• bert1
    2.1k
    I'm not sure what it would mean for an inductive argument to be sound. Strong or weak, yes. Soundness and validity are properties of deductive arguments.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    You want me to argue with you, but you don't understand basic logic. Moreover, you don't take the time to carefully read the thread or do basic research. Ya, right, "I'm projecting."
  • 180 Proof
    16k
    Ya, right, "I'm projecting."Sam26
    :up:

    Yes, I forgot ...
  • Philosophim
    3k
    Your critique of my work reflects a surprisingly limited and elitist perspective on philosophySam26

    No, just your work.

    You say philosophy is solely “the love of wisdom” built on logic, dismissing belief-based arguments as mere fiction or faith. That’s not just a misreading of my project, it’s a fundamental misunderstanding of philosophy itselfSam26

    No, I'm pretty sure that's actual philosophy. Philosophy is not just an opinion. Its a discussion of logical foundations. You do not have logical foundations.

    First, your assertion that arguing from belief isn’t philosophy, likening my NDE work to debating Gandalf’s height, is absurdly reductive.Sam26

    No, arguing merely from belief is not philosophy. That's religion. And no, I am not likening all of your work to Gandalf's height, I'm noting that many of your core premises to NDEs being viable outside of people experiencing them is illogical. You believing in something strongly does not make it true. You have to really be logical and rational to do philosophy. You are dismissing all the science and tests on NDEs that demonstrate the first person experiences of testimony do not align with the objective reality of what occurred. You are trying to wrap your belief system in philosophy because science will not legitimize it. Philosophy will not either.

    Philosophy isn’t an ivory-tower club for logic-chopping purists; it’s the systematic exploration of life’s big questions, engaged by everyone from Socrates to the average person pursuing meaning in a coffee shop.Sam26

    Correct. But all of them use logic and reason.

    As I argue in my book, epistemology, a core branch, is precisely about how we form and justify beliefs, whether about black holes, morality, or NDEs.Sam26

    No, epistemology is the study of knowledge. Beliefs are studied, but only for the purpose of figuring out what knowledge is.

    NDE testimonies involve real people reporting verifiable experiences, like accurate surgical details during flatlined EEGs, documented in peer-reviewed studies (e.g., 2024 ScienceDirect on consciousness continuity)Sam26

    Now that's something we can work with. I couldn't find the article on searching, mind linking it?

    You sneer that my work is “faith” or “religion,” not philosophy, because I explore consciousness survival.Sam26

    Nope. I'm noting you're dismissing serious flaws that have already been pointed out and committing logical fallacies. Your topic is not the issue. If you provided reasonable evidence and arguments for the existence of consciousness outside of brain death, that would be cool! An argument from emotion or desire for it to be true is not a rational argument.

    Philosophy has always tackled the speculative: Leibniz on possible worlds, Kant on noumena, even Chalmers on the hard problem of consciousness.Sam26

    Yes, and they all used logic. And when Liebniz' monads had flaws due to further scientific discovery, no one considered them viable anymore. If you are going to talk about a subject that is in the scientific realm, you better be able to scientifically back it if you are going to come up with some philosophy about it.

    Dismissing this as non-philosophical because it’s not yet “proven” ignores how philosophy engages open questions.Sam26

    No I'm dismissing it because you're ignoring the science that shows NDEs can be simulated outside of near death experiences, and to the date that I had checked in 2023-24, no scientific experiment has ever resulted in reported NDEs accurately reporting on things in the room that they could not personally sense and see with their body.

    My book and this thread confront counterpoints head-on.Sam26

    No you don't. You ran on my last serious post to you.

    Finally, your patronizing advice to “apply my passion” elsewhere, charity, neuroscience, teaching kids, reveals your contempt for philosophical inquiry into the profound.Sam26

    Its personal life advice. Take it as patronizing or not if you want. Listen to it if you want or not. But I see no evidence of you having the capability to meet the challenges of this thread, let alone the challenges of experts in this field.

    A 2024 Taylor & Francis review shows NDEs’ cross-cultural consistency, suggesting a universal phenomenon worth exploring.Sam26

    This adds nothing. Everyone already know NDEs are real and have a wide classificaiton of simiularities on average, but also a significant minority of differences. We explored that back then in one of your citations if you remember.

    If you think philosophy should only chase “real issues,” you’re not loving wisdom; you’re stifling it.Sam26

    No, I'm saying you need to address the issues in science. You're trying to hide your inability to do so in philosophy with the idea that opinions or belief systems are valid. They are not. They are religion and faith. I see no evidence of good science or philosophy here. Just a person obsessed.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    "Estimated 400-800 million cases" how and by whom?180 Proof

    The 1992 Gallup poll estimated that 5% of Americans had experienced NDEs, suggesting 13-15 million cases in the United States alone. A 2024 Scientific American review, citing studies like Kondziella et al. (2019) across 35 countries, estimates 5-10% global prevalence in the general population, representing potentially 400-800 million cases worldwide amid a 2025 world population of approximately 8.1 billion.
  • boundless
    555
    No two experiences, whether NDEs or everyday perceptions, are ever exactly identical, even among people sharing the same event in the same moment. Even witnesses at a car accident: Their accounts vary based on vantage point, attention, emotions, and memory, yet the core facts often align.Sam26

    Yes, I agree. I was questioning if with NDEs we get the same degree of agreement that we can, confidently, assume that people witness the same 'experience'. But you are right, we can't expect to have perfect agreements between reports in any case.

    This subjectivity is a hallmark of human consciousness, and it applies powerfully to NDEs. Research consistently shows that while NDEs share striking similarities (suggesting a possible universal mechanism), individual differences go beyond cultural backgrounds, influenced by personal psychology, expectations, neurobiology, and worldviews.Sam26

    Can all the differences in the actual experiences be explained by the differences among the subjects?

    A 2024 Taylor & Francis review of NDEs across cultures and history found high similarity in features like out-of-body experiences (OBEs), encounters with light or beings, life reviews, and feelings of peace, appearing in approximately 60-80% of global reports. These similarities hold even when controlling for cultural expectations (e.g., Westerners might see Jesus, while Easterners describe Yama, but the "being of light" archetype persists). This is not unusual; it happens in our everyday experiences, too.Sam26

    Thanks for the reference, I'll try to check it.

    To make an example to clarify my point... Let's say that Alice has a peaceful NDE where she has a life review, encounters some luminous spirits in a meadow which seems 'more real than real' and, then, encounters a 'supreme being of light'. The, Bob also reports a peaceful NDE where he gets the life review, encounters some spirits in a meadow that also he describes as 'more real than real' and, then, encounters a 'supreme being of light'. When, however, questioned further, Alice says that her review was also in the perspective of other people but this isn't true in the case of Bob. Also, let's say that you find out differences in the characteristics of the 'meadows' they 'saw'.

    To me, even if we assume that they visited a 'realm' of sorts, they clearly had 'visited' different 'places'. It's not just that they identified the 'deity' according to their background but they had different experiences. So, I would not say that they are like two witnesses of a car accident or like two people that give an account of their journey to the same city (in the same time period).

