Insofar that there is an object "God" as they describe it with various predicates I don't really think it's there. — Moliere
But I do believe the words mean something, and that my belief that they are false isn't really that important after all. And I believe that words mean, and they are sincere, so there's something there, like you said here — Moliere
Even if someone did have a mystical experience with unicorns -- which really might not be that unlikely, now that I think on it, just embarrassing so people wouldn't say it -- I think I'd put it in the same box as other religious experiences. — Moliere
But we could come up with another example to demonstrate the point that we can say true things about what we name which are still fictional and thereby not persuasive when we're talking about attributing existence to things. — Moliere
The mystics, however, really do attribute existence to things which others do not because of their experience. Given my fixation on empirical justification for existential claims it throws a wrench into my thinking which I have to accommodate.
I still think what I think, but I think the mystics make sincere claims that are pretty much on par with saying "The cat is on the mat". — Moliere
Even though I'm an atheist I believe that Mystics have visited God, for instance. — Moliere
An ontology with just one thing (or nothing!) would be more parsimonious. But this seems to me to be in the vein of the eliminitivist who wants to get rid of consciousness because it messes with their models. If you're ontology doesn't describe what there actually is, what good is it for it to be parsimonious? — Count Timothy von Icarus
P1: If things exist, they must be properly defined/delineated in exactly this sort of way (insert rigid, unworkable definition, often made in terms of "unique particle ensembles" or bundle metaphysics). — Count Timothy von Icarus
My take is that the difficulty arises from an inability to question presuppositions about what an adequate response can even look like. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Artifacts are (for the most part) not self-organizing. A bikini isn't. A bikini is a lot like a rock. It isn't even like a star or storm, which at least have "life cycles" and act to sustain themselves. A rock is fairly arbitrary. It isn't entirely arbitrary, but obviously we can blast a cliff with dynamite and form very many rocks, pretty much at random. This is not how storms work, or stars, or life.
Hence, I would point to the research on dissipative systems, complexity studies, systems biology, etc., since these explain how we get self-organizing, self-determining systems that are arranged into wholes with proper parts. In living things, parts are unified in goal-directed pursuits. What makes a cat a cat then is primarily its being alive, and its being a specific sort of living thing, not its being comprised of some unique particle ensemble or fitting the rigid criteria of some bundle of properties. — Count Timothy von Icarus
If x and y are sets, then there exists a set which contains x and y as elements, for example if x = {1,2} and y = {2,3} then z will be {{1,2},{2,3}} — Wikipedia
I'm not sure what you mean. Horse in what race? — Tom Storm
For example, we can define a perfect unicorn, but this doesn't mean such an beast must exist. — Tom Storm
Basically, if Jesus and the documentary evidence we now possess are not self-consciously presenting evidence for Jesus' divinity, then the whole point is moot. If that is not in place then one could as easily claim that Benjamin Franklin was the Son of God as Jesus. — Leontiskos
(We actually have a lot of threads on these sorts of topics, so I don't want belabor this for too long.) — Leontiskos
It is merely a subset of the truth table where p!=q. — Leontiskos
If two things behave in precisely the same manner, then they do not have two different logical structures. — Leontiskos
The two modus ponens "arguments" under scrutiny behave in precisely the same manner; therefore they do not have two different logical structures — Leontiskos
You say that but then you want to make an ad hoc distinction between the "structure" of different modus ponens "arguments," so I still have hope for you. :wink: — Leontiskos
That's an interesting account, but I don't know of any rule of logic which requires that a modus ponens where p=q magically has a different structure. The validity rules are all the same, so it's not clear what it would even mean to claim that it has a different structure. If you're all about formalism, then the structure is exactly the same. — Leontiskos
Then you have no reason to claim that the modus ponens where p=q has a different structure, apart from poetry. "Poetically they have a different structure, but formally they do not." — Leontiskos
On my view if someone cannot see that this is a degenerate case of modus ponens, then they haven't grasped the raison d'être of logic:
1. p → p
2. p
3. ∴ p — Leontiskos
...and of course someone who limits themselves to "formalisms" cannot admit the notion of a degenerate case. — Leontiskos
Same structure:
p: God exists
q: God exists
1. p → q
2. p
3. ∴ q — Leontiskos
(The structure is modus ponens, and you yourself claimed that 1-2-3 is a modus ponens.) — Leontiskos
But just a few minutes ago you said, "An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it." Now you want to say that some sound arguments are good and some sound arguments are bad. So clearly there is something more to it. — Leontiskos
<Sure it does>. And when Frege first tried to introduce the material conditional he was resisted for decades for this very reason. — Leontiskos
But you yourself said that it is a "perfectly valid modus ponens." So what's the problem? What's the difference between a modus ponens where p=q and a modus ponens where p!=q? It seems that on your view there can be no significant distinction between the two modus ponens. — Leontiskos
Yes: you think 4-5-6 is the sound argument, right? — Leontiskos
Sure, if you rely on the degenerate cases of the material conditional, where a false antecedent or a true consequent guarantees a true conditional. But I think I spoke to that. — Leontiskos
Let me show why I disagree.
