If I investigate textbooks which academic departments use to teach science -- there is absolutely nothing in there about Jesus or God. — Moliere
The bud disappears when the blossom breaks through, and we might say that the former is refuted by the latter; in the same way when the fruit comes, the blossom may be explained to be a false form of the plant’s existence, for the fruit appears as its true nature in place of the blossom. These stages are not merely differentiated; they supplant one another as being incompatible with one another. But the ceaseless activity of their own inherent nature makes them at the same time moments of an organic unity, where they not merely do not contradict one another, but where one is as necessary as the other; and this equal necessity of all moments constitutes alone and thereby the life of the whole. But contradiction as between philosophical systems is not wont to be conceived in this way; on the other hand, the mind perceiving the contradiction does not commonly know how to relieve it or keep it free from its one-sidedness, and to recognise in what seems conflicting and inherently antagonistic the presence of mutually necessary moments. — Hegel
Yet that wasn't always the case. As Hegel suggests, in The Phenomenology of Spirit, the history of philosophy is like the maturing of a plant. We wouldn't say that the fruit refutes the flower, or that the flower refutes the seed. I believe the same can be said about science. In its contemporary version, it's the end product of a history in which its roots were deeply interwoven with matters of theology, whether we like it or not. It is what it is, as you oosians like to say. — Arcane Sandwich
Still... determining if God exists by modern science can't be done, either way. I like to say that this is a positive thing -- in a way Kant's philosophy is attractive because people can be of any religious persuasion and still believe the same things about the world we experience, and independently believe whatever makes them fulfilled in a moral sense. — Moliere
Georges Henri Joseph Édouard Lemaître (/ləˈmɛtrə/ lə-MET-rə; French: [ʒɔʁʒ ləmɛːtʁ]; 17 July 1894 – 20 June 1966) was a Belgian Catholic priest, theoretical physicist, and mathematician who made major contributions to cosmology and astrophysics. He was the first to argue that the recession of galaxies is evidence of an expanding universe and to connect the observational Hubble–Lemaître law with the solution to the Einstein field equations in the general theory of relativity for a homogenous and isotropic universe. That work led Lemaître to propose what he called the "hypothesis of the primeval atom", now regarded as the first formulation of the Big Bang theory of the origin of the universe. — Wikipedia
You lost me here. Can you please clarify what you mean by that? — Arcane Sandwich
I'm not sure I follow. The formal structure of that argument is the following one:
1) If p, then q.
2) p.
3) so, q.
If (1) is false, then (2) is true, and if (1) is true, then (2) is false. — Arcane Sandwich
Here you might be right, but only in the sense that both arguments might be valid and yet unsound. — Arcane Sandwich
If so, then that's a powerful reason for rejecting both arguments. — Arcane Sandwich
However, it's still the case that if one of the conclusions is true, then the other one is false, and vice-versa. — Arcane Sandwich
The concept of soundness (and unsoundness) applies only to arguments, not to propositions (premises and conclusions), just as the concept of validity (or lack of thereof) only applies to arguments, not to propositions. A proposition (being a premise or a conclusion) can only be true or false. That is at least the modern understanding of such notions. — Arcane Sandwich
This is indeed an argument — Arcane Sandwich
Since I'm an atheist... — Arcane Sandwich
Due to how the burden of proof works, I don't need to prove a negative — Arcane Sandwich
you said, "if FTI1 is true, then FTI2 must necessarily be false." Why? Why can't both premises be true? — Leontiskos
Okay sure, if you are appealing to the "degenerate cases" of the material conditional then I agree that the former Muslim cannot deny that God exists without affirming that, "If God exists, then God is identical to Jesus," at least if he is consistent. But I'm not sure how useful arguments that depend on such degenerate cases are. — Leontiskos
Here you might be right, but only in the sense that both arguments might be valid and yet unsound. — Arcane Sandwich
But isn't that precisely what you meant when you spoke about the possibility of "rejecting both arguments at the same time"? — Leontiskos
On the contrary, a sound conclusion is the conclusion of a sound argument. And as I said, "if either conclusion is sound then both first-premises must be true" (given material conditionals). — Leontiskos
It is not an argument in any substantial sense, and the "arguments" of the OP are similarly insubstantial. Namely, there is nothing persuasive or compelling about them. — Leontiskos
For example, I could write an OP:
1. If the moon is made of cheese, then pelicans are vegans
2. The moon is made of cheese
3. Therefore, pelicans are vegans — Leontiskos
I might follow this with, "Options for resisting the argument." But there is no argument to resist, not in any substantial sense. The person making the argument has the burden of proof in showing the argument to be persuasive or compelling, and mere validity does not succeed in doing this. (Formalizations such as this are only valid consequences, not cases of true inference.) — Leontiskos
So rather than give a substantial argument, you've asked TPF users to give substantial arguments against at least one of four propositions (namely, the premises). It's a bit like saying, "I think X. Prove me wrong."
(I would grant that ATI is closer to a substantial argument than FTI, since FTI1 is entirely opaque.) — Leontiskos
...the question is actually meaningless to you, and is basically a form of entertainment, if that. — Wayfarer
According to your Wikipedia article you have the burden of proof, for you are the one who spoke. — Leontiskos
Or rather, you have simulated a scenario in which someone gives a very opaque argument (FTI), and then you "denied" part of FTI (to quote Wikipedia), so for Wikipedia whoever spoke FTI has the initial burden of proof. So who spoke FTI? No one at all, it seems. It is part of an OP that offers no real argument, and which does not accept the burden of proof for what it claims. — Leontiskos
Both premises can be true, but they can't both be false. Only one of them can be false. — Arcane Sandwich
What can I say? I don't share your notion of a "substantial" argument. An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it. Logic is a science (a formal science, just like mathematics). It has nothing to do with persuasiveness, just as algebra or geometry have nothing to do with persuasiveness. — Arcane Sandwich
An since an argument is the same thing as a proof, it follows that I already gave two proofs in the OP. — Arcane Sandwich
Sure, if you rely on the degenerate cases of the material conditional, where a false antecedent or a true consequent guarantees a true conditional. But I think I spoke to that. — Leontiskos
Let me show why I disagree.