    Given these problems, can we consider the testimonies as reliable data to arrive, inductively, at some conclusions about, say, the presence or absence of an immortal soul, the characterstics of the afterlife and so on?

    Note that I do not come from an 'a priori skepticism' or anything like that. But generally, I see an agreement about the themes (which of course might well be evidence of something important) but I have doubts that the 'harmonization' of these accounts gives a reliable 'theory' about 'how the afterlife looks like'.
  • DifferentiatingEgg
    695
    I mean, there's testimony evidence that Bigfoot is real. *shrug* I'll go with Hume's knock on testimony—necessarily the weakest form. So unless you're trying to convince Christians, who already believe that anyways, you're going to have an up a steep mountain fight on your hands.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    The following is a summary of some of what I cover in my book, which by the way is about 95% complete. I'm looking at NDEs from an epistemological standpoint, which hasn't been done in such a robust way.

    What do you think of the title: 'The Threshold of Consciousness: Insights from Near-Death Testimonies'

    I'll also add chapter 4, which covers the main criticisms of my argument, in my next post. The eBook is about 120 pages. I'll probably be selling it on Amazon for about $4.99.

    Epistemology of Testimonial Evidence in NDE Inquiry

    The epistemology of testimonial evidence, as developed in The Threshold of Consciousness: Insights from Near-Death Testimonies, provides a rigorous framework for evaluating near-death experience (NDE) accounts as a legitimate source of knowledge about consciousness survival. Grounded in philosophical inquiry, this approach treats testimony as a primary knowledge path, comparable to its use in history, law, and science. With approximately 200-300 million NDE accounts worldwide, the framework underscores testimony's everyday importance and foundational role in human knowledge, revealing profound insights into consciousness and reality.

    Defining Knowledge and Testimony

    Knowledge is defined as justified true belief, requiring a proposition to be true, believed, and supported by robust evidence (Chapter 2). A fourth dimension, linguistic competence, ensures conceptual understanding through proper word use, critical for interpreting NDE reports. Testimony, one of five knowledge paths (alongside logic, sensory experience, linguistic training, pure logic), involves relying on others’ accounts to access truths beyond direct observation, such as historical events or scientific findings. In NDE research, testimony is central, as firsthand accounts (e.g., out-of-body perceptions, life reviews) provide the primary data for evaluating consciousness survival.

    Testimony's Importance in Daily Life

    Testimony permeates everyday knowledge, forming the foundation for much of what we accept as true. Consider facts like your birth date, Antarctica's existence, or DNA's role in genetics—you've likely never verified these independently, yet doubting them would be unreasonable. We rely on historians for ancient Rome's events, physicists for quantum mechanics, and doctors for internal bodily functions, none directly observable. Without testimony, our understanding of science, history, art, and morality would be severely limited, confined to personal experience. In NDE evaluation, this everyday reliance on testimony highlights its critical role, as millions of accounts offer insights into consciousness that deserve the same scrutiny as legal or historical reports.

    Testimony's Foundational Role in Knowledge

    Testimony is indispensable to knowledge itself, enabling access to vast information beyond individual capacity. In science, researchers trust colleagues' experimental reports; in law, juries rely on witnesses; in history, scholars depend on ancient accounts. This social dimension makes testimony a democratic tool, allowing anyone to assess credibility. For NDEs, with 200-300 million reports, testimony provides a robust dataset, evaluated through five criteria: volume (sheer number strengthens credibility), variety (diverse perspectives reduce bias), consistency (majority convergence on core features like radiant light), corroboration (independent verification, e.g., medical staff confirming details), and firsthand accounts (direct reports over hearsay, with trustworthiness assessed). These criteria, drawn from legal and historical practices, transform anecdotes into evidence, supporting conclusions about consciousness survival.

    Subjective vs. Objective Elements

    NDE testimony includes objective elements (verifiable details like surgical procedures) and subjective elements (e.g., feelings of love, encounters with deceased relatives). Corroborated objective elements, such as a child's verified ER observations, lend credibility to subjective reports, suggesting genuine experiences. Cultural variations affect interpretation (e.g., light as Jesus or ancestors), but core phenomena remain consistent, indicating universal features of consciousness.

    Implications

    This epistemology establishes NDE testimony as a valid knowledge source, supporting probable consciousness survival and challenging paradigms. It emphasizes testimony's daily importance—without it, knowledge would be isolated—and its foundational role in extending human understanding, fostering open inquiry into consciousness and existence.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    The following is chapter 4, but I'll still be tweaking it a bit before I release the book, probably in October. Chapter 4 addresses common criticisms of my argument given in Chapter 3. The chapter is in two parts (next two posts).

    Part 1 of Chapter 4

    Chapter 4: Addressing Counter-Arguments

    Any argument challenging fundamental assumptions about consciousness and survival will inevitably face objections. The systematic evaluation of NDEs that we've conducted represents precisely such a challenge to materialist orthodoxy. Rather than dismissing these objections, rigorous inquiry demands that we examine them carefully and respond with the same methodological standards we've applied to the testimonial evidence itself. The counter-arguments against NDE testimony generally fall into several categories: neurological explanations that attribute the experiences to brain chemistry or oxygen deprivation; methodological objections that question the reliability of testimonial evidence; cultural conditioning arguments that explain NDE consistency through shared beliefs rather than shared reality; and timing arguments that suggest the experiences occur during recovery rather than during clinical death. Each objection deserves careful analysis. Some raise legitimate methodological concerns that can strengthen our evaluation criteria. Others reveal unexamined philosophical assumptions that deserve scrutiny. Still others, when examined closely, actually support rather than undermine the case for veridical perception during clinical death. This chapter applies the same systematic approach we've used throughout: distinguishing strong objections from weak ones, examining the evidence that supports or refutes each challenge, and maintaining appropriate intellectual humility about what our conclusions can and cannot establish. The goal is not to dismiss legitimate concerns but to determine whether they provide sufficient grounds for rejecting the testimonial evidence we've examined.

    Section 1: The Hallucination Hypothesis

    Perhaps the most common dismissal of near-death experience claims they represent elaborate hallucinations produced by dying brain chemistry, oxygen deprivation, or the release of endorphins or DMT. This explanation appears frequently in popular scientific literature and provides a seemingly straightforward way to account for NDE reports without challenging materialist assumptions about consciousness.

    The hallucination hypothesis faces several serious problems when examined systematically. First, we must be clear about what hallucinations are. By definition, hallucinations are sensory perceptions that occur without external stimulus, experiences that exist purely within an individual's mind rather than corresponding to objective reality. Hallucinations are characteristically private, subjective experiences that cannot be corroborated by others present during the same events.
    This definitional point proves crucial because it reveals why the hallucination explanation fails to account for the most significant feature of many NDE reports: their objective corroboration by independent witnesses. When NDErs report seeing and hearing specific events during their out-of-body experiences, conversations among medical staff, procedures being performed, and people entering or leaving the room, these claims can be verified or falsified by others who were present.