Suppose I say that God exists, and you tell me that I've made an assertion rather than an argument. So I give what you view as an "argument":
1. If God exists, then God exists
2. God exists
3. Therefore, God exists — Leontiskos
Now apparently this is an argument, which is entirely different from an assertion. Since I have given an argument, you have the burden of proof in addressing the argument. You might say, "God does not exist," and I might say, "That's an assertion, not an argument." — Leontiskos
So you comply: — Leontiskos
4. If God does not exist, then God does not exist
5. God does not exist
6. Therefore, God does not exist — Leontiskos
We could do that for eternity — Leontiskos
on my view we are neither arguing nor giving arguments, whereas on your view we are (and I have encountered people who literally did this). — Leontiskos
Aristotle tells us that arguments move from premises that are better-known to conclusions that are lesser-known. If it doesn't do that, it isn't an argument. — Leontiskos
In fact 1-2-3 is a sound "argument," but I would contend that it is not an argument at all. — Leontiskos
An since an argument is the same thing as a proof, it follows that I already gave two proofs in the OP. — Arcane Sandwich
Well if you "spoke" the proofs then you have the basic burden of proof, no? Your Wikipedia article says that the one who speaks has the burden. — Leontiskos
Or rather, you have simulated a scenario in which someone gives a very opaque argument (FTI), and then you "denied" part of FTI (to quote Wikipedia), so for Wikipedia whoever spoke FTI has the initial burden of proof. So who spoke FTI? No one at all, it seems. It is part of an OP that offers no real argument, and which does not accept the burden of proof for what it claims. — Leontiskos
According to your Wikipedia article you have the burden of proof, for you are the one who spoke. — Leontiskos
...the question is actually meaningless to you, and is basically a form of entertainment, if that. — Wayfarer
you said, "if FTI1 is true, then FTI2 must necessarily be false." Why? Why can't both premises be true? — Leontiskos
Okay sure, if you are appealing to the "degenerate cases" of the material conditional then I agree that the former Muslim cannot deny that God exists without affirming that, "If God exists, then God is identical to Jesus," at least if he is consistent. But I'm not sure how useful arguments that depend on such degenerate cases are. — Leontiskos
Here you might be right, but only in the sense that both arguments might be valid and yet unsound. — Arcane Sandwich
But isn't that precisely what you meant when you spoke about the possibility of "rejecting both arguments at the same time"? — Leontiskos
On the contrary, a sound conclusion is the conclusion of a sound argument. And as I said, "if either conclusion is sound then both first-premises must be true" (given material conditionals). — Leontiskos
It is not an argument in any substantial sense, and the "arguments" of the OP are similarly insubstantial. Namely, there is nothing persuasive or compelling about them. — Leontiskos
For example, I could write an OP:
1. If the moon is made of cheese, then pelicans are vegans
2. The moon is made of cheese
3. Therefore, pelicans are vegans — Leontiskos
I might follow this with, "Options for resisting the argument." But there is no argument to resist, not in any substantial sense. The person making the argument has the burden of proof in showing the argument to be persuasive or compelling, and mere validity does not succeed in doing this. (Formalizations such as this are only valid consequences, not cases of true inference.) — Leontiskos
So rather than give a substantial argument, you've asked TPF users to give substantial arguments against at least one of four propositions (namely, the premises). It's a bit like saying, "I think X. Prove me wrong."
