The opening lines of the SEP article on logical pluralism acknowledge that the idea seems crazy at first glance, but that it becomes more plausible on further examination. I found myself getting more of a handle on it when reading the objections to it. It's all pretty technical, and that's not really something I'm super familiar with, but I did get that logical pluralism isn't taking anything away from the regular logic.
If by dissolving all things and having only a single universal process you mean 'reductionism', there is no risk associated with using the view of physicalism, in my opinion.
The notion of validity that comes out of the orthodox account is a strangely perverse one according to which any rule whose conclusion is a logical truth Is valid and, conversely, any rule whose premises contain a contradiction is valid. By a process that does not fall far short of indoctrination most logicians have now had their sensibilities dulled to these glaring anomalies. However, this is possible only because logicians have also forgotten that logic isa normative subject: it is supposed to provide an account of correct reasoning. When seen in this light the full force of these absurdities can be appreciated. Anyone who actually reasoned from an arbitrary premise to, e.g., the infinity of prime numbers, would not last long in an undergraduate mathematics course.
Surely, there's an idea of rationality and proper reasoning in general discourse, e.g. we say that we are rationally warranted to hold some beliefs but not others, that we can jointly hold some beliefs but that holding others jointly would be inconsistent, and so on. To deny this would be one of the most fringe positions one could possibly take on anything. And this idea also includes that of in some sense 'proper' and 'improper' inferences (deliberately avoiding the word valid for now). We are supposed to 'accept' some arguments of the form '{premises}, therefore conclusion', that someone might tell us at work, at the family dinner, in politics, but not others. So there's a notion of some consequence relation between propositions that sometimes holds and sometimes doesn't.
The question then simply is whether there is a logic, including in the specific sense of some formal system, whose consequence relation coincides with that of proper reasoning in ordinary discourse, such that we could for example turn to it and use it to settle the validity of an argument in ordinary discourse, period. If there's exactly one such system that gets the job done, that's monism, if there are multiple that have equal claim to something like that, that's pluralism, and if something like that simply doesn't exist, that's nihilism
First think about the historic development of logic starting with Aristotle, the idea of what logic is supposed to do for us, and the pre-theoretical idea of validity. What is the definition that absolutely every student who takes a course in (formal or informal) logic or critical thinking (or reads a Wikipedia article) learns? Usually, something along the lines of "an argument is valid iff it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion nevertheless to be false". And why did people think this is an important concept? I don't want to talk about Aristotle on my own, so I rely on John Corocan here:
"Every non-repetitive demonstration produces or confirms knowledge of (the truth of) its conclusion for every person who comprehends the demonstration. Persuasion merely produces opinion. Aristotle presented a general truth-and-consequence conception of demonstration meant to apply to all demonstrations. According to him, a demonstration is an extended argumentation that begins with premises known to be truths and involves a chain of reasoning showing by deductively evident steps that its conclusion is a consequence of its premises. In short, a demonstration is a deduction whose premises are known to be true. For Aristotle, starting with premises known to be true and a conclusion not known to be true, the knower demonstrates the conclusion by deducing it from the premises—thereby acquiring knowledge of the conclusion."
The last sentence is probably the most interesting one here: thereby acquiring knowledge of the conclusion. Of course, that's how we typically think about logic, long before we think about verification of program correctness, multi-agent systems, games, and 5 million other use cases for dozens of logics these days.
But on a first view, that makes the idea that there is more than one accurate account of logical consequence and that they are equally correct, somewhat problematic. There's a challenge sometimes referred to as "Priest's challenge" by Read and Restall. Imagine there are two equally correct accounts of logical validity, L and K. We agree/know that a set of premises S is true. According to L, p follows from S, according to K it doesn't. Just like most people, the most popular logical pluralists are not relativists about truth, and K and L here are allegedly accurate accounts of validity, not of truth. Further, they don't deny that the most important objective of any logical system is to describe an account for logical consequence. So is p true or not?