    Consider Pam Reynolds' case from Chapter 1. During her standstill surgery, she reported observing the unusual bone saw ("like an electric toothbrush"), hearing the female surgeon's comment about her arteries being too small, and witnessing the decision to access her femoral artery from the left side. These observations were subsequently confirmed by the surgical team. Dr. Robert Spetzler, her neurosurgeon, acknowledged his bewilderment: "I don't have an explanation for it. I don't know how it's possible for her to quote the conversation, see the instruments, these are things she shouldn't have been able to experience."

    If Reynolds were hallucinating, we would not expect such precise correspondence between her subjective experience and objective events witnessed by others. Hallucinations, by their very nature, do not provide accurate information about external reality. The fact that NDErs consistently report verifiable details about events occurring during their unconsciousness suggests we're dealing with perception rather than hallucination.

    The consistency problem provides another challenge to the hallucination hypothesis. If NDEs were simply products of individual brain chemistry, we would expect significant variation in their content based on personal psychology, medical history, and specific neurochemical conditions. Instead, research reveals remarkable consistency across different populations, medical circumstances, and cultural contexts.

    Dr. Bruce Greyson's NDE Scale, used in academic studies worldwide, identifies consistent elements that appear across thousands of cases: out-of-body experiences with accurate environmental perception, movement through tunnels toward light, encounters with deceased relatives, life reviews, and profound feelings of peace and love. This consistency extends across age groups (including young children with no mature concepts of death), religious backgrounds (including committed atheists), and cultural contexts (including societies with no prior exposure to Western NDE literature).
    Random hallucinations produced by dying brain chemistry should generate random content. The fact that we find structured, consistent experiences across diverse populations suggests encounters with phenomena that transcend individual brain states.

    The phenomenology of NDEs also distinguishes them from typical hallucinations. NDErs consistently report that their experiences felt "more real than real," hyperreal in ways that distinguish them from dreams, drug-induced states, or psychiatric hallucinations. This enhanced sense of reality persists even when NDErs are familiar with altered states of consciousness and can differentiate between various non-ordinary experiences.

    Dr. Eben Alexander, a neuroscientist who experienced an NDE during severe bacterial meningitis, noted that his experience differed qualitatively from any altered state he had studied or experienced: "The level of detail, the clarity, the vividness, it was beyond anything I had encountered in dreams or drug-induced states. It had a quality of absolute reality that was unmistakable."

    Perhaps most significantly, the hallucination hypothesis cannot account for veridical perception during periods of documented unconsciousness. Hallucinations do not provide accurate information about distant events, yet NDErs sometimes report observations of activities occurring in other parts of hospitals, conversations among family members miles away, or encounters with deceased individuals whose deaths they couldn't have known about through normal means.

    The University of Virginia's study of NDEs found that 22% of experiencers met people during their NDEs whose deaths they couldn't have known about beforehand, information that was only verified after resuscitation. Such cases are incompatible with the hallucination hypothesis, which predicts that subjective experiences should reflect only information already known by the NDErs.


    Section 2: Brain-Based Explanations and the Correlation-Causation Problem

    More sophisticated objections acknowledge that NDEs represent genuine experiences but argue they can be explained through brain-based mechanisms without requiring consciousness to survive bodily death. These explanations typically invoke correlations between brain states and conscious experiences, arguing that consciousness must be produced by brain activity since changes in the brain consistently affect mental states.

    This argument involves a common logical confusion: mistaking correlation for causation. The fact that brain states correlate with conscious experiences doesn't prove that brains generate consciousness any more than correlations between radio components and received programming prove that radios generate the signals they receive.

    Consider this analogy carefully. When we examine a radio, we find consistent correlations between its components and the programs we hear. Damage the antenna, and reception suffers. Adjust the tuner, and different stations become available. Replace the speaker, and the audio quality changes. These correlations are real and predictable, yet no one concludes that radios generate the electromagnetic signals they receive.

    Similarly, correlations between brain states and conscious experiences might indicate that brains function as receivers or reducers of consciousness rather than generators. This possibility becomes particularly relevant when we examine cases where enhanced consciousness is reported during periods of reduced brain function. The "dying brain" explanation faces a crucial empirical problem: NDEs often involve enhanced rather than diminished consciousness precisely when brain function is most compromised. If consciousness were simply a product of brain activity, we would expect mental clarity to decrease as brain function deteriorates. Instead, NDErs consistently report expanded awareness, enhanced sensory perception, and improved cognitive function during periods when their brains are shutting down.

    Pam Reynolds' case again proves instructive. During her standstill procedure, her brain was cooled to 60°F, her heart was stopped, and EEG monitoring showed no brain activity. Yet she reported the most vivid, detailed conscious experience of her life. Similarly, patients during cardiac arrest, when brain function ceases within seconds, often report elaborate, coherent experiences that seem impossible given their neurological state.

    Dr. Eben Alexander's case provides another compelling example. During his week-long coma from bacterial meningitis, his neocortex was essentially non-functional, "mush," as he described it based on his brain scans. According to materialist theories, this should have eliminated higher-order consciousness. Instead, Alexander reported the most profound conscious experience of his life, complete with detailed memories that persisted after recovery.

    The timing problem poses another challenge for brain-based explanations. Critics sometimes suggest that NDE memories form during brief moments of recovered brain function, either just before clinical death or during resuscitation. This explanation faces several difficulties.
    First, many NDErs provide specific temporal markers for their experiences, describing events that occurred at particular times during their unconsciousness. When these reports are compared with medical records, witness testimony, and electronic monitoring, they often correspond to periods of documented brain inactivity.

    Dr. Michael Sabom's research compared NDE patients' reports about their resuscitation procedures with the reports of control groups who had not experienced NDEs. When non-NDE patients were asked to imagine what their resuscitation might have looked like, they made significant errors about medical procedures, equipment, and timing. NDE patients, by contrast, provided accurate accounts of actual procedures performed during their unconsciousness.

    The enhanced consciousness reported during NDEs also challenges reductive explanations. NDErs don't simply report maintaining normal awareness during clinical death; they describe expanded sensory perception, enhanced cognitive function, and access to information unavailable through ordinary consciousness. The blind report detailed visual experiences. The deaf describe complex auditory phenomena. Individuals with lifelong sensory limitations suddenly have access to perceptual modalities they've never experienced.

    These reports suggest that whatever consciousness is, it transcends the limitations typically imposed by brain function and sensory organs. Rather than consciousness being produced by neural activity, the evidence points toward the brain's functioning as filters or reducers that normally constrain a more fundamental conscious capacity.

    Section 3: The Scientism Problem

    A particularly common objection dismisses NDE testimony as "unscientific" and therefore inadmissible as evidence. This objection reflects a philosophical position known as scientism, the belief that scientific methods provide the only legitimate path to knowledge. While this position appears methodologically rigorous, it involves several problematic assumptions that deserve careful examination. The scientism objection typically proceeds as follows: science has not confirmed consciousness survival, laboratory studies cannot reproduce NDEs under controlled conditions, and testimonial evidence doesn't meet scientific standards for reliability. Therefore, we should dismiss NDE reports as irrelevant to serious inquiry about consciousness and survival. Each element of this argument contains questionable assumptions. First, the demand for scientific confirmation assumes that scientific methods are appropriate for investigating all phenomena. While science excels at studying repeatable, measurable events under controlled conditions, consciousness itself presents the "hard problem" that has resisted scientific solution for decades. We don't understand how subjective experience emerges from objective neural processes, how qualia relate to brain states, or why there's "something it's like" to be conscious rather than nothing at all. If science cannot yet explain ordinary consciousness, why should we expect it to provide definitive answers about consciousness survival? The scientism objection puts the cart before the horse, demanding scientific solutions to problems that may require preliminary philosophical analysis before scientific methods can be effectively applied. Dr. Neil deGrasse Tyson's dismissal of NDE testimony illustrates this confusion. In response to questions about near-death experiences, Tyson argued that testimonial evidence represents "one of the weakest ways of gathering evidence" and suggested that relying on witness testimony should make us suspicious of our legal system. He also claimed that "your senses are some of the worst data-taking devices that exist."

