problem to solve at all. If I am a dumb machine that only has one function, there is no need to determine which function to execute. Multiplicities of possible 'whats' and 'hows' are themselves ambiguities.

    So is there an answer to “does the psychologist admit to different kinds of reason, as the philosopher absolutely requires?”Mww

    Different to problem-solving? No, I don't think so. I've been racking my brain for a counter-example (looking at a painting? teaching a class? watching a film?) and can't think of a single thing that reason does that doesn't reduce to some kind of problem to solve. There are certainly things that reason has that aren't problems to solve in themselves but are factors of problems: the evidences of our senses, our feelings. But these are inputs. The outputs are decisions.

    This suggests my unconscious mind actually does something to the picture of shaded squares.Mww

    Indeed it does. The unconscious mind does a lot. It filters out unimportant noises like traffic. It interprets patterns in shapes. It shifts all the colours of what you see, if it can, such that the ambient colour is closer to white (which is why filmmakers can't use normal lightbulbs for interior shots: everything comes out yellower, because that's the actual ambient colour of your room... you can try this yourself). It gives images 3D depth (a common basis for optical illusions). It assesses body language and provokes emotions that your consciousness receives as feelings. It gives us proprioception. It turns impure notes into pure ones. It guides you to work based on pattern recognition so you don't need to think about how you get there. And all that and much more while regulating your entire body. It's a legend! The rational mind is an employee hired for solving certain problems that now thinks it's the boss!

    Why couldn’t optical illusions just be an error in judgement, given from improper understanding of that which is the cause of it?Mww

    For one thing, the uniformity of the errors. If it were down to judgement, one would expect good judges and bad. For another, well, do you recall making such a judgement?
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    There is a direct relationship between racism and Christianity and the problem with education that we have experienced, preventing our democracy from being fully realized besides having a prison system based on false beliefs and the highest number of incarcerated people in western culture. The belief system supports the military-industrial complex and the notion that our military is serving God. That is a bit of a moral problem with serious ramifications.Athena

    Yes, Anglicanism is not what Christianity once was. (Worth remembering that Christianity was the moral revolution of altruism and empathy, until it itself acquired might.) Do you believe Christianity to be the chief cause rather than just another symptom? I'm unsure. Your country was the first major secularist country in the world. You had founding fathers who were quite incredulous about the notion of God in general and of Christianity in particular. Your country was religiously diverse while remain that secular too. It seems to me that nationalism was the American illness, and Christianity one of the government's rallying points for nationalistic sentiment.
  • Is silencing hate speech the best tactic against hate?
    As such, it needs to be fought.tim wood

    For sure, I just disagree with prior restraint as the best way of winning the fight. If you could snuff out racism this way, I'd be all for it. But it seems a bit fallacious. Censorship is anti-racist, therefore it will stop racism! How? By alerting every individual mind to the concept of racism without giving any of them the opportunity to have a single emotional reaction against it? No. Censorship is not a preventative: it is a means of creating generations of silent, unchecked, unjudged, unhumiliated, unargued-against racists. Except of course when they all get together, making themselves the only people with opinions that matter.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Failure to accept evolution and the sciences that study our humanness is a very serious morality problem with social, economic, and political ramifications.Athena

    Well said. I agree with the worry about the ramifications of non-empirical moral metaphysics. I think that understanding what we are, and why we are that way, should shed light on which ethics are consistent with human society and which aren't.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Every experience someone has that feels bad to them, i.e. that hurts them — not their emotional or cognitive judgement of the morality of something they perceive, but the immediate experience of a bad sensation, where the sensation itself conveys its own badness, i.e. pain etc — take that to be bad (an “ought not”), as it seems to be, and add that to the list of things that are bad (a bunch if “ought nots”), which then demarcates the boundaries of what still might be good (“maybe ought”).Pfhorrest

    But this is describing individuals. It does not describe objective "oughts" and "ought nots" but rather those arising from the experience of each person separately/

    It’s really not though. There being something banging on the door is there being something that is actually (objectively) moralPfhorrest

    Then you're making no differentiation between an empirical fact and a belief. It is an empirical fact that something is banging on the door. Objective morality is not an empirical quantity: it cannot be detected, or verified. It is only a belief, like that there is a monster at the door. What I can measure are my moral feelings: how I feel when I see a child in distress, or a person being attacked, etc. I have no access to any objective moral truths, but I do have access to scientific evidence that those feelings are explicable in terms of physiological drives. I have a window to see what it is that is banging on the door, and whether, knowing this, the belief is justified.

    I’m just saying that the persistent shared experience of something banging on the door is all there is to there being something really banging on it.Pfhorrest

    Right, and the beliefs we generate about it aren't the thing itself. Likewise something objective concerning morality exists, but it need not be what we believe it to be. Asking how the branch could explain the presence of a monster is like asking how natural social responses and drives can explain what we morally ought to do. They cannot, because those moral oughts are statements about beliefs that morality is essentially teleological rather than reactive.

    But to agreed that there is this persistent shared experience of something banging on the door, yet deny that anything is really banging at the door, because of a doubt that monsters exist, is to conflate any belief in SOMETHING banging at the door with a belief in monsters specifically doing so.Pfhorrest

    Right, and the little girl doesn't deny that there's something banging at the door, she just denies the beliefs of what that thing is. And this is where we're at. I don't deny that we are moral beings. I deny that there is one objective set of moral values. I accept that we can do statistics with morality, which is the closest you and I come I think.

    For me, the drives are the real thing, and they objectively exist, insofar as they are amenable to scientific enquiry and, as I've said before, the simplest and best explanation for the success of science is the existence of an objective reality (which scientific models are analogous to in aspects and with limited accuracy). To that extent, real morality is objectively real. What is consciously experienced is not that, but the second-hand, partial results of that, in the same way that what we consciously see in an optical illusion is not what is in front of us, nor what our minds receive, but the outputs of unconscious processes. We can but rationalise and create beliefs about that moderated, partial data. But those beliefs cannot be more accurate than what is really going on; however they can be significantly less accurate. If those beliefs assign teleology to something that is fundamentally non-teleological, those beliefs are wrong. The thesis of the OP is that everything essential is non-teleological. There are no fundamental, rational "oughts", only selected-for (genetically or memetically) responses and drives.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    we have left the reasoning for what-is-to-be-done behind. And that will always be moral reasoning, when the thing to be done is primarily qualified by the goodness of it.Mww

    Yes, I feel the crux upon us. So this is the rationalist view of morality: I am presented with a situation, I rationally deduce what the good outcome will be, and I rationally deduce how to realise that outcome. But where did the quality of goodness come from? What makes that outcome "good"?

    Before heading off on that dialectical tangent, does the psychologist admit to different kinds of reason, as the philosopher absolutely requires? In other words, does your “generic problem solving” type of reasoning distinguish itself from the type of reasoning that grounds your “compelled to behave”?Mww

    Problem-solving is already vague enough. System 1 is a problem-solver. There's all sorts of problems it solves that I have no consciousness of. The rational mind is to me an algorithmic problem-solver.

    Behaviour is an outcome, physiological and neurological responses to stimuli are drives, some of which drive behaviours, some drive changes of internal state. Some of the those drives will require rational consideration to become behaviours. Basically, my impression of the rule-of-thumb is: if you have time or ambiguity, you need reason.

    The last part of the OP is that, on moral issues, reason must be used to determine an intended behaviour because there is ambiguity. I might make a joke in all virtual social groups bar one, perhaps a NSFW joke. I have to modulate my behaviour based on what is good for work. This is precisely what arises from not existing among relatives and neighbours with the same social mores in a small social group.

    If empathy boils down to mere recognition, which requires something to be observed, apparently negating being unaware. A philosopher will naturally balk at any phenomenon that does not present itself to our rationality, especially a stimuli-response example of it.Mww

    I don't think you can speak for all philosophers. After all, all scientists are just natural philosophers with a methodology. But, yes, that's what I am saying: empathy is an automatic process in which the unconscious mind mirrors the circumstances of another in order provoke emotions and insights, and it is these outputs that we are conscious of, if we are conscious of them at all.

    Not to mention, if we can rationalize with it, how can we not be aware of it? Or must we now separate being aware of, from being conscious of?Mww

    Whenever you see an optical illusion, you are unaware of the things your unconscious mind has done to the image before presenting it to your consciousness for consideration. You can still use what is provided to your consciousness for consideration, you just can't get back to the original image or know what was done with it.