To say "it depends" seems unsatisfying. Firstly, it's not clear what that's supposed to mean. Does the set of premises S guarantee the conclusion in the sense of validity or not? The pre-theoretical idea of validity doesn't appear to be relativistic, and the best-known pluralists aren't relativists about truth. The answer "Yes, p is true. K doesn't say it's not true, it just doesn't confirm that it is so. L confirms it" on the other hand, seems to contradict the claim that K and L are equally good accounts of logical consequence. If L tells us more without being incorrect, then L seems better than K.
Closely related to that is the concern about the normative status of logic. Many logicians and philosophers of logic held that logic is normative - it informs us how we ought to reason. That was certainly part of the intellectual background of the development of logic. A word used for logical principles or axioms by German mathematicians like Frege or Zermelo was "Denkgesetz" - a law of thought. Given the pre-theoretical idea of validity, in combination with conceptualizing logical laws as laws of thought, we shouldn't be surprised that one standard articulation of what it means to be a law of logic was that a principle must hold in complete generality - domain independent. Even pluralists have acknowledged that all of that is in obvious conflict.
So, there's quite a bit of explaining to do for the pluralist, as their conception of logic deviates significantly from how people have historically thought about logic and validity for the last 2300 years, even what it means to be a logic in the first place.
The monist's position, on the other hand, is rather 'standard': It seems to follow more naturally from nothing but the conceptualization of validity and logic. They don't have much explaining to do here. The opposite doesn't really hold, or to a lower degree: Many of the things that seem to be prima facie troubling for the monist, must likewise be answered by the pluralist. For example, maybe we want to ask the monist "There's only one true logic? How would you find out what logic that is, and what does this even mean?" This might be a legitimate question, but it needs to be answered by the pluralist as well. Neither Restall & Beall nor Shapiro hold that literally any possible logic (alphabet, formation rules, deductive apparatus) that we can write on a piece of paper is a 'true logic' in their sense.
"Correct" in that quote basically means appropriate. It has nothing to do with truth.
In order to answer the question about what makes a logic correct one has to address the prior question about what logic is about, i.e., the subject matter of logic. There is one view of logic, according to which a logic is specified by giving a consequence relation for any abstract formal language. There is nothing else to logic. This conception of logic trivializes the debate
Some would argue that logic is about natural language reasoning or vernacular reasoning (e.g., Graham Priest has most clearly articulated this view). If that is the case, then the correct logic is the one that correctly captures/represents the consequence relation in natural language or the consequence relation instantiated by reasoning in the vernacular. If there is no single consequence relation of the relevant sort, then one might be led to pluralism. If there is no consequence relation discoverable in natural language, one might be led to nihilism, etc.
Part of what the monism/pluralism/nihilism debate is about, however, is how to conceive of logic. Arguably, despite what I said above, this debate cannot be conducted entirely independently of the background problem about the correct conception of logic. Some pluralists would deny that logic is only or primarily about the consequence relation in natural language or about vernacular reasoning. Logics should model the consequence relation of any legitimate mathematical theory, leaving room for many "correct logics" which get the job done since there are, arguably, many legitimate mathematical theories (this is Shapiro's view).
This is not the purely abstract conception of logic, according to which logic just means pure logic - logics as models of any possible formal language whatsoever. But it is also not the more traditional view, according to which logic should be applied to vernacular reasoning before one can speak of correct logics, either. I say that the latter is the more traditional view because, arguably, in the history of logic, it was typical to assume that logic is normative for human reasoning and not about modeling any possible language whatsoever, mathematical or other.
There are yet other views, according to which logic should represent the logical structure of the fundamental language which carves nature at its joints (Ted Sider's view). That would be one way to cash out the ontological approach to the "application of logic."
Nihilism states there's no logical laws. Pluralism states there are more than no logical laws, and more than one logical law. Though "law", by the pluralist, is funny here. My thought is that "law" is stipulative -- my suspicion being that all arguments for a logic must beg the question the only way to evaluate a logic is to develop and utilize it in some fashion.
I'm thinking that the monist thinks there is, at the end of the day (ultimately?), only one set of logical laws that cohere together. The pluralist can accept laws insofar that they are limited in a non-lawlike(logical inference rule that fits within the logic) fashion. The nihilist states that all logical so-called laws are matters of preference -- something like a poetry of rhyme, but with ideas.