    These comments highlight a key oversight in how knowledge is acquired. Science itself depends extensively on testimonial evidence. When Tyson accepts colleagues' reports about astronomical observations, he's relying on testimony. When he reads peer-reviewed papers describing experiments he hasn't personally conducted, he's trusting testimonial accounts. The entire scientific enterprise rests on testimonial evidence about experimental results, observational data, and theoretical conclusions.
    Moreover, Tyson's dismissal of sensory experience as unreliable undermines the foundation of scientific observation. How do we gather data in scientific experiments if not through our senses? When astronomers observe distant galaxies, when biologists examine cellular structures, and when physicists read instrument displays, all involve sensory experience. The suggestion that our senses are "the worst data-taking devices" would collapse the empirical foundation of science itself.

    The real issue isn't whether testimonial evidence and sensory experience are reliable; they must be, or both science and everyday knowledge would be impossible. The issue is developing appropriate criteria for distinguishing reliable from unreliable testimony, which is exactly what our five-criterion framework accomplishes.

    The selective application of heightened evidential standards reveals the ideological rather than methodological character of many scientism-based objections. Materialists routinely accept testimonial evidence about brain scans, experimental results, and theoretical conclusions while demanding impossible standards for testimonial evidence about consciousness. They don't require laboratory reproduction of historical events before accepting historical testimony, nor do they dismiss archaeological conclusions because ancient civilizations can't be studied under controlled conditions.
    This double standard becomes particularly apparent when examining specific cases. When Dr. Eben Alexander reports his NDE, critics demand extraordinary evidence because his claims challenge materialist assumptions. When the same Dr. Alexander reports his interpretation of brain scans or neurological assessments in his professional capacity, those same critics accept his testimony as a reliable expert witness.

    The scientism objection also misunderstands the relationship between scientific and philosophical inquiry. Science and philosophy represent complementary rather than competing approaches to understanding reality. Science excels at investigating measurable, repeatable phenomena; philosophy provides tools for analyzing concepts, examining assumptions, and evaluating arguments based on various types of evidence.

    Questions about consciousness and survival involve both empirical and conceptual elements that require both scientific and philosophical analysis. Scientists can monitor brain states during cardiac arrest and document physiological changes. Philosophers can evaluate the logical structure of arguments based on testimonial evidence and clarify conceptual confusions about terms like "real," "consciousness," and "evidence."
    Rather than demanding that all questions be answered through scientific methods alone, intellectual honesty requires using the most appropriate tools for each type of inquiry. When we have extensive testimonial evidence about subjective experiences that can be partially corroborated through objective means, the appropriate response is systematic philosophical analysis using established criteria for evaluating testimony, not dismissal based on inappropriate methodological demands.

    Section 4: Memory Formation and Timing Objections

    Critics often argue that NDE memories form during brief periods of recovered brain function rather than during actual clinical death. This objection suggests that the brain, during the final moments before unconsciousness or the initial moments of recovery, rapidly constructs elaborate false memories that appear to correspond with objective events.

    While this explanation initially seems plausible, careful examination reveals several serious problems. The timing objection requires that barely functional neural tissue accomplish something that healthy brains cannot reliably do: construct detailed, coherent false memories that perfectly match independent witness testimony about specific events.

    Consider the neurological implausibility of this proposal. Brains recovering from severe trauma or prolonged unconsciousness don't typically exhibit enhanced memory formation capabilities. The suggestion that damaged or barely functional neural tissue could suddenly generate elaborate memories about past events contradicts everything we know about how memory works.
    Memory formation requires complex neural processes involving multiple brain regions working in coordination. During cardiac arrest, brain function ceases within seconds. During a severe coma, higher-order cognitive processes shut down. During general anesthesia, memory formation is specifically suppressed. The proposal that such compromised neural states could generate detailed false memories that happen to match objective reality requires assuming capabilities that far exceed what healthy brains can accomplish.

    The specificity problem poses another challenge. NDErs don't report vague, dream-like memories that might result from random neural firing. They provide specific, detailed accounts of particular events: exact conversations, precise descriptions of medical procedures, accurate reports of who entered or left the room and when. When these reports are checked against medical records and witness testimony, they often correspond exactly to documented events, that is, they’re objectively corroborated.
    Pam Reynolds described the unusual shape of the Midas Rex bone saw, the groove at the top where interchangeable blades fit, the case containing spare blades, and the specific pitch (a high D natural) that bothered her musician's ear. She accurately reported the female surgeon's comment about her arteries being too small and the decision to try femoral access from the left side. These weren't vague impressions but precise technical details that were subsequently confirmed by multiple members of the surgical team.

    The false memory explanation requires that Reynolds' barely functional brain somehow constructed detailed false memories about surgical instruments and procedures she had never seen, conversations she hadn't heard, and technical details she didn't possess. This explanation is not merely implausible; it's highly improbable given current neuroscience and what we know about memory formation and brain function during clinical death.

    The timing evidence itself contradicts the false memory hypothesis. Many NDErs provide specific temporal markers for their experiences, describing events that occurred at particular times during their unconsciousness. When these temporal claims are examined against medical records, witness testimony, and electronic monitoring, they often correspond to periods of documented brain inactivity.
    Dr. Michael Sabom's research compared NDE patients' reports about their resuscitation procedures with the reports of control groups who had not experienced NDEs. When non-NDE patients were asked to imagine what their resuscitation might have looked like, they made significant errors about medical procedures, equipment, and timing. NDE patients, by contrast, provided accurate accounts of actual procedures performed during their unconsciousness.

    The corroboration problem presents perhaps the greatest challenge to false memory explanations. These explanations require that multiple independent witnesses systematically lie or misremember when they confirm NDErs' reports. Doctors, nurses, family members, and other observers would all need to be consistently mistaken about the timing of events, the accuracy of reported conversations, and the correspondence between NDE accounts and objective reality.

    Consider the logical structure of this explanation: it requires assuming that elaborate false memories, constructed by barely functional brains, consistently happen to match the independent recollections of multiple reliable witnesses. This explanation multiplies improbabilities rather than resolving them.
    The delayed formation hypothesis faces additional problems when we examine the quality and persistence of NDE memories. False memories, when they occur, typically exhibit characteristic features: they're often vague, inconsistent, and subject to revision over time. NDE memories exhibit the opposite characteristics: they're typically vivid, consistent, and stable across decades. Research comparing NDE memories with memories of imagined events demonstrates that NDE memories exhibit the characteristics of genuine rather than false memories. They're associated with strong sensory details, emotional significance, and confidence in accuracy, features that distinguish real from imagined experiences.

