• frank
    16k
    From the PI:

    "It amounts to this: that only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations; it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious’ (§281). :

    “But in a fairy tale a pot too can see and hear!” (Certainly; but it can also talk.)

    “But a fairy tale only invents what is not the case: it does not talk nonsense, does it?” — It’s not as simple as that. Is it untrue or nonsensical to say that a pot talks? Does one have a clear idea of the circumstances in which we’d say of a pot that it talked? (Even a nonsense poem is not nonsense in the same way as the babble of a baby.)"§282

    The question is: in the story in which the pot is conscious, is it that the author is telling falsehoods? Or is it nonsense?
  • Paine
    2.5k

    I took the point of the observation to be that we can deliberately use what is not experienced (for the most part) to imagine a scene that is neither false nor meaningless.

    The sword cuts in two ways. Separating truth from falsehood belongs to some activities but not to others. There is something about this constraint that invites other ways of making sense.
  • frank
    16k
    I took the point of the observation to be that we can deliberately use what is not experienced (for the most part) to imagine a scene that is neither false nor meaningless.

    The sword cuts in two ways. Separating truth from falsehood belongs to some activities but not to others. There is something about this constraint that invites other ways of making sense.
    Paine

    :up:
    There are two primary ways to interpret the PI:

    1. Pyrrhonism: that Witt believed that all philosophy is nonsense because it can't be about anything of this world.
    2. Non-pyrrhonism: that Witt believed that philosophy can point out the cases where philosophers fall into nonsense, but that he was also offering positive philosophical views (which often have to be reconstructed from the text).

    Then there's the third way: Witt wanted to abandon philosophy because he knew that it's all nonsense, but he couldn't stop, so the PI is confusing because he was stuck in this struggle when he wrote it.

    According to this scheme, there are three ways to take the private language argument:

    1. That he believed the question is nonsense.
    2. That he believed it is truly impossible to have a private language.
    3. That the argument carries the dynamic tension of the struggle all philosophers face when they realize that philosophy has no answers, but we can't stop looking for them.

    I took the point of the observation to be that we can deliberately use what is not experienced (for the most part) to imagine a scene that is neither false nor meaningless.Paine

    This is what we tell ourselves when we set out again asking philosophical questions, right?

    The sword cuts in two ways. Separating truth from falsehood belongs to some activities but not to others. There is something about this constraint that invites other ways of making sense.Paine

    What are the other ways of making sense?
  • fdrake
    6.7k
    The question is: in the story in which the pot is conscious, is it that the author is telling falsehoods? Or is it nonsense?frank

    You can unask the question. The author is not telling falsehoods about the pot in the story, if the author were speaking about a talking pot, in the same manner, out in the street, it could be falsehood or nonsense. There won't be a context independent criterion for falsehood, truth, sense or nonsense. Variations in the rules binding contexts of expression undermines forming a univocal criterion for making sense. "Is the author telling falsehoods?" "Or is it nonsense?", to those questions you must ask: "in what game?".

    §281 and §282 are part of a discussion regarding sensation language. The pot's sensations, and the child's game involving them, are analogies to provide insight on the boundaries of senseful sensation language. Specifically how the ascription of sensations should be understood in normal contexts, so that we can understand how we might err in the uncritical use of that language in other contexts. So the pot story is a signpost that says: "Look! Here's somewhere outside the normal use of sensation ascription language! How could this work?"

    The broader context of the entire discussion regards what conditions need to be in place for sensation ascribing phrases to make sense. Like "I'm in pain". And what illusions paying insufficient attention to those conditions creates. Like the illusion that when someone says "I'm in pain", they're evidencing the presence of a pain entity or process somehow "inside themselves".
  • Janus
    16.5k
    "It amounts to this: that only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations; it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious’ (§281). :frank

    How very anthropocentric!

    As to whether a story about a talking pot is nonsense, it all depends on what is meant by 'nonsense'. If I told someone "I saw a talking pot" it would not be out of the ordinary for them to say "don't talk nonsense".

    But then imagining seeing something that logically. even if not actually, could be a manifest phenomenon would not be talking outside the possible context of sense; that is of the senses, so in that sense it is not nonsense.

    If I said "I saw God" then that might be thought to be outside the possible context of sense, so in that sense saying I saw God would be truly nonsense.
  • Paine
    2.5k
    1. Pyrrhonism: that Witt believed that all philosophy is nonsense because it can't be about anything of this world.frank

    This view is odd since the Tractatus keeps referring to "what is the case." The Philosophical Investigations did not abandon this idea but accepted that more consideration was needed than what he included in his initial assertion.