Surely, there's an idea of rationality and proper reasoning in general discourse, e.g. we say that we are rationally warranted to hold some beliefs but not others, that we can jointly hold some beliefs but that holding others jointly would be inconsistent, and so on. To deny this would be one of the most fringe positions one could possibly take on anything. And this idea also includes that of in some sense 'proper' and 'improper' inferences (deliberately avoiding the word valid for now). We are supposed to 'accept' some arguments of the form '{premises}, therefore conclusion', that someone might tell us at work, at the family dinner, in politics, but not others. So there's a notion of some consequence relation between propositions that sometimes holds and sometimes doesn't.
The question then simply is whether there is a logic, including in the specific sense of some formal system, whose consequence relation coincides with that of proper reasoning in ordinary discourse, such that we could for example turn to it and use it to settle the validity of an argument in ordinary discourse, period. If there's exactly one such system that gets the job done, that's monism, if there are multiple that have equal claim to something like that, that's pluralism, and if something like that simply doesn't exist, that's nihilism
There are two interwining ways to cash out the phrase "correct logic":
Deontologically, as in there being propositions of e.g. the form, "If it is judged that A, and if it is judged that (if A then B), then it ought to be judged that B." Now, it would not be that there was only one correct logic in the sense of there being only one strictly commanded rule or pattern of inference, but we would claim that only one system of patterns of inference featured such "oughts," and either no other system featured "oughts" but at best only "mays" (you may infer this from that...) or the other systems would in some sense be forbidden.
Ontologically, as in thinking that objective/external reality is itself structured like a complex interlocking set of propositions, which proposition-like entities we usually call by the name of facts. Then some one completely correct logic would be one consisting in all and only inference rules reflected from the interrelations between possible facts.
Deontologically, pluralism is best understood as what we might call "permissivism," i.e. any acknowledged system of logic is permissible. (A pluralist doesn't actually have to acknowledge every system that the word "logic" is applied to, though they are less and less a pluralist, the more and more they limit the range of their acknowledgements.) This is subtly, but genuinely, distinct from logical relativism, which would be that different systems "ought" to be applied to different topics.
Ontologically, the pluralist is going to be the one who thinks that objective/external reality is chaotic or random enough to support all sorts of anomalies and fluxes with respect to the relations between its constituent facts. (Logical nihilism, or rather logical asemanticism, seems more accurate in this context, though, if it is not accurate to think that reality is structured according to any completely specifiable system of logic at all. Or maybe there are a few rules that are universal as such, i.e. exactly those pertaining to universal quantification, if this be doable in an unrestricted way.)
there is more than one sense in which arguments may be deductively valid, that these senses are equally good, and equally deserving of the name deductive validity”.
You can reject the metaphysical axioms I've stated: I haven't claimed they are logically necessary. But I do think they are a better explanation than the alternatives, and I think I've shown that. We can discuss that further, once you accept the coherence of the framework I've stated.
Just to be clear, for other folk, Tim's question is loaded precisely becasue the notion that there is a "correct logic" for which a definition might be provided is exactly what is denied by both logical pluralism and nihilism.
You will not, for example, find a definition of "Correct Logic" in the Open Logic text. But you will find definitions of validity, satisfaction, truth and so on. These are the terms used by logicians when doing logic.
It's fairly straightforward to demonstrate that truth can't be analyzed in that way.
What makes you think this?
Either the folks who responded that they accept correspondence theory didn't understand the question, or they interpreted "correspondence" in some creative way.
Correspondence is not accepted by anyone who's familiar with the topic. It's fairly straightforward to demonstrate that truth can't be analyzed in that way.
Spontaneous generation" connotes coming into existence after a time at which it did not exist. Rather, an initial state just entails existing uncaused, with no point of time at which it does not exist.
There hasn't been any serious attempt to go back to correspondence theory. It's defunct.
Cheshire would prefer to see us start from where we are, here in the world, with our problems in view instead of down in a brain-vat
If you want to make use of the term, then you can set out what you take it to mean.