    Section 5: Subconscious Sensory Leakage

    Some skeptics propose that veridical NDE details result from subconscious sensory input during clinical death, suggesting faint auditory or visual cues are processed and later reconstructed as out-of-body perceptions. This objection attempts to explain corroborated observations without invoking consciousness survival. However, it fails under our five criteria. The volume of sensory leakage studies is limited, relying on small-scale experiments unlike the millions of NDE accounts (Chapter 3). Its variety is narrow, as it doesn’t address NDEs in blind individuals (e.g., Kenneth Ring’s 1998 research, Chapter 3) or cases with sensory barriers (e.g., Pam Reynolds’ taped eyes/ears, Chapter 4, Section 1). Consistency is lacking, as leakage should produce varied, fragmented perceptions, not the structured NDE patterns (Greyson’s NDE Scale, Chapter 3). Crucially, it lacks objective corroboration, as no empirical evidence shows sensory processing during flat EEGs. Firsthand NDE accounts, verified by medical staff, outweigh this speculative hypothesis, which cannot explain precise details like Reynolds’ bone saw observation.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    Part 2 of Chapter 4

    Section 6: Cultural Conditioning and Belief System Arguments

    Another common objection suggests that NDE consistency results from cultural conditioning rather than encounters with objective reality. According to this argument, people report similar experiences because they've been exposed to similar cultural narratives about death and dying, not because they're perceiving actual phenomena.

    This explanation faces immediate problems when examined against the demographic evidence. If NDEs were simply products of cultural conditioning, we would expect significant variation based on religious background, cultural context, and prior exposure to NDE literature. Instead, research reveals consistent core elements across radically different populations.

    Young children provide particularly compelling evidence against cultural conditioning explanations. Dr. Melvin Morse's research with pediatric NDE patients found that children as young as three years old report classic NDE elements: out-of-body experiences, tunnels of light, encounters with deceased relatives, and life reviews. These children often lack mature concepts of death and haven't been exposed to cultural narratives about afterlife experiences.

    One three-year-old boy, after recovering from a near-drowning incident, accurately described the medical procedures performed during his resuscitation, including specific details about the emergency room equipment and the appearance of medical personnel. He also reported meeting his deceased grandfather, whom he identified from a family photograph only after his NDE. Such cases are difficult to explain through cultural conditioning when the experiencers lack the conceptual framework that conditioning would require.

    Cross-cultural research provides another challenge to conditioning explanations. Anthropologist Dorothy Counts found similar NDE elements among Papua New Guinea populations with no prior exposure to Western death literature. Dr. Allan Kellehear's cross-cultural studies documented consistent core features across societies with vastly different religious traditions and death practices.
    If cultural conditioning were the primary factor, we would expect NDEs to vary significantly between cultures with different death traditions, Buddhist societies emphasizing reincarnation, Christian societies focusing on judgment and salvation, and secular societies lacking afterlife beliefs altogether. Instead, the research reveals similar core elements across these diverse contexts, suggesting encounters with phenomena that transcend cultural construction.

    The religious interpretation problem supports rather than undermines the objectivity of NDE reports. When Christian experiencers interpret beings of light as Jesus, Muslim experiencers see them as religious figures from Islamic tradition, and secular experiencers report them as unknown loving presences, this suggests that cultural conditioning affects interpretation rather than the underlying experience itself.

    This pattern indicates that people encounter genuine phenomena but interpret them through available cultural frameworks. A Christian who meets a being of light naturally interprets this encounter through familiar religious categories, just as a physicist encountering an unfamiliar natural phenomenon might initially describe it using familiar scientific concepts.

    The interpretation versus perception distinction proves crucial for evaluating NDE reliability. If experiencers were simply reproducing cultural narratives, we would expect variation in the core experiences themselves, not just in their interpretation. Instead, we find consistent core elements (out-of-body perception, movement toward light, encounters with loving beings) combined with variable interpretations based on cultural background.

    Atheists and agnostics provide particularly strong evidence against cultural conditioning explanations. These individuals explicitly reject survival beliefs and have no cultural framework that would predict NDE experiences. Yet they report the same core elements as religious experiencers, often expressing surprise and confusion about experiences that contradict their materialist worldviews.
    Dr. A.J. Ayer, the famous atheist philosopher, experienced an NDE during a cardiac arrest and reported classic elements, including out-of-body perception and encounters with beings of light. Despite his lifelong commitment to materialist philosophy, Ayer acknowledged that his experience challenged his assumptions about consciousness and survival. Such cases demonstrate that NDEs occur independently of prior beliefs or cultural expectations.

    The historical precedent argument provides additional evidence against cultural conditioning. As we noted in Chapter 1, NDE-like experiences appear in historical accounts from ancient Greece (Plato's account of Er), medieval Europe (Hildegard of Bingen's visions), and indigenous traditions worldwide. These historical accounts predate modern NDE research by centuries or millennia, yet they contain remarkably similar elements. If NDEs were products of contemporary cultural conditioning, we wouldn't expect to find similar accounts throughout history and across diverse cultural contexts. The fact that ancient Greek warriors, medieval mystics, and contemporary cardiac patients report similar core experiences suggests encounters with phenomena that transcend particular cultural moments or belief systems.

    Section 7: The Burden of Proof and Standards of Evidence

    Perhaps the most persistent objection to NDE research involves shifting standards of evidence. Critics often demand extraordinary proof for consciousness survival while applying less rigorous standards to alternative explanations. This selective skepticism reveals more about philosophical commitments than about appropriate evidential criteria.

    Carl Sagan's famous maxim that "extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence" is frequently invoked to dismiss NDE testimony. But this principle raises crucial questions: What makes consciousness survival more "extraordinary" than consciousness emergence from matter? Why should survival require higher evidential standards than materialist explanations that assume consciousness is produced by brain activity? Moreover, are NDE claims “extraordinary” when there are millions of similar NDE accounts? How else are we to say what’s veridical other than millions of us are experiencing the same reality?

    From a purely logical standpoint, the emergence of subjective experience from objective neural processes might be considered equally extraordinary. The "hard problem" of consciousness remains unsolved precisely because we cannot explain how brain activity gives rise to subjective experience. Yet materialist explanations of NDEs are rarely subjected to the same "extraordinary evidence" standards applied to survival hypotheses.

    The asymmetrical application of evidential standards becomes apparent when we examine specific cases. When researchers propose brain-based explanations for NDEs, oxygen deprivation, endorphin release, and temporal lobe seizures, these speculative explanations are often accepted without demanding the same level of proof required for survival hypotheses. Yet many of these materialist explanations lack empirical support and involve their own theoretical difficulties.
    Consider the burden of proof fairly distributed. Survival proponents must explain how consciousness could continue without brain function. But materialists must explain how consciousness emerges from brain function in the first place, a problem that remains unsolved despite decades of neuroscientific research. Both positions involve theoretical challenges, yet only one is subjected to heightened evidential demands.