Suppose I say that God exists, and you tell me that I've made an assertion rather than an argument. So I give what you view as an "argument":
1. If God exists, then God exists
2. God exists
3. Therefore, God exists — Leontiskos
Now apparently this is an argument, which is entirely different from an assertion. Since I have given an argument, you have the burden of proof in addressing the argument. You might say, "God does not exist," and I might say, "That's an assertion, not an argument." — Leontiskos
So you comply: — Leontiskos
4. If God does not exist, then God does not exist
5. God does not exist
6. Therefore, God does not exist — Leontiskos
We could do that for eternity — Leontiskos
on my view we are neither arguing nor giving arguments, whereas on your view we are (and I have encountered people who literally did this). — Leontiskos
Aristotle tells us that arguments move from premises that are better-known to conclusions that are lesser-known. If it doesn't do that, it isn't an argument. — Leontiskos
In fact 1-2-3 is a sound "argument," but I would contend that it is not an argument at all. — Leontiskos
An since an argument is the same thing as a proof, it follows that I already gave two proofs in the OP. — Arcane Sandwich
Well if you "spoke" the proofs then you have the basic burden of proof, no? Your Wikipedia article says that the one who speaks has the burden. — Leontiskos
I'm open to the idea that God might exist, and that Jesus might be God. — Arcane Sandwich
There's nothing "degenerate" about such cases. That notion has no place in a formal science such as logic. — Arcane Sandwich
Which is why the arguments in the OP, while being modus ponens, do not have the same structure as the one in your example. Because in your example, the conditional has the form "if p, then p", while the conditionals in the arguments of the OP have this other structure: "if p, then q". — Arcane Sandwich
It's not a sound argument, at least not to my atheist eyes. It is valid, however. Just not sound. — Arcane Sandwich
<Sure it does>. And when Frege first tried to introduce the material conditional he was resisted for decades for this very reason. — Leontiskos
But you yourself said that it is a "perfectly valid modus ponens." So what's the problem? What's the difference between a modus ponens where p=q and a modus ponens where p!=q? It seems that on your view there can be no significant distinction between the two modus ponens. — Leontiskos
Yes: you think 4-5-6 is the sound argument, right? — Leontiskos
They have different structures. "If p, then p" is not the same structure as "If p, then q". — Arcane Sandwich
But I wouldn't endorse that argument myself, because it's easily refutable. To speak poetically for a moment, it's not a good argument, even though it's both valid and sound. — Arcane Sandwich
I'm going to need to ask you two if you have horses in this race, before proceeding any further. — Arcane Sandwich
Same structure:
p: God exists
q: God exists
1. p → q
2. p
3. ∴ q — Leontiskos
(The structure is modus ponens, and you yourself claimed that 1-2-3 is a modus ponens.) — Leontiskos
But just a few minutes ago you said, "An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it." Now you want to say that some sound arguments are good and some sound arguments are bad. So clearly there is something more to it. — Leontiskos
There's two types of structures in logic: the structure of arguments, and the structure of propositions. Two arguments can have the same structure (i.e., both of them are modus ponens) while having propositions with different structures (i.e., p → q instead of p → p). — Arcane Sandwich
When I say that some arguments are good and that some of them are bad, I'm speaking poetically. In other words, I'm being rhetorical, not logical. I don't dismiss rhetoric, I simply declare that being persuasive and compelling are within its province, instead of being qualities of the formal science that we call logic. — Arcane Sandwich
That's an interesting account, but I don't know of any rule of logic which requires that a modus ponens where p=q magically has a different structure. The validity rules are all the same, so it's not clear what it would even mean to claim that it has a different structure. If you're all about formalism, then the structure is exactly the same. — Leontiskos
Then you have no reason to claim that the modus ponens where p=q has a different structure, apart from poetry. "Poetically they have a different structure, but formally they do not." — Leontiskos
On my view if someone cannot see that this is a degenerate case of modus ponens, then they haven't grasped the raison d'être of logic:
1. p → p
2. p
3. ∴ p — Leontiskos
...and of course someone who limits themselves to "formalisms" cannot admit the notion of a degenerate case. — Leontiskos
Not quite, because the difference between p → p and p → q affects their truth values. — Arcane Sandwich
That's not what I claim. Formally they have different structures, not poetically. — Arcane Sandwich
The same goes for the notion of degeneracy. It only makes sense outside of logic, not within it. — Arcane Sandwich
It is merely a subset of the truth table where p!=q. — Leontiskos
If two things behave in precisely the same manner, then they do not have two different logical structures. — Leontiskos
The two modus ponens "arguments" under scrutiny behave in precisely the same manner; therefore they do not have two different logical structures — Leontiskos
You say that but then you want to make an ad hoc distinction between the "structure" of different modus ponens "arguments," so I still have hope for you. :wink: — Leontiskos
Put it this way: when someone gives a modus ponens you don't have to check with them first, to make sure that p!=q. It makes no difference at all. There is no caveat when it comes to modus ponens, no condition where if p=q the rule fails. — Leontiskos
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.