    Jeeez, it sucks getting old. After spending all that time with a book written by him, it never even crossed my mind. Predispositions. (Sigh) If I’d been proper and used his last name with all those equivalences, I might have got it right.Mww

    Nah, my bad. I'm still impressed you read it so quickly. I've been reading the same book for months. (More in a music rut atm.)
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Again, encultured responses to a situation outweigh rational considerations.Isaac

    Yes, I agree it must be cultural in part. It might also be modal. Large groups subdivide, hence rankings. Relations within ranks might have been more egalitarian for the same reason that smaller groups are more egalitarian. Rather than naturally extending egalitarianism to the whole group after the catastrophe, less aggressive males mimicked the now deceased aggressive males as a cultural replication, not toward lower-ranking males but toward the peers who were previously dominated by high-ranking males perhaps.

    It's parameters are set by the tools we use (the hard-wiring), but within those parameters, there's considerable scope and modifications to the environment or social structures reveal those other options.Isaac

    I'd go slightly further. The mode of the culture might be quite arbitrary, and I think how arbitrary is highlighted in the baboon case where there is absolutely no benefit to what they did, but uniformity of social structures typically speaks to an underlying cause. This could in principle be a common culture, which would suggest similarity of cultures, or another predisposition, which would allow for diversity of cultures.

    It's worth pointing out that the emerging inter-rank aggressive culture that Sapolsky described is likely a transitory effect of a catastrophic event. Generally, animals who expend large resources and take mortal risks to zero benefit or their own detriment do not prosper. The more stable culture is likely the lower-rank egalitarianism arising from reduced stress. As per the Boehm article, it is a predictable response to a smaller group size and greater resources, and it won't hurt that the self-harming dominance of higher ranking members will be evidentally bad in an egalitarian culture.

    Things change when you bring power back into the equation. If high-ranking individuals attacked, exiled or killed egalitarian members, there would then be benefit in conforming to this nonsensical culture and it would persist longer. This covers quite a few human cultures, I feel, and speaks to the power of culture over sense.

    Usually with innovators (the active development of social norms), a smaller group size leads to greater diversity as there's less of a tendency to revert to the mean (we see this in some of the seemingly bizarre cultural practices in isolated tribes).Isaac

    I'm aware of this happening due to outside influence (trying to build runways made of logs to summon planes full of food, or building harbours to attract boats). I'm not aware of any cases of this occurring, spontaneously or gradually, within a small isolated group. Did you have anything in mind?

    To my knowledge, innovation in tribes (without outside influence) is generally mimetic, not pedagogical, i.e. the innovator has no authority and, to boot, is not necessarily aware of why their innovation is successful (Dennett's boat builders again). I'll firm up on this in a subsequent post, but if you have counter-examples ready that'll save me the effort (laziness is my moral virtue).

    I'm not sure I'd go as far as to say social dominance was therefore selected for. I think it's sufficient that it remain a threat. If you see social behaviours as the result of culturally propagated norms, then it only need be the case that anti-social behaviours be possible for there to be an advantage to fierce egalitarianism.Isaac

    Boehm's modal dominance seems reasonable to me, and he seems to think that a biological basis is the consensus. But, even though human groups have mostly been small, we may have evolved from large precursor species groups, so it's not a given that, if there is a biological basis for dominance, it is particularly for dominance of the group over the individual.

    Again, you further seem to qualify that with something about taking into account everyone's meta-ethical positions and coming to some 'more right' meta-ethical position, but a) I've yet to establish how this actually happens, and b) even then, the sum total of everyone's meta-ethical positions is still an 'is', there's nothing to say we 'ought' to take that to be our meta-ethical position.Isaac

    Yes, well put, and I think this is the problem with the 'ought' complaint. There are no more justified schemes for deriving oughts, only less justified ones. As far as I've ever been able to tell, such objections are not only predicated on unjustifiable assumptions, they fail their own burden-of-proof criteria.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    But "harmful" and "bad" seem to me roughly synonyms.Pfhorrest

    Because you are a socially-inclined human being. If your pre-social drives were dominant, it might seem that "harm" and "opportunity" were synonyms, or "harmed" and "non-threatening". Harmful and bad only seem synonymous for a pre-existing, altruistic definition of "bad".

    That is the "notion of good" that we share, and exactly why I say to appeal to hedonic experiences as the common ground for determining what in particular is good.Pfhorrest

    Right, and what in particular is good is a question arising from the lack of a pre-existing answer given by innate biases and homogeneous socialisation. It depends on those innate biases having no fitness in your environment and your socialisation being incomplete or incompatible with another's. In a small group, these questions would not arise, only the questions of whether to do good/bad (priorities) and how to do good/bad.

    This is exactly the conflation of phenomenalism with nihilism that I think underlies half of the views I'm againstPfhorrest

    Someone or something keeps banging at the door. Everyone says, "Holy crap, a monster." (an unjustified interpretation of a real phenomenon). Parents teach their kids, "Don't open the door!" A few people toy with the idea that there's no monster at the door. "Are you mad? You can hear the monster banging! How can you be nihilistic?!"

    One day a little girl sneaks upstairs and peeks through a window. She can't be sure, but it looks like there's tree branch banging against the door in the wind. She goes downstairs and says it looks like there's no monster. "Nihilist! She says nothing is banging against the door." (error: NOT (A+B) implies NOT B). She tries to explain, no there is something banging, it's just a tree branch. "Then how do you explain the monster with your tree branch?" She can't.

    This is essentially the conversation we're having. I believe in the banging, I just believe it isn't a monster doing it. (I believe in the objective reality of the phenomenon underlying our rational conceptions of morality, I just don't believe in the objective reality of a given rational conception.) You therefore identify an error correctly: the conflation of phenomonalism (I see a tree branch banging against the door) with nihilism (there's nothing banging against the door), but you misidentified the person doing the conflating.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    To me, “externally validated” might mean physically exhibited, manifest outside the agent himself.Mww

    Ah I think I misunderstood you and covered this elsewhere in my response to you. Yes, I agree, having a biological social drive cannot tell you how to satisfy that drive. We do need reason to figure out how to do e.g. the good thing, in the same way we need reason to figure out which roads to take on a drive. The reasoning is not moral, it's just generic problem-solving.

    External validation for altruism is easy....actually helping somebody immediately validates it.Mww

    That tells us that someone was compelled (be it external, biological or willed) to behave altruistically. It does not validate that altruistic drives are "good". Which is what I thought you were saying.

    Empathy....maybe, maybe not. Being empathetic towards someone is a rational activity, so....not much external validation there.Mww

    Empathy is a neurological response we are unaware of taking place in our brains. It cannot be rational. We can rationalise with it, but it appears to be a dumb, conditional, stimuli-response phenomenon.

    What’s the earliest proper exposition of your altruism/empathy social drives?Mww

    Individually, they're largely pre-homo. Cognitive empathy likely did not develop as a social mechanism, but as a means of gauging the threat or vulnerability of an individual in sub- or even pre-social mammals. Altruism itself certainly developed as a parenting skill, not a social one. These traits are present in other mammalian species. This article concludes that humans had a unique evolutionary pathway for social altruism, in addition to socialisations and their psychological adaptations, whereas the one I quoted above to Isaac seems to suggest common genetic heritage with modal behaviours to explain the universality of egalitarianism in hunter-gatherer tribes. Obviously they're not the same behaviours: egalitarianism does not necessitate altruism.

    Since ultra-cooperative behaviour is seen only in humans among mammalian species, it's not possible to study earlier potentially ultra-cooperative groups, since all the contenders are extinct. A more complete understanding of the genetic basis of why we are so social might allow us to posit that earlier homo species of similar group sizes were also socially altruistic, but unfortunately we can never verify it. by studying e.g. homo erectus in situ.

    DK.....(stabbing haphazardly)....direct knowledge?Mww

    Haha I meant Daniel Kahneman :rofl: My bad.