I'm not sure I'd go as far as to say "correct" in describing a logic.
The question for logic, IMO, is not "How does one move from true premises to true conclusions?" -- I'd say that's a question for epistemology more broadly -- but rather logic is the study of validity. The big difference here from even introductory logic books is that the truth of the premises aren't relevant, which I'm sure you know already -- the moon being made of green cheese and all that.
So we don't care if the premises are true or not. We only care that if they are true, due to the form of inferences, that the conclusion must be true.
So we don't care if the premises are true or not. We only care that if they are true, due to the form of inferences, that the conclusion must be true.
I'm not sure the entailment relationship ends up being any more stable than the LNC or the principle of explosion. Pick your hinge and flip it!
Hegel describes the determinateness of quality as involving both “reality” and “negation.” These are the successors, within determinate being, of being and nothing (WL 5: 118/GW 21:98–99,29–35/111). What Hegel seems to have specifically in mind, in connection with “negation,” is that qualities are organized in what we might call a conceptual space, such that being one particular quality is not being the other qualities that are conceptually related to it. Being the quality, “red,” for example, is not just being a conceptually indeterminate “something or other,” knowable only by direct inspection; rather, it is being something that belongs in the conceptual space of color, and thus it is not being the color,“blue,”the color,“yellow,”and soon. In this way, the identity of the quality, “red,” essentially involves reference to what that quality is not:It essentially involves “negation.”6 Hegel sometimes refers to this dependence of quality on other qualities as “alteration” (WL 5:127/GW 21:106,8–9/118;EL§92,A), but it’s important to remember that in this initial context of quality as such, there is nothing analogous to time(or space) in which literal alteration could take place, so the term should be understood as referring to a relationship of logical dependency rather than to one of temporal sequence or transformation, as such.
Under the heading of “reality,”in contrast to“negation,”Hegel seems to want to capture a thought shared by philosophers such as John Duns Scotus, F. H. Jacobi, and C. S. Peirce, who stress an irreducible brute “this-ness,” or haecceitas, distinct from any relatedness or subsumption, as essential to reality. It seems to them that what a particular determinate being or quality is should just be a fact about it, rather than being a fact about how it relates to innumerable other determinate beings or qualities.7 Hegel’s introduction of “negation” alongside of “reality” makes it clear that “reality” (as something like “this-ness”) is not without problems, but that doesn’t cause him to abandon it. Working its problems out will, in effect, be the motor of the Logic as a whole.
If Hegel were asked: Why should we be concerned about this “reality” of determinate being? Why couldn’t we just accept the notion that all qualities are interdependent, defined by their relations to other qualities, “all the way down,” with no remainder (and that all of them are thereby equally “real” or equally “unreal”)?– his answer would be that if something could be what it is by virtue of itself, rather than solely by virtue of its relations to other things, it would clearly be more real, when taken by itself, than something that depends on its relations to other things to make it what it is. This is not to say that the thing that depends on other things is, in any sense, illusory– the “reality” that we’re talking about here is not contrasted with illusion, but with depending on others to determine what one is. Something that makes itself what it is has greater self-sufficiency than something that doesn’t do this, and this self-sufficiency is likely to be among the things that we think of when we think of “reality.” If it is among the things we think of, this could be because we’re aware that “reality”– like the word that Hegel uses, which is real, “realitat”– is derived from the Latin res, or “thing,” so that it contrasts not only with illusion but with anything that is less independent or self-sufficient than a thing.
Robert Wallace - Hegel's Philosophy of Reality, Freedom, and God
Isn't the 'brute fact' at the end of this one a necessary being or a circularity
Yes. If they weren't, then all forms of naturalism would be false.
Well, in a comparison of ontologies I suppose it might be considered question begging. Or on the question of "how might physicalism best be reconceived or reformed," it also seems to include problematic presuppositions.Of course. But What's wrong with that?
What makes you think that? I'm referring to David Armstrong's ontology- which accounts for everything that (unarguaby) objectively exists.
Please elaborate. I don't see how any sort of dualism fits into physicalism.