Even in that more general case, the Bayesian approach can give a switching strategy with a positive expected net gain. — andrewk
As an aside, I think we're saying the same thing from different angles. — fdrake
I see the situation as this:
Assume there's £10 in my envelope and that one envelope contains twice as much as the other. The other envelope must contain either £5 or £20. Each is equally likely and so the expected value of the other envelope is £12.50. I can then take advantage of this fact by employing this switching strategy to achieve this .25 gain. — Michael
Of course you won't. You don't like facts that disagree with your beliefs.I will not further debate such specifics. — Jeremiah
I hope I'm not talking down, that isn't my point. But probability really needs great care with terminology, and it has been noticeably lacking in this thread. This question is a result of that lack.You're going it again. Is X the value of my envelope or the value of the smallest envelope? You're switching between both and it doesn't make any sense, especially where you say "if you have the lower value envelope X/2".
If you did, that statement was completely obfuscated by your sloppy techniques. And it isn't the argument that is flawed, it is the assumption that you know the distribution. As shown by the points you have ignored in my posts.I specifically said that my simulation is not about finding expected results as that entire argument is flawed.
The thing to notice here is that you can't use your "X"- the lower value - as a condition unless you see both envelopes, which renders analysis pointless.The thing to notice here is that in all cases the absolute value of the difference between column one and column two is always equal to the lesser of the two (save rounding errors). The lesser of the two is X.
I pointed out a few times that the sample space of event R and the sample space of event S are equal subsets of each other, which means mathematically we can treat them the same.
This is unintelligble.R and S is the event you have X or 2X when you get A. By definition of A and B, if A=X then B =2X, or if A =2X then B=X. So by definition if A equals X then B cannot also equal X.
This may be what you were referring to when about "Y." It still refers to ill-defined sets, not distributions.I also pointed out that as soon as you introduce Y they are no longer equal subsets and therefore mathematically cannot be treated the same.
It is provable without simulation that the the two distributions are the same, so this is pointless. We can accept that the distributions are the same. And it is is obvious you didn't read my posts describing why the simulation is pointless. In short, the "data" you apply "data science" to pertains only to how well your simulation addresses the provable fact.The point of this demonstration is to show that the possible distribution of A is the same as the possible distribution of B. ... So we see with a D test statistics of 0.0077 and a 0.92 p-value we don't have strong enough evidence to support the alternative hypothesis that the two distributions are reasonably different.
And again, you won't say what results you mean.I am happy with my correct results.
... is a correct solution to the original problem when you don't look in the envelope. The problem with it, is that it doesn't explain to why his program doesn't model the OP. That is something you never did correctly, and you refuse to accept that I did.If you have X and you switch then you get 2X but lose X so you gain X; so you get a +1 X. However, if you have 2X and switch then you gain X and lose 2X; so you get a -1 X.
... is also correct, although it is easier to prove it directly, But it is still irrelevant unless you determine that the two distributions are independent. AND THEY ARE NOT.the possible distribution of A is the same as the possible distribution of B
... that is incorrect, as I just showed in my last post. The probability that A has the smaller value depends on the relative values of two probabilities in that distribution, so it is significant to the question you address here.the distribution in which X was selected from is not significant when assessing the possible outcome of envelope A and B concerning X or 2X.
I am well aware 0 was a possible outcome, the code just runs better without the loops, and it was not significant enough to care.
Sorry my simulation proves you wrong.
In short, the "need to" include the probability distribution is because the formulation of the "simple algebraic solution" is incorrect if you exclude it.I'm just trying to understand the "need to" in that sentence.
That isn't as useful as you might think. You can assert how that independence is obvious, since the random variable R (where R is 1/2 or 2 if you picked low or high) is chosen without knowledge of the random variable L (the low value of the pair). But all this independence means is, for any values of the unknowns L1 and R1, that:Doesn't this amount to saying that the loading of the envelopes and the selection of an envelope are independent events,
What? You don't want to address a correct analysis, until I weed through pages of debate that appears to be inconclusive? Because I can guarantee you, that applying my correct analysis can resolve them.I am not doing this, not until you actually read all of my posts in this thread. — Jeremiah
Yes, my point was that the lottery example is a very bad description of a sample space. In fact, It is the archtype for just that. But so is ignoring that you are assuming a distribution of amounts as well as whether you picked high or low. Maybe if you looked at my examples, you'd understand this. That was also a point I made.That is a very bad understanding of what a sample space and an event is. You are not applying your Principle of Indifference there, which states from your link: "The principle of indifference states that if the n possibilities are indistinguishable except for their names, then each possibility should be assigned a probability equal to 1/n." n in this case would be the total possible combinations of the lottery numbers.