    So where do we go from here?Mww

    Do you mean in this discussion or as a species?
  • Metaphysics Defined
    The pattern-recognition you reference has nothing to do with whether physicalism, idealism, or some other ontological system is true - or else with what types of causality (efficient, teleological, formal, material as just some examples) are true - or else with the nature of time (e.g., presentist, eternalist, or what not) - or else with what laws of thought (law of identity, of noncontradiction, of excluded middle) are true - or else with the nature of self as that which is conscious of (e.g., it being a machine or not).javra

    I have yet to argue that causality is real. I am arguing that science works fine (insofar as it does) whether causality is real or not. It does not need to take a metaphysical stance. Metaphysics categorises science as taking a particular metaphysical position consistent with science, but science doesn't refer to metaphysics at all. That is the argument, so it is your response that is the straw man I'm afraid.

    That we have historically established a set of metaphysical beliefs X which have been used to engage in the modern empirical sciences we have; which, in turn, have empirically evidenced themselves to be fruitful in innumerable (but by no means all) ways; does not negate the fact that today's empirical sciences are necessarily founded on metaphysical beliefs X - this in the plural.javra

    Going back to Democritus, yes, the birth of science fell inside metaphysics, because there was no empirical evidence for atoms. It does not follow that science has a metaphysical basis. Science itself is empirical, and empiricism replaces the need for metaphysics such as determinism. We can detect such patterns phenomonologically without adopting a position of belief in such patterns. When empiricism is not consistent with determinism, such as in the measurement problem of quantum mechanics, determinism is not "believed" in because no such pattern is detected. (A different pattern, consistent with probabilism, is detected.)
  • Is silencing hate speech the best tactic against hate?


    If you ban an idea, you also ban universal reaction to that idea, letting legislature take the place of public opinion. But legislature only tells you what you can do, not what's right to think. The opinions of your peers are far more important in influencing your own opinions, including in cementing a robust position against things.

    Recently in the UK, posh moron Laurence Fox (of the Fox acting nobility) unexpectedly aired his hitherto unknown views of racism on a panel show called Question Time. And it was great! Not because of his views, naturally, which, had anyone expected them, would likely have invalidated him from speaking (QT generally tries to get a diversity of opinion, but also to keep the public complaints sufficiently low that the BBC won't get itself referred). But because everyone in the UK hates him for it.

    What would you rather happen to some naive, confused posh white boy who has only ever met people of colour who swear blind they're happy to work for his family? To see Laurence Fox getting his ass handed to him by an entire country? Or for Laurence Fox to come up to him and say, "You know all this racism stuff is a myth, right?"
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    One is active, the other passive. The active one is about influencial members trying to stand outIsaac

    Gray, who I linked an article by earlier, seems to think that reverse domination and the like are socialisations rather than particularly selected for. My scepticism about this is based on the uniformity of "fierce egalitarianism" in hunter-gathered groups.

    Another anthropologist even believes that dominance hierarchies might themselves be socialisations:

    This means that both some kind of social dominance hierarchy and some degree of group leadership, present in all humans and in all three African great apes, can be plausibly hypothesized to have existed in the African common ancestor.
    The above argument has been made at the level of behavior, but implicit in it is the notion that the African common ancestor and its four descendant species are genetically disposed to develop dominance behavior and group leadership. I have cited several theorists who suggest that dominance tendencies may be innate, and I agree with them. However, in considering genetic dispositions to hierarchical behavior, it is important to be as precise as possible about the types of behavior that are readily learned: both competitive dominance and submission are useful to individuals organized by dominance hierarchies, be they orthodox or reverse.
    When a behavior is universal or even very widespread, the question arises whether it is not part of "human nature." In beginning to think in more specific terms about human nature as a potential influence on cultural behavior, we may be better off thinking about coevolved genetic predispositions that go in contradictory directions or, more specifically, about the empirically identifiable universal or widespread ambivalences these are likely to generate than about monolithic stereotypes such as "warlike" versus "peaceful" (see Boehm 1989). Given that so many locally autonomous small-scale societies exhibit egalitarian behavior, it might be useful to try an "ambivalence approach" here as well.
    ... In small-scale societies that exhibit very limited hierarchy, potential victims deal with their ambivalence by setting aside their individual tendencies to submit and forming a coalition to control their more assertive peers. As a result, prudent (and sometimes equally ambivalent) leaders set aside their own tendencies to dominate and submit to their groups even as they lead them. I have said that the social result of this interaction is a consensus-oriented community, a group that cooperates well and that remains small because in the absence of strong leadership it so readily subdivides. Its small size in tum tends to keep major factions from forming and stabilizing. The resulting unity of purpose makes it possible for all or most members of local communities to unite against leaders and, by threat of disapproval or active sanctioning, circumscribe their role. These would seem to be the personal and social dynamics that keep a typical egalitarian society in place. One aspect of these dynamics is an egalitarian ethos, both a cause and an effect of the ambivalences just discussed.
    ... In stronger chiefdoms or kingdoms a not too dissimilar underlying ambivalence may exist, but it is accompanied by a very different ethos that legitimizes ranking or class distinctions among the main political actors, substantial exercise of legitimate authority by leaders, and sometimes even physical coercion. These changes are accompanied by a decidedly submissive behavioral standard for the rank and file, which no longer assertively defines itself as "equal," and the emergence of strong leaders who properly look to their own special interests as well as to group interests.
    ... What is distinctive about egalitarian humans is that the rank and file manages to retain the upper hand. The overall approach to solving common problems in these groups is consensual (see Service 1975), and this approach is applied very effectively to the internal political sphere by use of moralistically based sanctioning. Perhaps a key feature in explaining egalitarian behavior is that one person's attempt to dominate another is perceived as a common problem.
    ... I have suggested that "egalitarian society" needs to be reconceptualized in terms of some universal causal factor and have proposed a specific behavioral explanation in terms of reverse dominance hierarchies: the main political actors idealistically define themselves as peers, and on a practical basis they make certain that their basic parity is not too seriously damaged by individual domination. This viewpoint takes human intention to be a powerful independent variable, one that interacts, obviously, with important constraints of social scale, social organization, and natural and political ecology.
    Granting the serious limitations of reliable data, simple foragers, complex hunter-gatherers, people living in tribal segmentary systems, and people living in what I have called incipient chiefdoms would appear to exhibit a strong set of egalitarian values that express an active distaste for too much hierarchy and actively take steps to avoid being seriously dominated. In a sense, these societies may be considered to be intentional communities, groups of people that make up their minds about the amount of hierarchy they wish to live with and then see to it that the program is followed. So long as all of the main political actors continue to define themselves as peers and are able to make this definition stick, a reverse dominance hierarchy is maintained even though certain features of hierarchy may be present. When authority becomes strong and intergenerationally transmitted and when classification of people into hierarchical categories takes on serious meaning for their lives, the transition from reverse dominance hierarchy to orthodox dominance hierarchy is complete, even though limits to domination are still recognized and enforced.
    ... I have suggested that smallness of scale may be a predictable side effect of egalitarian behavior because such behavior keeps groups subdividing, while small, intensively cooperative groups remain able to unite effectively and control their leaders. In short, there could be an important functional symbiosis here that might be useful in helping to explain why human groups seem to have remained minuscule for so many millennia.

    The idea seems to be that dominance is genetic, and whether that dominance is hierarchical or reverse is modal.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Do you think this has much influence on them? I mean, if this hypocrisy was pointed out, do you imagine it would make them uncomfortable enough to want to change, or is our capacity to invent new narratives too slippery to catch that way?Isaac

    Yes, discomfort is the problem, and I recognise that in myself too. I think hypocritical values and a history of guilt are a heady mix. But people calm down eventually.

    I only have the paper citation, but have you read Sapolsky's research on baboons (Sapolsky RM, Share LJ (2004) A pacific culture among wild baboons: Its emergence and transmission)? It's quite revealing about the role of culture even in animals like baboons in maintaining social systems.Isaac

    I thought I had when I saw the title, but reading it now, I don't think I have. It's an interesting mixture of factors: large catastrophic event, leading to a shortage of males; changes in sexual selection (focus on competition with similar-ranking members); changes in environment that lead to physiological changes in the group members (e.g. the stress reduction in unattacked low-ranking members)... and then of course the resultant effects on social behaviour that the young learn from. I liked this in particular:

    For example, juvenile rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta) housed with stumptail macaques (M. artoides) assume the latter's more conciliatory style (de Waal and Johanowicz 1993). — Sapolski

    They say people become like their dogs! :rofl: One of the interesting points:

    A number of investigators have emphasized how a tolerant and gregarious social setting facilitates social transmission (e.g., van Schaik et al. 1999), exactly the conditions in F93–96. — Sapolski

    which suggests, looking back the other way, a conservativism of socialisation in intolerant, unequal, or stressful environments, which I think describes humans pretty well too. (Stress, depression, and anxiety lead to anti- or asocial behaviour, self-centredness.)