(I would grant that ATI is closer to a substantial argument than FTI, since FTI1 is entirely opaque.) — Leontiskos
Still... determining if God exists by modern science can't be done, either way. I like to say that this is a positive thing -- in a way Kant's philosophy is attractive because people can be of any religious persuasion and still believe the same things about the world we experience, and independently believe whatever makes them fulfilled in a moral sense. — Moliere
Georges Henri Joseph Édouard Lemaître (/ləˈmɛtrə/ lə-MET-rə; French: [ʒɔʁʒ ləmɛːtʁ]; 17 July 1894 – 20 June 1966) was a Belgian Catholic priest, theoretical physicist, and mathematician who made major contributions to cosmology and astrophysics. He was the first to argue that the recession of galaxies is evidence of an expanding universe and to connect the observational Hubble–Lemaître law with the solution to the Einstein field equations in the general theory of relativity for a homogenous and isotropic universe. That work led Lemaître to propose what he called the "hypothesis of the primeval atom", now regarded as the first formulation of the Big Bang theory of the origin of the universe. — Wikipedia
If I investigate textbooks which academic departments use to teach science -- there is absolutely nothing in there about Jesus or God. — Moliere
The bud disappears when the blossom breaks through, and we might say that the former is refuted by the latter; in the same way when the fruit comes, the blossom may be explained to be a false form of the plant’s existence, for the fruit appears as its true nature in place of the blossom. These stages are not merely differentiated; they supplant one another as being incompatible with one another. But the ceaseless activity of their own inherent nature makes them at the same time moments of an organic unity, where they not merely do not contradict one another, but where one is as necessary as the other; and this equal necessity of all moments constitutes alone and thereby the life of the whole. But contradiction as between philosophical systems is not wont to be conceived in this way; on the other hand, the mind perceiving the contradiction does not commonly know how to relieve it or keep it free from its one-sidedness, and to recognise in what seems conflicting and inherently antagonistic the presence of mutually necessary moments. — Hegel
It's just not rational in terms of scientific justification -- there's not a science which can evaluate which religious concept of god is superior because, by the science, they're all
false, and mostly useless. So the science doesn't have much to say on the issue. (which is what Kant's "theoretical knowledge" is based upon) — Moliere
Hence the atheist will have to propose serious arguments against it [Anselm's argument] instead of the sophistry of the logical imperialist. (...) In short, Anselm was far less wrong than his modern critics would have it. — Bunge (2012: 175)
The notion of god is inconsistent.
Anything follows from an inconsistency.
Therefore Jesus is God. — Banno
I'm more tempted to say that God, as a concept, is empty than inconsistent -- it's like the empty set. — Moliere
First, if it is not possible to deny both premises, then it would follow that if one is false, then the other must necessarily be true. — Leontiskos
Your opposite claim simply does not follow. — Leontiskos
(FTI1) If God exists, then God is identical to Jesus.
(FTI2) God exists.
(FTI3) So, God is identical to Jesus. — Arcane Sandwich
To give a counterexample, consider a Muslim who became an atheist. They deny (1) and (2). So it is very clearly possible to deny both premises. — Leontiskos
Conversely, it's not possible to reject both arguments at the same time. If you reject one of them, then that means that you accept the other one — Arcane Sandwich
This too looks to be false. The conclusions are contradictories, but that does not entail that the arguments are "contradictories" (so to speak). The believing Muslim is someone who rejects both arguments. — Leontiskos
(Beyond that, I wouldn't count the formalizations of the OP as arguments, given that their premises are neither intuitive nor defended.) — Leontiskos
That gets into the questions similar to <this thread>. My point wasn't to claim that both first premises are false. That cannot be done if we are using material conditionals. Note, though, that if we are talking about material conditionals, then if either conclusion is sound then both first-premises must be true. — Leontiskos
It's a different argument from the atheist. Furthermore we can plug in any God here -- there's a lot to choose from in picking out God's identity. But God existing just says that without saying what God is. — Moliere
Further, unlike saying something like "John Doe exists", there is no way to adjudicate between any of the above arguments. There is absolutely no difference in the external world whether God does or does not exist, which is normally how we'd go about making a decision as to which premise -- God exists or God does not exist -- to accept. — Moliere
So, in isolation, sure -- but in terms of how people go about deciding these things I don't see a reason to accept that there is a relationship between God's -- or any objects -- existence and what they are identical to. — Moliere
Let us now use the existential predicate introduced above to revisit the most famous of all the arguments for God’s existence. Anselm of Canterbury argued that God exists because He is perfect, and existence is a property of perfection. Some mathematical logicians have claimed that Anselm was wrong because existence is not a predicate but the ∃ quantifier. I suggest that this objection is sophistic because in all the fields of knowledge we tacitly use an existential predicate that has nothing to do with the “existential” quantifier, as when it is asserted or denied that there are living beings in Mars or perpetual motion machines. — Bunge (2012: 174-175)
Using the existence predicate defined a while ago, we may reformulate Anselm’s argument as follows.
