how to weigh freedom over different things within the normative theory of freedom consequentialism — Dan
Assumptions from Dan’s paper:
“Likelihood of truth (including internal consistency and not relying on propositions that we have good reason to believe are false)
Universality
Objectivity
Applicability to all free, rational agents
Action-guidingness
Achievableness (possible to live up to)
Consequentialism
Simplicity (in the sense of not postulating entities beyond necessity)
Extent to which the theory is in line with commonly held moral intuitions.”
That’s a ton. In the interest of simplicity, how about three:
1. Objective, universal (applicable to all), truth.
2. Achievable consequences guiding action
3. Extent it is already normative (compare against the prevailing wisdom).
(I agree as well we should seek simplicity, not for simplicity’s sake, but for clarity’s sake. Why complicate assumptions you are not going to question anyway?)
With that said, I like (my) assumptions 1 and 2. As for consequentialism, I’m not an expert. I prefer the more immanent “telos” to the more distant “consequence” as a term for what is action guiding, but that may be quibbling over assumptions.
“It is only the freedom over things that already belong to a person that matters, so getting more stuff over which a person can have freedom is not morally valuable. Things are bad, on this measure of value, when they prevent a person from being able to understand and make their own choices. Doing good—which I will discuss more in the following section—using this measure of value, is just a matter of preventing or reducing bad things from happening.”
“…there is sometimes a distinction drawn between positive and negative freedom, where positive freedom is freedom to do, have, or be something, whereas negative freedom is freedom from some external constraint. I do not think this distinction is particularly helpful...”
“While I have now explained the measure of value that freedom consequentialism uses.”
More feeedom good; less freedom bad? Is that the measurement we are taking? Freedom itself is the value we measure?
“An action is bad if scenario one has worse consequences than scenario two. An action is good if scenario one has better consequences than scenario two. And….is good …to the extent … causes no bad…”
Are we saying anything when using “better” and “worse” to define good and bad? Seems “better” sits on a scale between good and bad; so we need to define “good” and “bad” without using “better” and “worse,” because “better” and “worse” are tautologous with good and bad. Scenario 1 and scenario 2 may bring “good and better” and so “bad and worse” with them, but if we are trying to bring the measuring stick with us to the table and measure Scenario 1 against Scenario 2, using our “good better - bad worse” measuring stick, we may need to define them in themselves a bit, absent all scenarios.
This sounds like consequentialism. I’m not yet seeing what “freedom” consequentialism is. Im not seeing the need for universal applicability or objective truth yet either.
(10,000 prize? -I hope I don’t get fined for not understanding the premise!
:yum:)
“[Freedom consequentiialism] is a form of satisficing consequentialism that treats the ability of persons to understand and make their own choices as the measure of consequences’ moral value.”
The “ability to make choices” is the measure of the consequences’ value”. Sounds like freedom IS the value.
“When faced with a decision between funding a drug that saves one life every ten years and a drug that restores eyesight to five blind people within the same timeframe, how do we know which to fund? The obvious answer is “whichever protects the most freedom,” but how do we know which that is?”
You say “whichever protects the most freedom.” This is interesting to me. We assume agency and freedom exist; and then we are faced with a decision. The “good” choice is the choice we must make if we are to be moral. But I just said “must” which sounds like a limitation on freedom. (If there is something I “must” do it can be said that I have no choice.). So admittedly, morality (the objectively good choice) limits freedom. BUT, when that morality bases the “good” on “whichever protects the most freedom,” it can be said by doing what I “must” do, what I have no choice in doing, if I am to be good, if what I must do is good, my freedom is saved in the fact that what I have determined is most good is the most protective of freedom that existed in the first place.
Interesting.
“I think is most promising, that of determining the relative importance of freedom over different things by reference to a preferred order of wrongs.”
“Preferences need not be valuable in order to use them…”
“this does not tell us what to do when preferences conflict.”
I think your question here can be simply stated as “what are the objectively good rules?”
Conflicting preferences, how to weigh freedom over different things within the normative theory of freedom consequentialism… what I see as missing are the objective rules.
We assumed universal, objectivity, but then did not identify it or use it as part of the movement of comparing scenario 1 to scenario 2 on the scale of valued freedom, applied to conflicting preferences. These applications do not get beyond the subject-agent to the objective community of agents who conflict. Meaning, the consequentialism you’ve described starts to show the process of acting free, but cannot apply that process any further where the free act is directed against the freedom of another agent. So basically, we have two free agents in conflict with no objective measure to settle the dispute (possibly limiting both of their freedoms) - so you are basically asking “what are the rules?”
If there were rules carved in stone, then we could really pay no attention to preferences. But since there are no rules, the preferences (which ”prefer” incorporates a “good-better bad-worse” measuring stick to even say “prefer”, so is tautologous) are still vital in the measurement of “good” and “bad.”
This is why I don’t find utilitarianism satisfactory in general. It’s a method to solve disputes, that requires rules to employ, but has no rules (using synonyms and tautologies for “good” and “bad” to beg the presence of rules). Utilitarian theories can’t tell you what to do - they tell you
how to determine what to do, but leave it up to your preferences and pain and pleasures and betters and worses to make your own temporary rule and fight through what to actually do.
So I don’t see how to solve your problem. It’s an age old problem of “now that I know how to make a decision, what am I supposed to do now?”
But I liked the idea that “whichever protects freedom” is itself a measure of good. I just still don’t know what specifically truly is good in the end.