    While it is obvious why low-ranking baboons had an easier time of it, one thing I haven't really gotten my head around yet is why the loss of all of the most aggressive males led to increased aggression between similar-ranking males. One would have thought that, if anything, the high female-to-male ratio would make competition between males rather slight.

    One thing to bear in mind is that we carry with us much of the genetics of our ancestors, and when we see a social group at a given time, we are seeing how individuals behave in that specific environment, including that group's reigning socialisation. What the above shows is how quickly group members change when the environment and the socialisation suffer catastrophe. Behavioural characteristics that were not very important in one generation might become dominant in the next, or the next but one.

    It seems to me that social groups have two systems for creation and maintenance of behavioural norms. One is active, the other passive. The active one is about influencial members trying to stand out, the passive one is like a game of Chinese whispers, each member simply trying to copy the other (to reinforce group identity) but making small errors in doing so.Isaac

    In hunter-gatherer groups, reverse domination acted specifically to stop an individual standing out and becoming dominant. This was one of the means by which social groups ensured egalitarianism. It seems more likely that individuals were able to become influential once homogeneous socialisation was weakened by having larger, more intermingling groups. That said, plenty of other primate species have alpha males, and we have relatively recent common ancestors with them. I wonder if we evolved a distrust of alphas, perhaps the origin of lampooning :)

    The Chinese whispers thing is very true though, and the indoctrination of children into religions for their supposed benefit is always the example I think of, since it is essentially the banana-ladder experiment but real. More positively, I'm not sure if I brought it up here or elsewhere but Dennett's summary of various anthropologists looking at the origins and developments of culture are along these lines, which is why I think that memetics is the best descriptive tool for that sort of thing. (Dennett's memetic description of culture focuses on a fictitious illustration based on real anthropological findings, in which, when an artefact of culture, such as a fishing boat, is shown to be more successful, all of its features are imitated, including ones that had nothing to do with its success. I'll dig out my copy of From Bacteria to Bach and Back for the citations.)
  • Causality, Determination and such stuff.
    Nice commentary, Kid. In 1954 I wrote a short paper on this for my physics class in high school. At the time I loved reading science fiction. Of course, the technical details were beyond me, but my teacher, an elderly lady we all loved was impressed.jgill

    Thanks! Yeah I ended up doing a physics simply because I couldn't get past the mathematics of the physics books I wanted to read. For the love of gawd, someone needs to invent an easier way to do physics than maths! Glad your teacher liked it, she sounds like a cool old lady.
  • Metaphysics Defined
    Really, we're innately biased (as machines, no less) to be causally deterministic? Then how is it that most people hold onto the bias of being endowed with some form and degree of free will?javra

    I didn't say we were biased to be deterministic per se, although Kant would agree, just that we're biased to establish patterns, often when they're not there. As for free will, the incompatibilist argument has never struck me as particularly intelligent, but if you want a more thorough description, see this thread: https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/8130/simple-argument-for-the-soul-from-free-will/p1

    It doesn't answer why one set of innate biases ought to be accepted on face value while another form of communal bias ought not.javra

    Who said anything about "ought"? You've presumably come across optical illusions such as this one below, in which the two labelled squares have the same shade of grey but appear to have different shades of grey.

    1280px-Checker_shadow_illusion.svg.png

    Do you ask the question why you ought to see them as two different shades, beyond an explanation of a) how you see them as two different colours and b) why that process would be useful in most cases, if erroneous in this case? To that extent, you can explain why you "ought" to model the world in a causal way. But nature has use for your oughts. Any biases she gives you, she gives you because it helped your ancestors survive and procreate.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    But having a non-rational altruistic reaction, says nothing about the possibility, or indeed even the validity, of determining a moral action because of it.Mww

    This still presumes there must be an external validation of it, which is erroneous (albeit understandable) in my view because the morality itself derives from biology, history and statistics. The possibility of validation is an illusion arising from being thus biased and not knowing why, in an environment in which that bias cannot logically be satisfied. (By logically, I mean the logic of natural selection, not the logic of the rationalist.)

    If so, we are still left with what to do about it.Mww

    Exactly! Et voila: moral philsophy is born!

    Help others may be a general rule of altruism, understand others may be the general rule of empathy, but both of those do not instantiate the rational prerogatives of the subject who merely understands the rule., but knows not, because of it, how he should act concerning it.Mww

    And this would have been the case too in groups of 20-50 people. Your social drives cannot tell you how to help, they only give you the desire to help, which is rationalised now as 'good'. The 'how' is not a moral problem. It is not qualitatively any different from 'how do I get my kite out of the tree,' itself following from a desire to reunite with one's kite. This is also true in most philosophical rationalisations: "maximise the benefit" does not tell you how to maximise the benefit.

    So this 'how' is not the redundancy. The imperatives were the redundancy. It's worth reiterating that our social drives are no longer fit for our environments for the most part. Figuring out the how has always been an issue, but now the what (different socialisations) and the when and the who (non-feasibility of obeying imperatives) also require rationalisation. Moral philosophy (of the what/who/when kind) is not necessarily redundant now, is rather a symptom of the lack of its own redundancy.

    Still, if harsh and perhaps even unwarranted, it permits the philosopher to say to the psychologist....you’ve taken what I’ve given and made a gawd-awful mess out of it. (Kidding. Nobody really says that. Do they?)Mww

    Yes, I'm saying it. I'm saying the metaphysician has taken what nature has given them and made a gawd-awful mess out of it. The psychologist discovers only what nature has given, incrementally, with limited accuracy and no hope of completeness.

    Given that moral philosophers are biased by their own nature (as we all are) and given that their job (unbeknownst to them) is to rationally reconcile that bias plus their idiosyncrasies with what is actually needed in our contemporaneous environment (no longer the same thing), one might expect the cleverest of them to hit the nail close the head sometimes. Even DK isn't 'truth', just a fairly minimal approximation to it. However given that each of them is now more unique in their thinking and experience than any possible interlocuters 20,000 years ago, one must also expect that they disagree. They can't mostly be consistent science, and none are apt to be consistent with science all of the time.
  • Metaphysics Defined
    One's presumption of causal determinism - just as with one's presumption of physicalism - will be fully metaphysical, rather than empirical.javra

    Not at all. In fact, we are biased the other way. We see patterns in empirical data because we are pattern-recognition machines. We see them erroneously because we are necessarily imperfect pattern-recognition machines. It takes mental effort to dismiss an apparent pattern due to knowledge that seeming regularity has an underlying indeterminism. Don't believe me? Grab a randomer on the street and explain quantum mechanics to them. Chances are they don't even know what metaphysics is.

    How do empirical observations of balls and such determine that our intentions - which always intend, and are driven by, some goal - are in fact not teleological (and this without the use of metaphysical considerations and conclusions)?javra

    The above answers this also.
  • Causality, Determination and such stuff.
    True backward causation introduces true randomness (even if the universe was otherwise deterministic, the moment that information from the future arrives introduces a fork in the timeline, and from the perspective of someone living through that moment it’s random which timeline they “end up in”). So it seems that something that seems to approximate backward causation (ordinary prediction) would in turn introduce something that looks approximately like randomness, i.e. chaos, even if everything was technically strictly deterministic.Pfhorrest

    Actually not quite. In fact, one of my preferred interpretations of QM has precisely this backward causality, along with normal forward causality. The condition that stops what you expect is self-consistency. The question remains then as to what laws of physics guarantee this self-consistency.

    An example is matter-antimatter pair creation and annihilation. A photon excites the electron field temporarily, leading to an electron and positron being created which then attract one another and annihilate. If the photon is energetic enough, the electron and positron can be created with sufficient kinetic energy that they escape one another's attraction and become 'real'. But there is a charge-parity-time symmetry in the universe that is obeyed in this phenomenon: a spin-down positron is just a spin-up electron moving backwards in time. (This is true of all antimatter.) Taking the electron's PoV where energy is insufficient to become real, it is excited from the vacuum, then spontaneously emits a photon of twice its own energy and reverses direction in time to conserve energy. It then does it again to change direction to our normal forward direction in time, and it follows this causal loop for an infinite number of iterations. From the outside, a pair is created then annihilated, and that's that.