God is perfect ______________________ Pg
Everything perfect exists in R [really]_____∀x(Px → ERx)
God exists in R.______________________ ERg
Both premises are controversial, particularly the first one since it presupposes the existence of God. Hence the atheist will have to propose serious arguments against it instead of the sophistry of the logical imperialist. An alternative is to admit the existence of God for the sake of argument, and add the ontological postulate that everything real is imperfect: that if something is perfect then it is ideal, like Pythagoras’ theorem or a Beethoven sonata. But the conjunction of both postulates implies the unreality of God. In short, Anselm was far less wrong than his modern critics would have it. — Bunge (2012: 175)
I'm kind of uncertain about properties just as I'm uncertain about objects, but that'll take us pretty far astray :D -- a lot of my skepticism is based in wondering how we can reliably make inferences with respect to metaphysics, and generally wondering how it is we can really ascertain what metaphysics is preferable in the face of many smart and educated people asserting contradictory opinions on the subject. — Moliere
Ontology should precede epistemology. And yet modern philosophy started rejecting metaphysics. It did so just because the ruling metaphysics around 1600 was obsolete. The price paid for this antimetaphysical turn was subjectivism, outspoken as in Berkeley’s case, or shame-faced as in Kant’s. — Bunge (2010: 201)
Such as your two arguments -- it's just kind of funny to make an inference between existence and identity. I'd be inclined to go the reverse -- if Jesus is God, then God exists. — Moliere
So God could exist without Jesus being God — Moliere
"If God exists, then Muhammed is the prophet, and Jesus is a prophet. God exists, therefore..."
Do you see how that's funny? — Moliere
Depends upon how far back you go. — Paine
But in following Kant there's not an easy distinction between predicates and properties. — Moliere
Well, yes, as I said, it's not a great example. We might get out our CRISPR and re-arrange the genetics of a fruit fly so that it has an extra body segment and two more pairs of legs. Is it still an insect? — Banno
I'm suggesting that this is as much a question of word use as it is of entomology. — Banno
Eugenics and classic nationalism of the 19th Century went away in the Nordic countries quite quickly. — ssu
More like a tourist attraction nowdays when you have Europe's "only indigenous people" around. — ssu
My thinking on existence is largely influenced by Kant. So sentences of the sort "God exists" do not have conditions of justification even if they have a truth-value, so I wouldn't bother believing "God exists", or its negation, on rational grounds. The old "existence is not a predicate" is something that rings basically true to me -- logic does not prove existence, existence exists regardless of a choice of logic -- and the thought experiment between the imagined unicorn and the imagined unicorn existing demonstrates to me that there's not really a property added to something I'm thinking about. I need some other kind of justification to infer that something exists. — Moliere
This process might involve persons receiving (accepting) the revelation of Jesus Christ as redeemer and sanctifier who calls persons to a radical life of loving compassion, even the loving of our enemies. By willfully subjecting oneself to the commanding love of God, a person in this filial relationship with God through Christ may experience a change of character (from self-centeredness to serving others) in which the person’s character (or very being) may come to serve as evidence of the truths of faith. — Charles Taliaferro
Each of these attributes has been subject to nuanced different analysis, as noted below. God has also been traditionally conceived to be incorporeal or immaterial, immutable, impassable, omnipresent. And unlike Judaism and Islam, Christian theists conceive of God as triune (the Godhead is not homogenous but consists of three Persons, Father, Son, and Holy Spirit) and incarnate as Jesus of Nazareth (fully God and fully human). — Charles Taliaferro
The “truth” of the Incarnation has been interpreted in such terms as these: in Jesus Christ (or in the narratives about Christ) God is disclosed. Or: Jesus Christ was so united with God’s will that his actions were and are the functional display of God’s character. Perhaps as a result of Hick’s challenge, philosophical work on the incarnation and other beliefs and practice specific to religious traditions have received renewed attention (see, for example, Taliaferro and Meister 2009). Hick has been a leading, widely appreciated force in the expansion of philosophy of religion in the late twentieth century. — Charles Taliaferro