concepts are used in different ways. — Shawn
I'm not. I'm wondering about your thinking on the topic, and how it relates toIf you're looking for a specific answer, then go ahead, provide one. — Shawn
It is clear Wittgenstein is rejecting any notion of treating words as just names, and that concepts are about use, not just grammar....the passage of the Philosophical Investigations, I/§383, regarding "concepts as words" and Wittgensteins nominalism. — Shawn
Midgley's plumbing metaphor might show the point better than Wittgenstein's therapy metaphor.Are philosophers still in need of therapy? — Shawn
We are not analysing a phenomenon (e.g. thought) but a concept (e.g. that of thinking), and therefore the use of a word.
I'm just not going to go on a tangent to other topics. — Vivek
G.E. Moore asks a similar question. What exactly do we mean when we say something is good? What does it mean when we say something is right or wrong? — Vivek
So, I think, there is some internal aspect of how learning can at all take place... — Shawn
Not qualities, but uses. In addition to the grammar, there is what we do - we choose the blue bicycle and go for a ride. That's not grammar.Are you alluding to qualities of concepts — Shawn
If it is all about the externalities of the topic, then I'm only concerned with the internal aspect of how concepts are understood. — Shawn
So you say sharing a common grammar makes it possible for us to understand concepts. What are concepts?I've always held that by obeying the same grammar, which allows people to coherently formulate their thoughts in language, we are able to understand concepts. — Shawn
132. We want to establish an order in our knowledge of the use
of language: an order with a particular end in view; one out of many
possible orders; not the order. To this end we shall constantly be
giving prominence to distinctions which our ordinary forms of
language easily make us overlook. This may make it look as if we
saw it as our task to reform language.
Such a reform for particular practical purposes, an improvement in
our terminology designed to prevent misunderstandings in practice,
is perfectly possible. But these are not the cases we have to do with.
The confusions which occupy us arise when language is like an engine
idling, not when it is doing work.
133. It is not our aim to refine or complete the system of rules for
the use of our words in unheard-of ways.
For the clarity that we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But
this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely
disappear.
The real discovery is the one that makes me capable of stopping
doing philosophy when I want to.—The one that gives philosophy
peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions which bring itself
in question.—Instead, we now demonstrate a method, by examples;
and the series of examples can be broken off.—Problems are solved
(difficulties eliminated), not a single problem.
There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed
methods, like different therapies.
593. A main cause of philosophical disease—a one-sided diet: one
nourishes one's thinking with only one kind of example.
254. The substitution of "identical" for "the same" (for instance)
is another typical expedient in philosophy. As if we were talking about
shades of meaning and all that were in question were to find words
to hit on the correct nuance. That is in question in philosophy only
where we have to give a psychologically exact account of the temptation
to use a particular kind of expression. What we 'are tempted to say'
in such a case is, of course, not philosophy; but it is its raw material.
Thus, for example, what a mathematician is inclined to say about the
objectivity and reality of mathematical facts, is not a philosophy of
mathematics, but something for philosophical treatment.
255 . The philosopher's treatment of a question is like the treatment of an illness. — Philosophical Investigations
What pisses me off most about the choice debate is the insincerity of the antagonists.
The reason you want to ban abortion is nothing to do with fair ethical consideration. It's because the people who tell you what your invisible friend wants say abortion is naughty.
The same misogynist folk who fight against child care, public education, maternity leave, and most other things that will actually benefit people. The ones who think giving guns to children is a good idea, and are shit scared of anyone who is slightly different, sexually, ethnically, geographically, politically or spiritually.
The folk who will not mention, let alone consider, the role of the potential mother; utter bullshit. — Banno
Opposition to abortion is immoral.
It is immoral because it puts the "needs" of a cyst ahead of those of a human.
Pretending a cyst has rights in order to defend one's invisible friends is immoral.
My blood cells are human. They do not amount to a human being. A blastocyst is human. It is not a human being. Anti-abortion rhetoric relies on equivocating between human and human being. Cysts are not persons. Being a person involves sentience, emotion, affection, physical health, an appetite, and rationality. A woman is capable of all of these. A cyst, of none.
But a blastocyst can only achieve personhood by inflicting its demands on a woman. Opposing the morning after pill is immoral because it denies the dignity of the woman involved. The cyst has no moral standing.
Nor does a foetus start as a person.
Now some folk have trouble with this; they need a firm, hard line drawn. They find the fact of the slow development of the person from the embryo disconcerting. They try to force a firm break into a situation where one does not exist.
That's their problem. A proper study of philosophy of language might lead to an improvement in their understanding of what is going on when we categorise stuff, and may hopefully dispel their need for certainty.
It is also important to recognise the usual mode of argument of the anti-abortionist. They start with the belief, gleaned from their invisible friends, that abortion is wrong, and then proceed to find arguments for their case.
They are not involved in a real open discussion of the ethical issues involved. Their minds are already decided. — Banno
It looks at philosophy from an odd angle. — fdrake
Assertion does NOT equal denotation.. "The cat" is a reference to something "in the world". — schopenhauer1
Extensionality. I understand that Frege spoke of the "course-of-values" for a variable - the list of values it might take. Tarski added the definition of truth as part of a metalanguage.Tarski? — schopenhauer1
Just to be sure, the reason I introduced talk of illocutionary force into the discussion was to give @J and others something by way of context against which they might develop whatever notion of force they see in Kimhi. I said explicitly that I would "go over my own understanding of the Fregean account and subsequent developments"....the muddle between force in thread and illocutionary forces... — fdrake
I think this is trivially true. — frank
Well, yes... that was kinda the point. The grass will be green in the case in which being green is satisfied by grass. It's a conditional, and hence "grass is green" is not asserted.The command doesn't contain a proposition. — frank
From my first postI develop propositional attitude by analyzing the context of utterance, — frank
First we should be clear about the nature of illocutionary force. Taking your example, "The grass is green", we can imagine various situations in which this utterance does quite different things. Imagine a meeting in which a landscape gardener is presenting their plan for the forecourt of a new build. One of those present is unclear as to which parts of the drawing are cement and which are lawn, and asks "The grass is green?". The designer replies, "Yes. The grass is green." There follows a conversation about how best to represent the lawn after which the manager gives the instruction "The grass is green!". Here we have the same sentence being used in three quite different ways - as a question, as a statement and as an instruction. The same sentence is being used with three differing illocutionary forces. — Banno