    The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics interprets the complex conjugate of the wavefunction to be a wavefunction going backwards in time. (Which is not unreasonable: the wavefunction has an exponent proportional to i*t -- the imaginary number multiplied by time. Taking the complex conjugate [i*t --> (-i)*t] and reversing the direction of time the wave travels through [i*t --> i*(-t)] are mathematically identical, and therefore equally valid.)

    Self-consistency is easier to arrive at in this case because the wavefunction itself is not measurable, but the probability density (via the Born rule) is. A photon being emitted from an atom, for instance, will deterministically spread outwards in all or many directions at once. Where that wavefunction encounters other atoms that can absorb it, those atoms emit photons whose wavefunctions move backwards in time (photons are their own antiparticles: a backwards emission is identically an absorption). The only "cause" consistent with the "effect" is the original atom that emitted the forwards photon. This self-consistency is maintained by the requirement that real phenomena have wavefunctions that are not orthogonal to each other. It is the same process of elimination that stops the cat being in a state of dead when radioactive decay has not occurred.

    In principle, this back-and-forth could evolve over an infinite number of iterations, with certain paths initially tried by the original photon ironed out (sum over histories) until we're left with a single set of trajectories with the same cause and the same effect(s). Not knowing the future, we can only consider the forward propagation and cannot explain the decisiveness of the effect (the measurement problem).

    If you mean macroscopically, like the grandfather paradox, I would suggest that the above, if true, would be subject to the same classical limit as all quantum effects. A person is, while technically a wave, not wave-like, period being inversely proportional to mass. Any back and forth jiggery-poker would have to occur at insanely, maybe impossibly small timescales.
  • Metaphysics Defined
    How is the very nature of causation a topic that is in the purview of the empirical sciences—rather than in that of the philosophical branch termed metaphysics?

    To me this is a Hume 101 question. Succinctly explained, a cause is not a percept—and so cannot be empirical (as empiricism is understood in modernity).
    javra

    So science cannot avoid metaphysics... according to metaphysics. I can quite easily drop balls ninety-nine times and predict that on the hundredth time the ball will fall to the floor. You can insist that, in making such a prediction, I am relying on metaphysics, e.g. assuming determinism. I respond that, on the contrary, metaphysical explanations and justifications for determinism instead rely on the empirical fact that the balls fell to the floor ninety-nine times.

    In which case I have ninety-nine problems, but metaphysics is not one.
  • Donald Trump (All General Trump Conversations Here)
    Love the film, but I don't find that it expresses or advocates any real political theme.Maw

    I meant the main character's political philosophy, not the film's.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Are you implying that there are no longer any social groups, or that individuals belong to too many social groups such that those groups no longer matter?Luke

    There are no longer single, small, homogeneous social groups for which our social drives were developed. We have a different kind of environment now. The idea of a social group persists in a more malleable way: the nuclear family, work colleagues, friends, social network, my church (I don't have one) or other community. Less so these days, we have communities centred around neighbourhoods. This is no longer one social group but many 'virtual' groups. We no longer inhabit them immediately and unavoidably, but dependently.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Many social workers, for example, are cruel to their own children on their return from work - stressed out by a hard day 'altruistically' helping others, they lash out at their own families when they get home. What would explain this phenomena if these people just happened to be more in touch with their empathy than others? I think a better explanation is that they've joined a social group whose norms are the helping of others, but when at home they follow the very family-management norms they've just spent the whole day observing.
    ...
    We wear different masks for different social roles.. there's nothing wrong with that, until one of the masks seems to so wildly contradicts another that we feel there's no possible unifying narrative.
    Isaac

    I think this is an interesting example because, as noted in e.g. Paul Bloom's Against Empathy, which argues for rational compassion, we are supposed to be biased to extend empathy more to those who are biologically close to us. (I also disagree with Paul Bloom's conclusion, and find that he makes the error of mistaking outcomes with capacities.)

    I had this sort of thing in mind when I mentioned my nationalistic, anti-immigration friend-of-a-friend to, I think, Pfhorrest. A social worker who is abusing their child is a hypocrite. They have, as you say, one virtual social group (the nuclear family) in which one set of moral values is championed, and another (the industry they work in) in which a different and contrary set of values is championed. The person cannot rationally argue for one and the other: they might, for instance, work against another person abusing their child.

    With a few notable exceptions, inequality (not meeting the needs of your fellow) is unheard of in nomadic hunter-gather tribes, but as soon as there is settlement (the ability to store surplus) we start to see the emergence of it.Isaac

    Yes, to my knowledge, surplus is really only an issue after the neolithic revolution, in which roles must be assigned (social stratification: we can't all be farmers in an agricultural society) and which can't be supported by small social groups, so we're already moving from an environment in which our social genes are fit to one in which they are not.

    Given how common social stratification is in other primate species, even just considering the usual alpha-omega structures, it seems reasonable that a bias toward social stratification could be selected for, which would require some rewording of the OP wherein morality and sociality are pretty much synonymous. But maybe not. As far as I can tell, there's no consensus that we are genetically driven toward social stratification in the literature, unlike, say, bees. Which begs the questions: why does social stratification arise?, and why does it not arise in human hunter-gatherer groups?

    A stratifying bias (which may be nothing more than in-group bias + emergent specialisation) might be subdued in small groups by socialisation, e.g. in reverse dominance (https://www.psychologytoday.com/gb/blog/freedom-learn/201105/how-hunter-gatherers-maintained-their-egalitarian-ways) but then one would expect the majority of hunter-gatherer tribes to still be bent toward stratification. Perhaps humans are just different to many other primates in that respect.

    As I believe you've mentioned, most rationalisation is post hoc, we try to understand the behaviours we're inclined to do (and the objectives and affects we're inclined to feel) in terms of a narrative which attempts to unify what are, in reality, a completely disparate set of urges/feelings. I think persuasion has to be more subtle than philosophical debate ever is. It has to present an attractive alternative narrative, one which makes the undesirable behaviour stand out as incoherent. Then there's a concomitant need to present an alternative set of social norms (as behaviours, not theories) for people to feel comfortable with, and a social group whose identity is dictated by those behaviours. Only all three aspects will work, I think. Narrative, social norms, available social group identified by those norms.Isaac

    Yes. The sort of thing I had in mind were the philosophies of the French revolution, which appear to have focused social unrest arising from systemic corruption and inequality, exacerbated by the failing agricultural system and bad financial management by a minority of wealthy, powerful people who did not share in the suffering of consequences. My feeling is that individual reactions to the situation under traditional monarchistic-nationalistic socialisations that could no longer subdue both selfish and selfless responses cannot have been uniformly rational of the form: This is bad because it is against liberty, or This is bad because it is inequality. Those moral philosophies, themselves influenced by human social drives, appealed to the outraged masses who were both victims (selfish) and witnesses (selfless) of a society collapsing under a condition of antisociality. Any vestiges of the prior reigning socialistion -- you cannot kill a King -- fell to this more appealing one.

    Contrast that with the recent global economic crisis, again caused by a failing industry and the mismanagement of the economy by a powerful, wealthy minority who did not generally share in the consequences of their failures (the odd suicide notwithstanding). Our response was similar, and yet much more muted because it was, on the whole, abstract. I personally suffered very little from the economic crisis. I continued to be paid, have good job security, I never went hungry, and the misfortune I saw was largely limited to the closing down of a few nice shops and bars. I did have a sense of injustice, but it was more a) in line with existing social mores and b) quite abstract and less empathetically stimulating. One can perhaps imagine how much injustice and inequality people under a very different socialisation will suffer, and did suffer in France, before they go nuts.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Asking that question presumes you known what is or isn’t moral, which is exactly the question at hand. Can we know that? If so, how? What does that even mean?Pfhorrest

    This is still predicated on the assumption of a top-down moral objectivity. The question is meaningless in a bottom-up naturalistic description. What is moral is what my social drives make me feel is moral. If I hurt someone, I feel emotional empathy: I feel pain. That is 'bad'. If I do good for someone, I do so with a hit of oxytocin which feels nice. That is 'good'. If I do something that I know is perceived antisocial, for instance refuse to torture a prisoner in Abu Ghraib, I feel anxiety. That is 'bad', but is it as 'bad' as harming others? If I do something that I know is perceived social, such as share 'My thoughts and prayers with the victims of whatever' on social media, I feel included. That is 'good', but is it as good as not posting BS and doing something?