    The testimonial evidence standards applied to NDE research also reveal selective skepticism. When historians evaluate ancient documents, they don't demand a laboratory reproduction of historical events. When courts assess witness testimony, they don't require impossible standards of certainty. When scientists accept colleagues' reports about experimental results, they rely on testimonial evidence they haven't personally verified.

    Yet when evaluating NDE testimony, suddenly testimonial evidence becomes inadmissible, corroboration becomes insufficient, and consistency across multiple sources becomes irrelevant. These heightened standards would invalidate most historical knowledge, legal proceedings, and scientific collaboration if applied consistently.

    The quantity and quality of NDE evidence exceed what we typically require for knowledge claims in other domains. We have millions of consistent firsthand accounts, thousands of cases with objective corroboration, cross-cultural replication, and long-term longitudinal studies. This represents a more extensive evidential base than exists for many historical events we consider well-established.
    Consider the evidential standards applied to medical research. When evaluating new treatments or understanding disease mechanisms, medical researchers routinely rely on patient testimony about symptoms, case studies from individual practitioners, and patterns observed across multiple patients. These same evidential types, testimonial reports, case studies, and pattern recognition, form the foundation of NDE research, yet suddenly become inadmissible when they challenge materialist assumptions.

    The real question isn't whether extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence, but whether extraordinary resistance to evidence reflects extraordinary commitment to prior assumptions. When substantial testimonial evidence is dismissed without serious consideration, when corroboration by medical professionals is ignored, and when consistent patterns across diverse populations are explained away through increasingly complex theoretical gymnastics, we may be witnessing ideological rather than methodological responses.

    A fair approach would apply consistent evidential standards while acknowledging the theoretical challenges faced by all positions. Survival hypotheses must address questions about consciousness mechanisms and survival processes. Materialist explanations must address the hard problem of consciousness and the specific features of NDE experiences that resist brain-based explanation. Neither position should be exempt from evidential scrutiny, nor should either be subjected to impossible standards.

    Conclusion: The Weakness of Objections in Light of Testimonial Strength

    The counter-arguments examined, hallucinations, brain-based mechanisms, scientism, memory formation, cultural conditioning, subconscious sensory leakage, and coincidence/confirmation bias, fail to provide compelling alternatives to the conclusion that consciousness can survive bodily death. Each objection raises valid questions about interpretation and methodology but falls short when evaluated against the five testimonial criteria: the massive volume of millions of accounts worldwide, the universal variety across ages, cultures, and contexts, the remarkable consistency of core elements like out-of-body perceptions and life reviews, the objective corroboration of veridical details during documented unconsciousness, and the reliability of firsthand reports from credible sources. Hypotheses like subconscious sensory leakage or confirmation bias rely on speculative mechanisms that cannot explain cases such as blind individuals’ visual corroboration (Chapter 3) or children identifying unknown deceased relatives (Section 5). These objections lack the empirical support and logical coherence they demand of survival claims, revealing an asymmetry rooted in unexamined materialist assumptions, as explored in Chapter 6.

    This pattern of resistance mirrors the paradigm challenges described by Thomas Kuhn in scientific revolutions, where substantial evidence is dismissed without serious consideration. For instance, corroborated details, such as Pam Reynolds’ bone saw observation (Section 1) or the 22% of NDErs meeting unknown deceased (Section 1), are ignored in favor of ad hoc theories that multiply improbabilities. Intellectual honesty demands consistent standards across domains. If testimonial evidence is deemed unreliable for consciousness research, it should be equally suspect in medicine, history, or science, where testimony underpins knowledge. Similarly, the standard of heightened scrutiny applied to NDE testimony must also challenge materialist assumptions about consciousness emergence, which remain unsolved (Section 3).

    Open questions persist, such as the timing of experiences or the mechanisms of survival, but these do not negate the robust evidence for consciousness persistence. As with gravity before Einstein or anesthesia before its mechanisms were understood, we accept phenomena based on evidence prior to full explanation. The testimonial evidence’s strength, systematically gathered and rigorously verified across millions of accounts, outweighs speculative dismissals. This warrants serious consideration of consciousness survival as a widespread, objective phenomenon, not an anomaly requiring exceptional proof, but one deserving continued interdisciplinary inquiry with methodological openness and evidential rigor to explore a reality that may transcend current theoretical frameworks.
  • Wayfarer
    25.2k
    For NDEs, with 200-300 million reports….Sam26

    I read your rationale for this the other day but it easily seems like overreach. It is inferred that there would be that number of reports, on the basis of scaling up the numbers of reports from a sample population, but if many of these experiences are not formally written down or described then it’s purely conjectural. And it’s a large number! I don’t think it would hurt your case to omit references to such large speculative numbers, while still pressing the point that they are frequently reported and may be far more common than we're inclined to believe.

    When astronomers observe distant galaxies, when biologists examine cellular structures, and when physicists read instrument displays, all involve sensory experience. The suggestion that our senses are "the worst data-taking devices" would collapse the empirical foundation of science itself.Sam26

    But it’s not directly comparable. Third-person validation is obviously missing from near-death experiences. The difference is not merely in kind of object observed but in what sort of epistemic access is possible. Empirical science rests on public reproducibility, while SME research often relies on private, unrepeatable events. True, there is the ‘replication crisis’ in science, which is probably of special relevance in your subject matter, as it is much more common in the social than the physical sciences. But even so, the experiences reported by these subjects can only be validated first-hand by actually having them. Otherwise they remain anecdotal.

    Subjective vs. Objective Elements

    NDE testimony includes objective elements (verifiable details like surgical procedures) and subjective elements (e.g., feelings of love, encounters with deceased relatives). Corroborated objective elements, such as a child's verified ER observations, lend credibility to subjective reports, suggesting genuine experiences. Cultural variations affect interpretation (e.g., light as Jesus or ancestors), but core phenomena remain consistent, indicating universal features of consciousness.
    Sam26

    Fair distinction between the subjective and objective elements of NDEs, and I agree that verifiable observations—such as accurate descriptions of surgical instruments or events during clinical death—are especially significant. They do suggest that something more than imagination is at work, and lend weight to the credibility of the overall report, although it’s important to stay mindful of the epistemic difference between first-person and third-person validation. While veridical cases strengthen the evidential basis of NDE studies, many of the other reported elements—particularly those involving feelings of peace, tunnels of light, or meetings with deceased persons—remain inherently subjective. This isn’t a criticism, but a caution about evidential weight.

    Cultural frameworks may shape the interpretation of NDEs —whether the “being of light” is perceived as Jesus or an ancestor—and while that may point to a universal phenomenological core, it could also reflect how deeply interpretive structures are embedded in the unconscious. That cultural dimension was also encountered by Ian Stevenson in his research of past-life memories, where children in cultures like India were far more likely to be believed than those reporting such memories in Western cultures. ('In the West', he once said, 'people ask "why would you research that? Everyone knows it's a myth". In the East, the reaction was more like "why would you research that? Everyone knows it happens all the time.")

