Haugeland is saying, I think, that a pattern exists when there is a set of rules that govern what something should do, and how we're supposed to respond when it does (or doesn't) do what it's supposed to do. We follow these rules by responding the way we're supposed to. — Pneumenon
There is one (possibly two) distinction that Haugeland makes and that you possibly missed, and another one that is merely implicit in Haugeland's discussion, and that he makes more explicitly in a subsequent paper: (
Truth and Rule Following).
The first (explicit) distinction to be made distinguishes two levels of patterns exemplified, respectively, in the constitutive standards that objects obey, and, secondly, in the objects themselves. For instance, to recognize something as a
bishop in the game of chess is to recognize it as the object that it is, and to recognize that bishops, in the general case, only move along diagonals, corresponds to the recognition of (or insistence on, or institution of) a higher level pattern -- i.e. the existence of a constitutive standard.
The merely implicit distinction alluded to above is that between two sorts or "rule-following". When the objects (lower level patterns) obey the objective standards, they -- the objects themselves -- are "behaving" in accordance with rules, we may say. But our recognizing them the be the objects that they are, on the one hand, and our recognizing that they accord with the constitutive standards, on the other hand, both depend on
our correctly exercising perceptual abilities, and hence,
our correctly following rules. (More comments on that later, in a followup post).
Those distinctions become apparent when (and make it possible that) the objects that we perceive appear not to behave in accordance with the constitutive standards of the domains that they belong to. Those distinctions are reflected in the different ways in which we can be mistaken and the different ways in which, accordingly, we attempt to correct those mistakes. One source of error consists in our having misidentified an object (e.g. we thought it was a bishop when, in actuality, it was a rook). Another source of error occurs when we are mistaken about some constitutive standard. The second case, however, splits into two sub-cases. When an object has been correctly identified (as a bishop, say) and then seems to have moved in a way that doesn't accord with a constitutive standard, this could be because we have
incorrectly judged it (in experience) to violate this constitutive standard, or we are
mistaken about this standard being empirically valid. (For the standard to be
empirically valid, here, isn't meant to be inconsistent with its being brought to bear to experience
a priori. For more on that, see my two posts above about synthetic
a priori propositions.)
This last distinction can be illustrated with numerous cases of apparent falsification of scientific theories when, historically, the theory was actually, and correctly, saved from falsification through the adjonction of an auxiliary hypothesis. Oftentimes, the
ad hoc (so called) hypothesis was later empirically confirmed independently. One classical example is that of Uranus that was seen not to precisely follow the orbit prescribed by Newton's laws of motion and gravitation. Inasmuch as Le Verrier was justified to postulate the existence of another planet that had precisely the mass and orbit of Neptune, in order to explain this anomaly, then the apparent discrepancy exemplified an error in our bringing to bear the constitutive standards of Newtonian mechanics to the behavior of Uranus. But it sometimes also turns out (as it later came to be the case with the anomaly in the orbit of Mercury) that the standards themselves have to be adjusted or relinquished.
This brings me back to your claim quoted above regarding what it is that the rules say regarding what
we are supposed to do when objects don't behave (or don't appear to behave) in the way they should. It is quite important to Haugeland that no rule dictates what it is that we should do in such circumstances. That is a matter of adjusting our
knowledge of (objects in) the world with our
understanding of (the constitutive standards of) the world. The adjustment is mutual, and, in some cases, the former may be at fault, and in other cases the latter may be at fault. But there is no general rule for deciding which. There only possibly could exist such a rule if empiricism were true, and the objects (lower level "patterns") could be singled out in experience independently of the standards that govern their behaviors. But Haugeland's insistance that the higher level patterns always are disclosed as
constitutive standards for the objects that can populate some empirical domain precludes the very possibility of such an independent identification of objects as correlates of "raw" experience.