    So far as I understand, what you're asking is: by what external measure do we affirm that these are good or bad, better or worse? And this completely misses the point. Our rational conceptions are a) overwhelmingly advised by our feelings, i.e. not that rational, and b) beyond that based almost entirely on ignorance and invention. You and I seem to have almost identical moral values but cannot, so far as I can see, agree on a single aspect of how those values are obtained. It is simpler to assume that our differences boil down to idiosyncratic rationalisations and what we have in common -- our values -- have an underlying bias.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    I think you've got a really good area for examination here.

    But, for example, when an ex-girlfriend long ago complained to me that someone she saw at work told her to smile, from that description alone I didn't understand why that was bad. I imagined myself being at work and someone telling me to smile, and I imagined that I would take it as a friendly gesture, someone trying to help cheer me up.Pfhorrest

    I'm not going to treat your experiences head-on as they are yours, rather I'll look for something similar in my own experience and see if there's common ground. I recall how sceptical I was of the cat-calling/car-slowing/horn-tooting problem that women face here on an hourly basis because I just didn't see it, and it that case magnitude is a factor. Of course, I did see it, I just didn't consciously see it, i.e. I didn't notice it. The brain is very good at hiding from itself what it sees as normal. Once my consciousness had been raised, I started to see it everywhere. And I was angry as hell, partly at myself of course, but mostly at the white-van--driving douchebags who hassle women. That anger arises without reasonable consideration: it is an automatic reaction that I did not have until I had had an empathetic response to victims of douchebaggery.

    I think this is likely typical, and gives a rough sketch of what actually happens when we acquire new empathetic responses. While the trigger for 're-programming' myself came from consciousness, the mechanism of wiring in that automated response to stimuli is unconscious. The action of the reason is to see harm which was not previously detected; it does not redefine my notion of 'good', rather it refines the way my brain detects external harm. Does that sound similar to you?

    Your discussion here gives a good solid account of why we have a lot of "ought" intuitions, why we evolved to be eager to accept that certain things are good or certain things are bad, and so to easily agree with at least some other people when they claim that something is good or bad. But that evolutionary account doesn't establish that or why those things are good or bad, just the cause of us often thinking so.Pfhorrest

    Agreed. Like with any other theory of morality, you cannot justify a particular notion of 'good' or 'bad' with regards to good-for-survival, especially an outdated good-for-survival. Often, the resolution to this is just to subscribe to a position. Here, we need not necessarily do that. By understanding the real processes taking place (and that have taken place in the past), the relationship between those processes and the benefit to social groups, and the relationships between sociality and our conceptions of morality, I believe we can see what those conceptions are analogues of. You give the conceptions primacy, I feel. I give the biology primacy, and see no reason why rational minds that have woefully incomplete knowledge of their own operations and origins ought to have their conceptions of morality taken more seriously.

    And despite that frequent agreement in the contexts where such agreement was evolutionarily advantageous, we also have frequent disagreements, especially now (the evolutionary "now", past 6-12Ka) that we live lives so different from the ancestral environment.Pfhorrest

    Yes, understandably, since we are surrounded by people who are unlikely to (have the opportunity to) reciprocate and have very different moral frames of reference to us. Part of my thesis is that such disagreements would not have been frequent or rationally debated (even with oneself) within socially homogeneous hunter-gatherer groups.

    Moral objectivism is only the claim that those disagreements can be rationally (small-r, not big) resolved: we can talk about why (as in reasons, not causes) one person or group thinks something is good or bad and another thinks otherwise, and work out some kind of unbiased conclusion.Pfhorrest

    Moral objectivism to my understanding is the claim that what is right or wrong doesn't depend on what people think is right or wrong. It is the assumption that there is a (potentially inaccessible) correct answer to a particular problem that is independent of the moral frames of reference of the people affected by that particular problem. Getting the views of the people affected would be redundant to the objective moral value, but it is the only pragmatic way of resolving the issue when an objective moral, should it exist, is unknown to all involved.

    As we've discussed before, the assumption of an objective reality in science is predicated on it being the best explanation for the seeming objective reality that allows for predictive modelling. Beyond that, it would be an arbitrary belief. Moral objectivity has no such feature since we cannot test the values of objective morals, only of individuals. There does not seem to be an objective morality in practise, that is: no process is consistent with only its existence. Any approach -- which is any pragmatic approach -- that factors in the moral values of the individuals involved in a particular conflict is, as far as I can see, relativistic. Ultimately whoever has the power to resolve the conflict is taking on board the evidence of others but making a judgement from their (hopefully now evolved) frame of reference. There is no non-subjective mechanics involved. Since objectivity does not enter into the mechanics, it does not strike me as useful or realistic.

    That is the moral objectivity I argue against, and the reason why I think the realistic description is (heavily biased) moral relativism. There is an extent at least to which your conception of moral objectivity coincides with the above, insofar as you have previously stated that, if a conflict arises, at least one party must be in error. To the extent that your conception of moral objectivity allows for negotiation, mediation, understanding the other's point of view, and relies on some subjective mind making a decision or failing to, and with no reason to believe by the end of it that they have an objectively correct answer, it appears consistent with my conception of natural moral relativism. Perhaps it would be easiest to consider cases where moral relativism is clearly not in play.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    The irrational insistence comes from neglecting the difference between costs a dollar and costs a dollar more. Such error follows from a cognitive neglect, the causality for which is merely a language game.Mww

    Yes, this was a mere accident. An unusable data point. For the record, I also said 10 cents. Most do.

    Redundant compared to....what?Mww

    It would be redundant in the same way that a verbal rule: "You should see with your eyes" would be redundant. We're all already doing that. Likewise defining a 'good' to be e.g. 'help those in need according to your means' would be likewise pointless since people already had a physiological, i.e. non-rational altruistic reaction to people in need.

    And what is a moral truth? Morality is a rational enterprise, sure, but mere rationalization doesn’t necessarily give truth. If morality is qualified by its good, truth could only apply if and when a moral disposition is truly good, which is a blatant redundancy, for there is no such thing as a good that isn’t good truly.Mww

    :up:

    But it certainly can’t be the case that genes are responsible for that redundancy.Mww

    Now? Sure, now it's a different redundancy, because we do have moral drives and we don't have a fit environment to use them in. We use our rationality to make up the difference (not necessary or meaningful in small, isolated, homogeneous groups). Rationally, we are ignorant and find nothing rational to justify a moral axiom, or rather find lots of things that fail to. I believe that, if, with a snap of a finger, we returned to hunter-gatherer environments tomorrow, in a few generations we would once again have no need to define 'good'. We would return to simply reasoning which of our desires -- selfish or selfless -- we were going to prioritise in a given situation, and how.

    it is still much more parsimonious to suggest, and indeed much more evident, that we are moral beings, than it is to suggest nothing we do matters.Mww

    It is also much more pragmatic. We immediately exist in a society. The cosmos is the stuff of documentaries and books, and lacks that immediacy. It's a valid frame of reference, but a poor choice nonetheless.

    As regards this inconsistent amnesiac, here we see why psychology branched from philosophy. The latter makes no room for dysfunctional impairment, while the former requires it. My philosophy tells me how I think, your psychology wants to tell me how wrong I am. Yours tries to warn me of pending mistakes, mine doesn’t warn me at all, but forces me change my thinking because of them. Difference being, of course, while. neither warnings nor experiences are always heeded, experience always carries the much more severe penalties and, even more importantly, carries the higher likelihood for change.Mww

    And knowing about it doesn't change much anyway, except in edge cases. I am as in error now when my rational mind verifies an inappropriate pattern-recognition result to an algorithmic problem as I was when I was ten, maybe a bit more mindful of it from time to time. I would bear it in mind, for instance, when writing exam questions. But I think philosophy is the kind of place where this sort of thing genuinely is useful. Philosophy is vested in rationalism. It would be good to have as many facts as possible, if only to identify which ideas are not useful to consider.