    Open questions persist, such as the timing of experiences or the mechanisms of survival, but these do not negate the robust evidence for consciousness persistence.Sam26

    Your argument highlights what I think is a central and underappreciated point: that materialist objections to NDEs and (and related phenomena such as past-life recall) often rest on explanatory gaps of their own, especially when faced with rigorously investigated cases of veridical perception. But I think the real challenge lies not just in identifying the limits of materialism, but in what the alternative is. Your metaphor of “survival” still implies a kind of thing that persists, and a mechanism by which it does so—concepts which themselves are grounded in the very materialist kind of ontology that you're seeking to question.

    If these phenomena point to anything, perhaps it's that we need to rethink the ontological categories themselves—maybe life and mind are not simply functions of biology, but expressions of a deeper order that isn’t bounded by physical birth and death. That doesn’t give us a ready-made metaphysical framework, but it may point to the need for one. I think there are hints of this emerging all over the place at this point in history, but it's obviously a very deep subject. So while I agree that NDEs may well 'transcend current theoretical frameworks', what the emerging paradigm might be is still, as you say, an open question.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    But it’s not directly comparable. Third-person validation is obviously missing from near-death experiences. The difference is not merely in kind of object observed but in what sort of epistemic access is possible. Empirical science rests on public reproducibility, while SME research often relies on private, unrepeatable events. True, there is the ‘replication crisis’ in science, which is probably of special relevance in your subject matter, as it is much more common in the social than the physical sciences. But even so, the experiences reported by these subjects can only be validated first-hand by actually having them. Otherwise they remain anecdotal.Wayfarer

    Whenever you can corroborate testimonial evidence, it's not anecdotal. Part of the problem is that most people aren't able to evaluate testimonial evidence properly. Almost everything you study is based on the testimony of others. You don't do the experiments; you rely on what others report.

    By the way, there is data that supports the number of people in the world who have experienced an NDE. These estimates are considered reliable because they come from peer-reviewed research, including prospective studies (tracking patients in real-time) and large surveys. For instance, the 5-10% general prevalence is widely cited and supported by recent data up to 2025. Scientific American (May 14, 2024) estimates an astounding 5 to 10 percent of the general population has memories of an NDE. If anything, the 2-300 million may be low, but even if it's 100 million, it doesn't affect the strength of my argument.

    You think I pull this out of the air. I've been researching NDEs for about 20 years. I do know what I'm talking about. I know that people are still going to disagree, but that's okay, it's why I posted in here. I wanted to hear the counterarguments.
  • Wayfarer
    25.2k
    it doesn't affect the strength of my argument.Sam26

    Indeed. A point to consider.
  • Banno
    28.5k
    @Sam26, do you at some stage consider what it is that survives death?
  • Janus
    17.4k
    The most fundamental constituents of the body survive death. @Sam26 seems to be thinking of consciousness, though.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    In chapter 5, I consider other possible conclusions. Personhood, as I see it, encompasses the core elements of self: identity, memories, relationships, values, and the capacity for awareness and empathy. It's what makes "you" you, beyond the physical human body. In NDEs, experiencers often report retaining and even expanding these aspects, meeting deceased loved ones who recognize them, reliving life events with moral insight, and feeling a profound sense of continuity amid heightened clarity. This suggests the surviving entity isn't the biological human (with its limitations like pain or mortality) but a relational, conscious personhood that transcends bodily constraints.

    For e.g., the "no harm" principle from Chapter 5 of my book implies that while the human form can suffer, personhood emerges intact, like waking from a dream where pain was real but temporary. Relationships endure as part of this personhood, with NDEs showing bonds that persist eternally, free from physical separation. Wittgenstein's hinges in Chapter 6 of the book add depth: consciousness and love as foundational certainties could be the bedrock of personhood, undoubtable and eternal.

    Speculatively, what survives might be this purified personhood, an eternal "I" that learns, connects, and evolves without the human shell's vulnerabilities. Being human is the temporary stage for that growth, but personhood is the enduring actor. It's a beautiful idea that reframes death not as loss but as liberation. Some of this is speculative, but it's not purely speculative; there are good reasons to suppose that much of this is factual. It's a good question, @Banno, but there's obviously a lot we don't know.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    Yes, but the idea of personhood remains intact.
  • Wayfarer
    25.2k
    By way of contrast this is where the Buddhist model is relevant. In the early texts, the Buddha emphatically denies that there is a ‘what’ that survives death. This is laid out clearly in two key discourses: the Sāti the Fisherman’s Son sutta and the discourse to Ariṭṭha.

    In the first, Sāti claims that consciousness is the “what” that transmigrates. The Buddha responds by firmly rejecting this as a wrong—and even pernicious—view. It is not simply mistaken, but actively obstructive to insight. After attempts to correct him fail, the Buddha dismisses Sāti as unable to grasp the teaching, and then clarifies with the monks the correct understanding: that consciousness does not persist as a self-same entity, but arises dependent on conditions, ceasing when those conditions cease.

    In the second dialogue, when Rādha asks the Buddha what the constituents of a ‘being’ are, the Buddha replies:

    “Any desire, passion, delight, or craving for form, Rādha: when one is caught up (satta) there, tied up (visatta) there, one is said to be 'a being.'”

    So again, the picture is not of an ego, soul, or substance that is born, dies, or survives. It is of a process: craving and clinging give rise to the experience of continuity, both within this life and beyond. What “continues” is not a person but an impersonal dynamic of becoming.

    Interestingly, this resonates with Schopenhauer’s conception of the will as the blind striving underlying phenomenal existence. But the Buddha goes further in prescribing a path by which this process can be understood and released (which is the entire thrust of his teaching.)

    In later Buddhist traditions—particularly Tibetan—the Bardo Thödol offers detailed accounts of what is said to occur in the intermediate states after death. These are rich with imagery and vivid experiences, including visions of light, peaceful and wrathful beings, and karmically influenced encounters. But the subject undergoing these experiences is not taken to be an enduring self, but rather a locus of karmic momentum—an apparent subjectivity without essence ('citta-santāna'). The continuity is real, but not personal in the conventional sense. This provides a philosophical model that avoids both materialist reductionism and dualism. And it arguably offers a conceptual framework within which to interpret NDEs—especially those that are less reassuring and more morally charged, like the account by Sam Bercholz in A Guided Tour of Hell.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    Some of the "Buddhist model" is based on NDEs and meditative states of consciousness, only they don't call it an NDE. NDE states can be reached without actually being near-death. When I was 21 years old, I had just such an experience.
  • Edmund
    34
    Not sure soul or conciousness transference is necessarily religious doctrine. Perhaps a doctrine adopted by or essential to religion?
  • night912
    48
    The 1992 Gallup poll estimated that 5% of Americans had experienced NDEs, suggesting 13-15 million cases in the United States alone. A 2024 Scientific American review, citing studies like Kondziella et al. (2019) across 35 countries, estimates 5-10% global prevalence in the general population, representing potentially 400-800 million cases worldwide amid a 2025 world population of approximately 8.1 billion.


    Nobody here that disagrees with you, are dismissing the notion that people have had NDE. There's plenty of evidence that supports it. However, we ARE dismissing your conclusion in regards to NDE because you have no evidence that supports your conclusion. You're using irrelevant data and claim that it's evidence for your conclusion regarding NDE. This is neither philosophy nor science.