    Witt wanted to abandon philosophy because he knew that it's all nonsense, but he couldn't stop, so the PI is confusing because he was stuck in this struggle when he wrote it.frank

    There is an effort there to move beyond certain problems, or at a minimum, to ask how we are stuck with particular articulations. But that approach is different from blowing them off as a class of accounts. And thus all the wondering about what distinguishes 'universals' from similarity. If the issue was not important, why draw so much attention to it?
  • frank
    16k
    This view is odd since the Tractatus keeps referring to "what is the case."Paine

    One interpretation of the Tractatus is that it concludes that we can only talk about what is the case in the world in which we find ourselves. Statements about the world itself are beyond the limits of language. Some say the PI should be understood in that light.

    By the way, I'm mainly trying to understand how Kripke's take on the private language argument fits into the larger zodiac of interpretations. To that end I'm collecting a flow chart of the different avenues. I'm not really looking for a deep dive on any particular one, although I'm always interested in people explaining what a particular philosopher meant to them personally.
  • Paine
    2.5k
    I don't know what to make of this place where you are collecting evidence for a particular purpose.
  • frank
    16k
    I don't know what to make of this place where you are collecting evidence for a particular purpose.Paine

    I'm not collecting evidence for a particular purpose.
  • Paine
    2.5k
    To that end I'm collecting a flow chart of the different avenues. I'm not really looking for a deep dive on any particular onefrank
  • frank
    16k
    I'm mainly trying to understand how Kripke's take on the private language argument fits into the larger zodiac of interpretations.frank

    :brow:
  • Paine
    2.5k

    Okay. How would you put that view in your own words?
  • frank
    16k
    Okay. How would you put that view in your own words?Paine

    Kripke's view? He says the private language argument indicates that there is no rule following. There was no rule you followed. There is no rule now.

    Open scalp. Brain explodes.
  • Paine
    2.5k
    So, how to measure that against all the observations that games were played within rules that Wittgenstein described?
  • frank
    16k


    It's in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language by Kripke.
  • Paine
    2.5k
    Yes, I have read it. I was thinking you could represent the argument since it is at the bottom of your OP.
  • frank
    16k
    Yes, I have read it.Paine

    Great. What did you think of it?
  • Paine
    2.5k

    I will let you go first.
  • frank
    16k
    I will let you go first.Paine

    I already did. It's in my recent thread: Kripke's skeptical challenge. I won't be responding further.
  • Paine
    2.5k

    Understood.
  • Banno
    25.3k
    Might be best to keep Kripkenstien to his own thread.

    Consider:
    464. What I want to teach is: to pass from unobvious nonsense to obvious nonsense.

    And around §500, as well as §522ff.

    When we muse about talking pots, we are playing a game that is somewhat different to the game we play when talking about a person who is mute. But what counts as false and what counts as nonsense will depend on the game being played.

    So what is the outcome if you say that talking pots are nonsense, as opposed to saying that it is false? It depends on how the games are set up.

    That might be what and said.
  • Caldwell
    1.3k
    I took the point of the observation to be that we can deliberately use what is not experienced (for the most part) to imagine a scene that is neither false nor meaningless.

    The sword cuts in two ways. Separating truth from falsehood belongs to some activities but not to others. There is something about this constraint that invites other ways of making sense.
    Paine
    Succinct. The fairy tale is a context that we all understand to be something that is fantastic and imaginative. So within this context, we can't assign lies or nonsense -- or at least, it's not an appropriate critique.
  • frank
    16k
    But what counts as false and what counts as nonsense will depend on the game being played.

    So what is the outcome if you say that talking pots are nonsense, as opposed to saying that it is false? It depends on how the games are set up.
    Banno

    That's cool. There's another way to interpret it though.

    Along these lines, two overlapping distinctions concerning how to read Philosophical Investigations have arisen: the resolute–substantial distinction, and the Pyrrhonian–non-Pyrrhonian distinction. In general, the resolute and Pyrrhonian readings make Wittgenstein out to be an anti-philosopher, one who is not offering positive philosophical theses to replace false ones; rather, his goal is to show the nonsensical nature of traditional philosophical theorizing. It is this goal that is partly responsible for the unique style of Philosophical Investigations (its dialogical and, at least at times, anti-dogmatic, therapeutic character). On the substantial and non-Pyrrhonian readings, Wittgenstein is not only presenting a method for exposing the errors of traditional philosophers, but also showing how philosophy should rightly be done and thereby offering positive philosophical views, views which must often be inferred or reconstructed from an elusive text.

    There is neither a single resolute/Pyrrhonian nor a single substantial/non-Pyrrhonian reading of Wittgenstein. Moreover, there is an important difference between the resolute–substantial and Pyrrhonian–non-Pyrrhonian distinctions. The former distinction arises from a continuing debate on how to read Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, both on its own and in relation to Philosophical Investigations (see, e.g., Conant 2004 and Mulhall 2007), and is associated with the so-called New Wittgensteinians (see, e.g., Crary and Read 2000). The Pyrrhonian and non-Pyrrhonian discussion is to be found, for example, in Fogelin (1994), Sluga (2004), and Stern (2004, 2007), and concerns the ways in which Wittgenstein might be considered as writing in the tradition of the ancient Pyrrhonian sceptics, who were philosophically sceptical about the very possibility of philosophy (see Fogelin 1994, pp. 3ff and 205ff). These distinctions cut across the distinction between Orthodox and Kripkean non-orthodox readings of the text: both Orthodox and Kripkean non-orthodox interpreters have tended to offer substantial or non-Pyrrhonian readings of Wittgenstein—though the line may not always be clear and some (e.g., Hacker, 1990) move from a resolute/Pyrrhonian to a substantial/non-Pyrrhonian reading without remarking the fact.