    If we could only come to terms on how that relates to morality, we’d be off to the rodeo.Mww

    That's the biggie. I don't think I've argued sufficiently well for this. My feeling is that OP has created confusion as to what I'm saying. I will sleep on it. N'night!

    Oh btw did you have some references in mind? You mentioned some in the message you deleted.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    We’re never taking a description of an experience that someone had and reaching a prescriptive conclusion from it, and so not violating the is-ought gap.Pfhorrest

    I think this is quite untrue. We don't even need someone else's conclusions to have our own moral reactions. We are prone to empathise even with fictional characters in fictional circumstances. It is precisely the descriptions we react to in both real and hypothetical situations, allowing us to draw our own conclusions by rationalising our own reactions. One of the recurring features of the Abu Ghraib investigations was that soldiers were taking part in abuses against their own moral judgement. They knew it was wrong, i.e. they did not accept the conclusions of the persons with previous experience and reached their own, but perpetuated the problem out of fear of leaving themselves vulnerable.

    Putting experience aside, prescriptive conclusions are inculcated from others' conclusions in abstract ways, by pedagogy, rhetoric, etc. But it is not generally possible to describe Othello dispassionately and just tack on 'Wasn't Iago a hero?' to seed an anti--mixed-marriage moral. People are naturally equipped to see what is good (social) and bad (antisocial), and learn from their own reactions, even if the describer drew the opposite conclusion.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Hi Isaac.

    The relatively wealthy walk straight past the homeless (when Sitting Bull toured with the rodeo for a time he apparently gave away his wages to the destitute in the cities - it's not that he was more saintly than the rest, just that he'd not been inculcated into ignoring them).Isaac

    Even saintly people must walk past the homeless. It is unfeasible to try to help everyone -- that's precisely the problem with having an outdated social biology -- and so one must choose who to walk by. And then you have empathy fatigue, wherein a person knows they can help, but just struggles to care any more. And then, yes, you have the normalisation of homelessness as a condition, and people who, normalised or not, just couldn't give a flying one.

    Lots of people do dedicate their time, effort and money to helping the homeless too. While we cannot rely on the altruism of everyone, we can currently rely on sufficient altruism, and that's a factor too: not so much not my problem as someone else has got this. I think your concern is that an idea can grab enough people to make this proportion insufficient?

    Whether someone is one of those that cannot help everyone, or that get empathy fatigue, or that never help, I think they mostly feel guilt arising from their empathy. (People explicitly point to this in the case of the homeless, and in the case of TV commercials for charities: "Without your five dollars, this cute but patently diseased and malnourished orphan will die!"... "They make us feel so guilty!!!") Individualism, to me, is best summed up as an ideology designed to console and, eventually, subdue guilt (by stimulating counter-empathetic responses, for instance) arising from systematic antisocial attitudes toward people outside of our virtual social groups. I think it serves much the same purpose as racist ideology serves to console and subdue guilt arising from one's instincts for dealing with out-groups. It is an antisocial philosophy endorsed by a powerful antisocial minority and subscribed to by otherwise perfectly social people grateful for an appeal to their pre-social instincts.

    So I think it's perfectly reasonable, if one is fit to be part of society unbegrudgingly, to fight against this, to not tolerate the antisocial elements that sell individualism, to raise the consciousness of those who normalise or don't question the need for the vulnerable classes, and to do that one obviously can't just rely on the better angels of our nature, durable though they are, and must construct counter-individualistic, pro-altruistic memes to combat antisocial ones. In other words, with an already existing idea of 'good' based on naturally-selected for social drives, moral philosophy is a somewhat important pragmatic tool (e.g. as an idea to rally people around and a tool for debating). Metaphysics, on the other hand, weakens that fight by making 'good' as easy to undermine as anything we might consider 'bad', such as the doctrine of individualism.

    Hunter-gatherer communities are notoriously lax with their children, letting them do almost anything. The one exception in most cases is that sharing is enforced. One of the ways egalitarianism is maintained is that non-egalitarian behaviours are simply never seen, and so can't be normalised, and so resist rationalising belief formation, and so are forcibly admonished, and so are never seen...Isaac

    Yes, exactly this. You do see it in social animals in natural history documentaries: one individual breaks the rules and gets a beating/exiled/killed. Some monkeys are particularly scary at this, for instance. So that's one reason it will be rare. The other, as you say, is the homogeneity of egalitarian behaviour in social groups: that's what children learn from, and we don't have that anymore. We're in a memetic competition, and not all of our better angels are winning. It's quite telling that things like individualism and animal rights can be simultaneously successful ideas, often in the same individuals. "F*** everyone else. Except dolphins, dolphins are cool."

    Interestingly, slavery used to be non-racist. Slaves were taken from defeated territories, from those in debt, or just random enemies. It wasn't until Christianity made the subjugation of one's enemies less noble that a new justification was needed and so sub-human races were invented. The behaviour persisted because it was seen and copied, all that was need was a new post hoc justification to match other beliefs (formed from other behaviours elsewhere).Isaac

    Good point. I guess I made an unconscious distinction between the enslavement of individuals (opportunistic slavery) and that of e.g. races (systematic slavery). My thinking could only really apply to the latter.

    We'd rather include as many people as don't present a threat. The trouble is twofold 1) we are surrounded by non-compassionate behaviours which create belief systems to justify it, and 2) there are people whose objectives are advanced by leveraging those belief systems toward some particular group.Isaac

    Exactly my thinking. I don't think it's 100% clean-cut us-v-them. 'They' are appealing to instincts, some of which will also have been developed in social groups (out-grouping, even social stratification), that exist within us. And I think even left to our own devices, we would still probably be negligent about a dominating culture such that consciousness-raising would still be required. After all, these are not natural circumstances to find ourselves in, i.e. nature could not have selected for skills to deal with it. But yes, in terms of behaviour toward individuals, I think our altruism would dominate.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    Eudaimonism (very primatively) says: if well-being (optimal capabilities/readiness for moral conduct), then habitualize virtues by (a) exercising them and (b) avoiding/abstaining from exercising vices; the "ought" prescribes a moral agent's readiness and not which preferences / rules / actions are or are not applicable to any given (or hypothetical) situation. In other words, what's 'hypothetical' for eudaimonists is derived from the conditional goal and not how to resolve the situational dilemma/tradeoff.180 Proof

    I like this wording of it a lot. "Readiness" is a good way of thinking about a moral position because it might be "I have a pre-prepared rational answer" or just an instinct.

    True. But nothing entails such "divorcement". In fact, eusociality requires convergence - complementarity - of self & group more often than not (as you point out vis-à-vis "antisocial behavior").180 Proof

    And yet it is nonetheless divorced. Helping a stranger today would generally lower my chances of my genome's survival, not increase it, were it not for the fact that a) I'm not likely to die from losing the competition for resources anymore (thanks welfare!), and b) we already think altruism is good from back before the divorce, so not being a selfish a-hole is a good in itself now (e.g. may be more attractive to members of the opposite sex).

    "Relativism" is too arbitrary, or reactive, to be as reliable as a morality needs to be for efficacy over many circumstances and thereby for mimetic success (e.g. cultural transmission).180 Proof

    This is, I'm guessing, based on relativism's arrival in philosophy, thus judging it on its memetic fitness within the context of other memes. But I'm not suggesting relativism needs to be argued for at all. We're more than aware that moral absolutism, such as that which is supposed to derive from an intelligent creator, is the King of Memes. It's still BS, though, and you can intelligently, using evidence-based methodology and, yes, rationalism, dismiss the meme as simply unjustified, however attractive it is. What I'm saying by "relativity is the default" is that we can just keep going until all we're left with is what nature gave us and the environment we find ourselves in: a drive to be altruistic, and no basis to choose who, when and how, i.e. freedom. It's less a derivation than a process of elimination.

