"This immediately reminded me of Gettier 'problems' with the JTB account."
— creativesoul
There is a kind of connection to the argument here. Gettier cases are examples of epistemic luck -- you have a belief, it's true, it's got something that counts as justification, but the proposition believed to be true is true under a different interpretation than the one you intended, and our intuition that these are not examples of knowledge is because the justification you had fit the interpretation under which your sentence was false, not the one under which your sentence was true. (That's probably not all cases -- if it were, I would have just solved the Gettier problem.)
There's another sort of luck that's even easier to get at because there's no question of knowledge at all: that's when you're asked a question on an exam (or a game show, whatever) and you guess -- and your guess is right! If you're asked when the Battle of Hastings was, "1066" is the right answer whether you've ever even heard of the Battle of Hastings or not, because truth is not the same thing as knowledge.
(Not getting into the disjunction thing yet, as I have an argument that uses disjunction still under litigation.) — Srap Tasmaner
That was a couple months ago in the "'True' and 'Truth'""
thread, and might be worth revisiting now.
P ∨ Q has four possible models:
(1) P=0, Q=0
(2) P=1, Q=0
(3) P=0, Q=1
(4) P=1, Q=1
The gist of the above remarks was that, to take Case II as the example, Smith's justification relates to the models in which P is true (2 or 4), but it turns out P ∨ Q is in fact true under the third model, in which only Q is true.
@creativesoul is arguing that because all of Smith's beliefs are formed under one of the interpretations in which P is true, that his belief does not include or encompass the interpretations in which P is false.
Michael Dummett makes a distinction (when talking about assertion, as usual -- here it is Smith's acceptance that is at issue) that may be helpful here: there are the grounds upon which you make an assertion (which he calls its "justification"), and then there is what you are committed to by making the assertion. It is clear that Smith's belief that P is the grounds upon which he accepts that P ∨ Q, but by accepting that P ∨ Q he is committed to accepting all four possible models.
The commitment part is what we rely on when we judge lucky guesses to be correct. If, on the basis of nothing more than a hunch, you were to wager that the Battle of Hastings was fought in 1066, your bet would pay off. It is also possible to get the right answer for the wrong reasons, rather than for no reason.
This distinction shows up in our language use in many ways. If you believe you will be off work in time to meet me for a 7:00 movie, and you promise to, you have committed to being there and that commitment doesn't change because you end up working late and standing me up. You have broken your promise. Misunderstandings too often arise because a person might have one thing in mind, but the plain language of what they say admits of another interpretation, and if they misspoke, perhaps only an interpretation they did not intend. "That's not what I meant!" "But that's what you said!"
We do not, in general, take the grounds upon which an assertion is made as constraining the commitment made by that assertion. If we did, much about our language use would be different, but one thing in particular. To assert, or in Smith's case to accept, that a proposition is true is
generally to accept that it may be false. That's usually the point of making an assertion. You provide information to your audience by telling them something is the case that might not be. (I tell you I stopped at the store and got milk, because I might not have.)
The exception, of course, is statements that are necessarily true. To make an assertion in which you admit as possible only the models in which the statement is true is take the statement as true necessarily. (If this were generally the case, we would all of us believe whatever we believed to necessarily be the case.)
In this case, if Smith were to accept that "Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona"
only insofar as Jones owns a Ford, then he would be allowing no possibility that Jones does not own a Ford. He would be taking "Jones owns a Ford" to be a necessary truth.
Obviously, there is no support for this claim in the text.