    Some (Fogelin, Stern, and Mulhall, for example) have come to question whether it makes sense to suppose that either one or the other, resolute/Pyrrhonian or substantial/non-Pyrrhonian, must be the correct way to read Wittgenstein. Fogelin and Stern see the tension in the text of Philosophical Investigations as the expression of a tension, indeed a struggle, within its author, between his wanting to uncover the ‘disguised nonsense’ of philosophical theses and his being tempted and drawn into still other philosophical positions on the nature of language, reference, private experience, and philosophy itself.
    SEP

    The interpretation you gave is non-Pyrrhonian, that is, you're saying Wittgenstein was offering a philosophical approach for all the follow. The alternative interpretations would be

    1. Pyrrhonian, which would take this passage as pointing to why all philosophy is nonsense: talk of a conscious pot is beyond the limits of language because there's no context for such talk. This means the words of the story are pulled out of regular language use.

    2. It could be that this passage highlights a struggle in Wittgenstein that lies behind PI. When he asks whether it's nonsense or false, he's actually asking about the PI itself. Of all the ways to interpret that passage, this is the most mind-blowing.

    Might be best to keep Kripkenstien to his own thread.Banno

    I was just explaining why I'm not looking for immersion in any particular method of interpretation. Kripke's interpretive anchor was the community view, but he draws some astounding conclusions out of it. I was just trying to fit Kripke into the rest of the history of Wittgenstein interpretation. Thanks for helping me flesh it out!
  • Banno
    25.3k
    Yeah, sure. As time goes on the interpretations of Witti become increasingly distorted. I think the Pyrrhonian reading misses much of what he had to say. Those who worked with him do not adopt it.
  • frank
    16k
    Yeah, sure. As time goes on the interpretations of Witti become increasingly distorted. I think the Pyrrhonian reading misses much of what he had to say. Those who worked with him do not adopt it.Banno

    There aren't any interpretations that aren't controversial though. It's interesting that in this case you emphasize age as the guide. You usually poo poo older philosophy and favor newer.
  • Banno
    25.3k
    You usually poo poo older philosophy and favor newer.frank
    Pretty much.

    My first stop would be Anthony Kenny, mostly because it is approachable and complete. Then to Anscombe and Malcolm for corrections. Of the newer stuff Monk seems to have the best balance. The rest is such a vast literature that one will quickly become lost.

    So roughly, nonsense is the stuff that happens between language games, or when terms from one are inexplicably applied to another, or when grammar is stretched beyond recognition.
  • frank
    16k
    So roughly, nonsense is the stuff that happens between language games, or when terms from one are inexplicably applied to another, or when grammar is stretched beyond recognition.Banno

    And that makes sense. In fact, it makes more sense than the PI itself. Non-Pyrrhonian interpretations fill in blanks with ideas that aren't there explicitly.
  • Banno
    25.3k
    Ok, then in contrast, true and false are moves within some language games.

    And there's the answer to your puzzle.
  • frank
    16k
    Ok, then in contrast, true and false are moves within some language games.Banno

    Exactly!

    The looming issue is this: when the ancient Greeks wondered whether the world is made of fire or water, were they engaged in a language game? Or were they beyond the limits of language? It appears that the context for their discussion is somewhere outside the world, outside of time, in short, outside of everything. So was it nonsense?

    And with this question in mind, we come back to PI itself. What of the concept of a language game? What's the context for this discussion? Where are we when we have a vantage point on language use? Is it nonsense?
  • Banno
    25.3k
    Some folk seem to think language games involve only language. They don't. Have a look at the example in §1. The language game is an activity involving matching apples with swatches and numbers, a physical activity in the world. §2 involves the movement of blocks, pillars and slabs. Language games are embedded in the world.

    Language games are about doing things. We get more done by talking of chemicals rather than fire and water. And from the language game of chemistry, wood is not solidified fire. That'd be false.

    But the articulation between language games is a topic of some considerable complexity. It's all that incommensurability stuff and the very idea of a conceptual scheme I keep ranting on about. IS that where you are headed with your thread?
  • frank
    16k
    But the articulation between language games is a topic of some considerable complexity. It's all that incommensurability stuff and the very idea of a conceptual scheme I keep ranting on about. IS that where you are headed with your thread?Banno

    Not really. I was just pondering Kripke's skeptical challenge. It's had me reaching around to get my bearings. :razz: Thanks for your help!
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.