    The "naturalistic default" - my metaethical naturalism is kicking-in - implied by this mismatch of drives & environment is pluralism, or logical space to game-out heuristically many different approaches to managing this drives-environments mismatch and ranking them by their utility ranging over variably many circumstances over time; there are [some number] X ways in [some number] Y situations with [some range] Z reliabilities, and ethics - moral philosophy - reflects / speculates on the plurality of these paths rationally [inventories the universe tools] and selects the most optimal path pragmatically [assembles a toolbox for eusocially sharing a commons of scarce goods, services, opportunities].180 Proof

    Selects on what basis? A purely pragmatic optimal will be the easiest thing to do. We must have a desire to satisfy in order for an outcome to be the best. Also, you are characterising moral philosophy here, not individuals generally, right? I don't think people spend their time generating hypothetical scenarios in order to prepare themselves for the real world; rather, they are informed as to the pragmatic option (or multiple options) for the future chiefly by experience of successes and failures in the past. It is mostly reactive rather than proactive, beyond whatever values are instilled in us by authority. We can and do sometimes rationalise about moral correctness in hypothetical situations, but we cannot derive the morally good outcome, only the morally best outcome(s) by a pre-existing notion of good (feel free to hit me with a counter-example).

    There is, to my mind, no such thing as a "natural justification" that is not a naturalistic fallacy (and thereby an ideology).180 Proof

    Except, as I've said often, I am not proposing justifying a moral ideology on natural grounds. It is not that I am justifying relativism by appealing to nature. The effort is purely descriptive, and starts from nature, not relativism. I do justify social behaviour, not as an objective good, but as a classification issue: we humans are social animals; to be antisocial is to be subhuman. One can still be so if one wishes.

    I'm afraid, KK, collapsing the is-ought distinction has left "Natural Selection" to fill your "existentialist void" (i.e. scientism-of-the-gaps).180 Proof

    Quite the opposite. The lack of an objective ought, not a justification of it, is precisely my point. Also, I start from natural selection, and proceed from there.

    Maybe the notion of "group" is too top-down and can be reconceived as bottom-up community (ecosystem).180 Proof

    Good-for-the-group in this context is any genetic feature selected for on the basis that good-for-group behaviour is good-for-me. It can only be re-rationalised as top-down; it cannot naturally be so, just from the mechanics of it.

    How do you account for, or understand, the salience of Hillel the Elder's "That which is hateful to you, do not do to your fellow"?180 Proof

    I covered this in the OP. First, one cannot oblige nature to verify moral philosophy; one can only ask why we are moral (as I'm trying to explain to Pfhorrest). Second, in this case, the golden rule is a rationalisation of something we already did without the need for moral philosophy or rational moral decision-making. In the absence of a competing and contrary philosophy, one may as well say, "Use thine eyes, not thine ears, for sight." The difference is that the reason we already did this did not apply to the general global population; while empathetic responses were not apparently subdued in the presence of out-group members, oxytocin production was and is subdued by other, counter-empathetic responses.

    So one can contrast Hillel with, say, Hitler (sticking with names of the form Hi*le* for s'n'g), who believed it was absolutely brilliant to do that which was hateful to him to his fellow, if one allowed 'fellow' to include Jews, which he did not. It seems that Hitler prioritised his counter-empathetic (largely pre-social) responses, while Hillel emphasised his social ones.
  • Natural and Existential Morality
    I read the book; it’s at academia dot com from a bing title search. I dumped my write-up commenting on it, being wrong on one count and superfluous on the next.Mww

    Oops! I should have reloaded the page before responding yesterday. Now I'm superfluous! :rofl:

    I didn’t encounter anything in the book that relates to your half of this conversation, hence my commentary on it being superfluous with respect to the OP. Which leaves me to think you just wanted me to be exposed to modernization. So, thanks.....I guess.Mww

    The bat & ball example was the sort of thing I had in mind. It is not that we get the answer wrong -- most do, and that isn't particularly interesting other than to show that human decisions aren't typically rational decisions. The interesting part is how the rational mind rationalises the irrational answer. People swear blind they thought it through rationally, i.e, worked out the answer mathematically, and yet they clearly didn't. That's what I find fascinating. We are not only irrational, we lie to ourselves about it, without knowing that we're lying to ourselves.

    We do moral things without the need to ask why, but if we do ask, we can only ask ourselves and only ourselves can answer. I grant the intrinsic circularity, always have. Like I said....blame Mother Nature. And if we do ask, is never our altruism or empathy receiving the query; we can ever only ask our reason.Mww

    And our reason swears blind that it worked out the ball cost $0.10. It will swear blind that it worked out altruism is good too (most of the time, not Ayn Rand, obviously). But, as I said to Pfhorrest, there isn't much more redundant than an altruistic animal working out that altruism is right.

    If altruism and empathy were naturally selected predicated on small groups, but we no longer inhabit small groups specifically, did altruism and empathy evolve in keeping with the evolution of group size?Mww

    It's a really interesting question. Humans are still evolving other than in arbitrary (e.g. sexual selection) way, but they tend to evolve quickest in isolated groups still, such as the evolution of genetic mutations to exist at high altitudes as seen in Tibet. Whether a larger social group could evolve traits for surviving in larger social groups depends on how long that group stays roughly that size: if the population expands faster than evolutionary timescales, it seems unlikely.

    Humans have, for 90% of their existence, lived in small groups of hunter-gatherers. The agricultural era of humanity is only about 12,000 years old. However this is long enough (Tibetans evolved to high-altitude existence in the last 3,000 years) if a selection criteria exists that prefers e.g. social stratification over reciprocal altruism (since we can't all be farmers in an agricultural society). As it happens, other primates and ancestral mammals already have such social strata, so there was likely an existing genetic amenability that nature could hijack for the neolithic revolution, which would speed things up. On the other hand, people started dying much less after agriculture (hence our population explosion), which gives nature a much more limited means of selection, which in turn means that evolutionary timescales are prolonged. 12,000 years might not be enough for any meaningful changes to how we organise, although there is evidence that we have evolved in the agricultural era to get better as certain tasks.

    I reject that an individual suddenly becomes moral just because he inhabits something more than a small group. How small is small? Is a hundred people a mall group? There never were 8M people in a large group until relatively recently, so.....seems altogether arbitrary to me.Mww

    Small enough such that a) socialisation is approximately homogeneous, and b) the people one meets on a given day are more likely to be relatives or neighbours. At that point, empathy becomes more accurate (the person you encounter is more likely to respond like you), and altruism becomes sufficiently reciprocal that nature can do something with it. If humans had evolved in sufficiently large social groups that socialisation was diverse and most people you encountered were strangers (e.g. from some large social group of primates), then empathy would not be accurate enough to be selected for and altruism not reciprocal enough to be selected for. I put that in bold because it's a good rewording of my key argument.

    Note, it is not the individual that changes from group size to group size, nor has the quality of the moral hardware altered one iota. If you took moral philosopher from Paris and put him in a hunter-gatherer tribe in Tanzania (I have hunted with one such tribe, but too briefly to anecdotally verify there were no philosophers :rofl: ), he would not change. There are not genes for switching between modes depending on environment (that I know of). There are genes specifically for small social groups that would make rationalisation of moral truths redundant.

    What is the frame of reference that is not violated by hypocrisy?Mww

    The cosmological frame of reference, in which nothing we do matters, would be one in which it is as reasonable to be a hypocrite as to be social.

    Conscious decision making is judgement, in which things are related to each other and a conclusion is drawn. Judgement is a facet of reason, and we make judgements every time things relate to each other.Mww

    Defining judgement as per the first emphasised point, the second is where I differ with empirical justification. Or rather I would not leave this open to the interpretation that our decision-making (conscious or not) is the judgement being made consciously. The way S1 and S2 work together is that S2 consciously verifies the decisions of S1 while believing them to be S2's decisions.

    Imagine a programmer with inconsistent amnesia. Every day he opens his project and there's some work that's been done. The programmer looks through the code and says, 'Yes, this is what I would have done, so I must have done this.' Occasionally he spots a bug and says, 'What was I thinking? This isn't right,' but most of the bugs he misses (as does any programmer: they are terrible at self-reviewing). Then he goes home, and another programmer sits at his desk, working hard not smart, adding to the first programmer's code.

    Rationalism is purely the first programmer's point of view. I'm not saying he doesn't also write code, just that he's mostly just unconsciously taking the credit for another programmer's work, good or bad.

    Moral philosophy is the first programmer coming to work and finding that he (thinks he) had started work on a new class consisting of boolean methods.

    private boolean giveToCharity(final Object situation, final float currentBankBalance, final String charityName) {
    ...
    }
    

    and he's like "What the f*** was I trying to do here?!?" unaware that the second programmer had misunderstood the problem.