Imagine three variations of this game:You are playing a game for money. There are two envelopes on a table.
You know that one contains $X and the other $2X, [but you do not
know which envelope is which or what the number X is]. Initially you
are allowed to pick one of the envelopes, to open it, and see that it
contains $Y . You then have a choice: walk away with the $Y or return
the envelope to the table and walk away with whatever is in the other
envelope. What should you do?
But she isn't asked for her confidence in that situation, so this argument is a red herring. A very appealing red herring, as you go on to describe, but irrelevant nonetheless.In standard SB, on (H & Tue) our Beauty receives no information at all. — Srap Tasmaner
No, it isn't.Probability is about expectations.
That is not what the condition is. It is {AWAKE}, which is can also be written as ~{HEADS&Tuesday} or {HEADS&Monday,TAILS&Monday,TAILS&Tuesday}.it sure does look like the design of the experiment involves conditioning heads on ~Tuesday,
"Random" is not a property of what you are looking at in an experiment. It is a property of what you know about it, but can't see. Either because the experiment hasn't happened yet, or it has but you can't see what happened.One thing I'm generally uncertain about is how strongly to lean on "what day today is" being random.
Yes, it is. The bolded text tells the lab techs what to do - or more accurately, what not to do - on both days. It defines two protocols for TAILS: interview Monday, interview Tuesday. It defines two protocols for HEADS: interview Monday, sleep Tuesday. Even if they send her home that day, that would still be SOTAI.What happens on Tuesday&HEADS is a part of the HEADS protocol, so you excluded part of it. — JeffJo
(a) No it isn't. From the OP:
A fair coin will be tossed to determine which experimental procedure to undertake: if the coin comes up heads, Beauty will be awakened and interviewed on Monday only. If the coin comes up tails, she will be awakened and interviewed on Monday and Tuesday. In either case, she will be awakened on Wednesday without interview and the experiment ends. — Srap Tasmaner
What matters is that there is a protocol on both days for both HEADS and TAILS. And that one of these four protocols is inconsistent with Beauty being interviewed. You keep treating the fact that she sleeps through a day as if that makes the day nonexistent,or that it is not something the lab techs have to have included in their protocol.The only thing that matters is one for heads and two for tails
?????(b) If it were part of the heads protocol, by eliminating it, you would be eliminating heads as an outcome. Simply being interviewed would tell you the coin landed tails.
Yep. Get two thousand volunteers. Order them randomly from #1 to #2,000. House #1 thru #1,0000 in the HEADS wing of your lab, and #1,001 thru #2,000 in the TAILS wing. Then flip your fair a coin.If that seems like a tendentious interpretation, consider what happens as you increase the number of tails interviews: whatever the ratio, that's your odds it was tails. Do a thousand tails interviews, and it's a near certainty -- according to thirders -- that a fair coin lands tails.
This is incorrect. What happens on Tuesday&HEADS is a part of the HEADS protocol, so you excluded part of it. And you treat the various possibilities inconsistently.If I condition on ~(Tuesday & HEADS), I exclude neither the heads protocol nor the tails protocol, as neither included it.
The "help" I am trying to offer, is to get you to see that you have to separate both protocols into individual days. And you are right, it will be of no help to you if you refuse to see this, just like you won't address my "four volunteers" proof that the answer is 1/3.This helps me not at all.
It is indeed true that Beauty has no evidence that she can use to distinguish Monday from Tuesday. This does not mean that such evidence does not exist, only that she does not have it.When Beauty is asked, "What is your credence that the coin landed heads?" she knows there's a chance the experiment is using the heads protocol, in which case this is her one and only interview, and a chance that it is using the tails protocol, in which case this may be her first interview, last, or one of many, depending. By stipulation, there is no evidence she can use to distinguish one interview from another; all she has to go on is her knowledge of the experiment's design.