Why does Moore say/think it would be said? — Ciceronianus the White
Fair enough.
The thing is, Moore sentences screw with what, to a budding philosopher, might seem like natural answers to the general question, "Why do people say the stuff they do?"
There is, sad to say, a gulf between the fact that
p and someone believing that
p. Thus, even if people always and only said what they sincerely believe, we could not deduce
p from someone asserting it, or from
p that people would assert
p and not assert
~p. So much we all know well enough.
We also all know that from someone asserting
p we cannot conclude that they believe
p. They may be insincere; they may have misspoken; they may not have meant
p by saying what they said, even though we might take them to have meant
p, and there are subcases of this last that are particularly noteworthy, such as irony.
But having gotten to irony, it looks like we've made a mistake.
A: "How was work?"
B: "Just peachy."
B is most likely not asserting that work was just peachy; she is asserting that work was not peachy at all by saying that it was. She is still asserting what she sincerely believes though, right?
A: "That bad, huh?"
B: "No, it was okay. Long stupid meeting this afternoon, that's all."
So B was also exaggerating, and didn't actually believe that the work day had been the opposite of peachy, although that is what she meant by what she said.
We can
mostly infer what someone believes from what they say, and we probably have to, because reasons. We can even do this taking some extra steps between what they said and and what they meant by what they said. (Or "what they meant by saying what they said," if that's better.)
The connection between what someone means and what they believe is clearly not just (logical) implication, as we all know. It looks a lot of the time like what Grice called 'implicature': this is a slightly weaker connection than implication in that the audience is encouraged or expected to make an inference, but not only does the speaker not require their audience to infer their belief, the speaker might actually
block that inference. Implicature is cancelable.
In the example above, we get one of each: in the first exchange, B encourages A to take her to mean work was the opposite of peachy; in the second exchange, B then cancels A's inference that B believes work was the opposite of peachy. And this is all perfectly ordinary. I've put some of Grice's terminology on it, but we all do this stuff everyday, and it seems barely even deserving the word 'theory'.
And it's also wrong. Moore sentences show that clearly, and Grice himself makes this very point. The inference of belief is not cancelable and is not implicature. I attempted a little sleight-of-hand here, which I'm guessing most readers caught: exaggeration is, like irony, a sort of insincerity, whether or not it is intended to deceive. Grice was aware of Moore's paradox. He treats irony as a violation of the maxim of quality*, and the assumption that the speaker believes what they (in the indicative mood) say as just assuming they are following the maxim. (And further, if you make an indicative mood utterance you intend that the audience think you believe what you are saying.)
According to this story, I'm not inferring that you believe
p when you assert
p, but assuming you do. (Leaving aside whatever interpretive hoops we jump through, for the moment.) When I assert
p, I don't intend you to infer that I believe
p, I intend you to believe that I believe it. Just the conclusion without the inference to get you there.
But are we really done with inference? Doesn't it seem like I'm actually reasoning something like this:
IF you assert that
p AND IF you are observing the maxim of quality, THEN you believe that
p.
Or we might put it this way:
IF you assert that
p, THEN EITHER you believe that
p OR you are not observing the maxim of quality.
Sure. But we could rephrase: when you say something either you believe it or you're lying, or exaggerating, or speaking ironically, or any of the other ways of violating the maxim. It's the violations that give rise to implicature, and the default is just non-inferential belief ascription.
I think this should strike most philosophers (of an analytic bent, anyway) as a somewhat bitter pill to swallow, rather like Hume showing you can't justify your reliance on induction. I think we want to say that ascribing beliefs to others based on their indicative mood utterances is rational -- and I believe it is -- but if it is, it is not because we infer what they believe from what they say. I mean to say: it is a question of rationality, within the sphere of reasoning, evidence and so on, not that "the rational thing to do" is believe people are always honest or something. Not the conclusion, but the process.
So if we are to find a place for rationality it's going to be somewhere else, which is a little surprising because the natural hook to hang rationality on would surely have been right around here somewhere, right? Language use, propositional attitudes, belief formation -- this looks like the place.
But we need something more. Since I've more than nodded at Grice, I'd like to be able to give his answer, but I'm not sure we get one. (And I'm no Grice scholar.) The next thing he reaches for should look familiar by now:
I think that this consequence is intuitively acceptable; it is not a natural use of language to describe one who has said that p as having, for example, "implied," "indicated," or "suggested" that he believes that p; the natural thing to say is that he has expressed (or purported to express) the belief that p. He has of course committed himself, in a certain way, to its being the case that he believes that p, and while this commitment is not a case of saying that he believes that p, it is bound up, in a special way, with saying that p.
But this ends up not being much of an account, because all Grice is going to claim is that when you make an indicative mood utterance you intend the audience to think you believe it. That might get us to treating the commitments of indicative mood utterances as the same as belief reports, but nothing more. It's not an account of what those commitments are or of the sense in which the management of such commitments is a rational matter.
(No one take this as any kind of final word on Grice, please, because I think it likely he addresses these issues in stuff I haven't read. If anyone knows, speak up.)
* Try to make your contribution one that is true; do not say what you believe to be false; do not say what you do not have adequate evidence for.