    I'm genuinely curious, have you ever had an experience of a hallucination caused by the consumption of hallucinogenic drugs before?
  • Sam26
    2.9k


    When someone tells me that NDEs aren't evidence,” I know we’re not having an epistemological discussion, we’re dealing with a preset worldview that refuses to be inconvenienced by data.

    Let me be blunt: if you think testimony isn’t evidence, then you’re not just wrong—you’re being selectively inconsistent. You accept testimony as evidence all the time: in courtrooms, in history books, in journalism, in scientific discovery. Much of what you believe about the world has been passed to you through other people’s words. Testimony is a fundamental mode of knowing. That’s not a fringe claim; that’s epistemology 101.

    So when someone says NDE accounts don’t count, what they really mean is: “I don’t like what these testimonies imply.” That’s not skepticism. That’s avoidance.

    Let me ask you plainly: if thousands of people from all over the world consistently reported seeing the same rare hallucination during cardiac arrest, would you call that data?

    If people clinically dead for minutes described things they couldn’t possibly have seen—like surgical instruments, clothing colors, or conversations in adjacent rooms—and those reports checked out, would that count?

    If blind people reported veridical visual experiences during unconsciousness, would that at least raise an eyebrow?

    Because that’s exactly what’s happening. And it’s dismissed not because it isn’t evidence, but because the implications are too uncomfortable.

    If you want to say, “The evidence isn’t conclusive,” fine. Make your case. But don’t try to rewrite the rules of epistemology mid-argument. Don’t pretend that testimony suddenly loses all value the moment it challenges materialist assumptions.

    That’s not critical thinking. That’s building a fence around your worldview and pretending it’s a lab.

    We’re talking about inductive reasoning, not metaphysical proofs. This is the same kind of reasoning we use to build theories in science, assess eyewitnesses in court, or trust long-range weather models. It’s not about absolute certainty—it’s about what the evidence suggests when we’re not busy filtering it through what we already believe.

    And when you look at the NDE data—its volume, diversity, internal consistency, and verifiable details—you have a body of testimony that meets or exceeds the standards we accept in other domains. So if you’re rejecting it, say why—but don’t pretend it’s not there.

    I’m not asking anyone to believe in the afterlife. I’m not asking for spiritual conversion. I’m asking for intellectual honesty. When thousands of people tell similar stories under extreme physiological conditions, and some of those stories include independently verified details that should’ve been inaccessible to them, that’s not fantasy. That’s evidence. And if you’re too philosophically rigid to admit that, then say so. But stop pretending the data isn’t there. It is.

    And it’s not going away.

    The Self-Sealing Fallacy

    This kind of objection, that NDEs “can’t be evidence” because they contradict materialism, is a textbook example of a self-sealing argument. That’s a fallacy where no counterexample can ever count against the belief, because the belief has been defined in a way that invalidates all contradictory data by default. In this case, the logic goes like this: “We know consciousness can’t exist apart from the brain; therefore, any report that it does must be false—even if it’s detailed, verified, and repeated across cultures.” That’s not skepticism. That’s immunizing your worldview against all challenges. It doesn’t matter what someone reports, or how well it’s documented, if your philosophical commitments require you to deny the possibility of evidence before it’s even examined, then you’re no longer doing inquiry. You’re defending dogma. This fallacy is common in both religious and atheistic discourse.
  • Apustimelogist
    876
    “We know consciousness can’t exist apart from the brain; therefore, any report that it does must be false—even if it’s detailed, verified, and repeated across cultures.”Sam26

    Why do we have brains if we don't need them for complex experiences?
  • Janus
    17.4k
    Let me be blunt: if you think testimony isn’t evidence, then you’re not just wrong—you’re being selectively inconsistent. You accept testimony as evidence all the time: in courtrooms, in history books, in journalism, in scientific discovery. Much of what you believe about the world has been passed to you through other people’s words. Testimony is a fundamental mode of knowing. That’s not a fringe claim; that’s epistemology 101.Sam26

    There is testimony and then there is testimony. The kinds of testimony you say we all accept is expert testimony which has been tested, documented and peer-reviewed. The testimony you are citing is not of the same kind.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    There is testimony and then there is testimony. The kinds of testimony you say we all accept is expert testimony which has been tested, documented and peer-reviewed. The testimony you are citing is not of the same kind.Janus

    Right—and pretending only “expert, peer-reviewed testimony” counts is a neat way to dodge the actual issue. We rely on multiple classes of testimony across serious domains every day: eyewitnesses in court, patient self-reports in medicine, historical documents in scholarship, field notes in anthropology, and yes, expert statements. All of those are testimony. Peer review doesn’t magically convert testimony into something else; it’s a vetting process applied to data and reports—often built on testimony.

    Now, if your standard is “tested, documented, and peer-reviewed,” I’ll meet you there, because there is a lot of NDE literature that is documented and peer-reviewed. There are standardized instruments (e.g., structured scales), prospective studies in medical settings, case reports with time stamps, surgical logs, and corroboration by clinical staff. On top of that, there’s the wider body: thousands of firsthand accounts with convergence across cultures and conditions, many with veridical details later verified. That’s not “random story-time.” That’s a dataset—messy like all human datasets, but governed by recognizable standards: volume, variety, internal consistency, independent corroboration, and proximity to the events.

    Also, the idea that we “all accept” only expert testimony is fiction. Courts convict on lay eyewitness testimony every day (with strict reliability tests like I've talked about). Physicians act on patient-reported symptoms constantly (because pain, dizziness, aura, etc., are only knowable by report). Psychology, sociology, and large swaths of medicine depend on self-report. If you’re going to declare those forms of evidence illegitimate here—but keep them everywhere else—you’re not defending rigor; you’re quarantining inconvenient evidence.

    If your point is really, “NDE testimony hasn’t been vetted enough,” good—then say that, and specify the bar: what documentation, what timing, what corroboration would move the needle? Because here’s the pattern I see: when presented with documented, corroborated cases, the standard shifts. First, it’s “peer review or it doesn’t count.” Then, when peer-reviewed cases appear, it’s “still anecdotal.” That’s moving the goalposts. And when no conceivable instance could ever count—because any positive case must, by assumption, be error, hallucination, or fraud—that’s a self-sealing posture, not an evidential one.

    Bottom line: testimony comes in kinds, sure, but so does vetting. NDE evidence isn’t asking for a special pass; it’s asking for the same rules we use elsewhere: clear criteria, consistent standards, and intellectual honesty about what the data—expert, lay, and documented—actually shows. If you want to argue it’s insufficient, make that case. But stop pretending it’s not evidence. It is.
  • Janus
    17.4k
    We rely on multiple classes of testimony across serious domains every day: eyewitnesses in court, patient self-reports in medicine, historical documents in scholarship, field notes in anthropology, and yes, expert statements.Sam26

    Sure we do rely on such inexpert testimony in many contexts, but the testimony relied on in those contexts is about commonly experienced events, not claims about extraordinary events like NDE's, or sighting Bigfoot or UFOs or being abducted by aliens.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    Sure we do rely on such inexpert testimony in many contexts, but the testimony relied on in those contexts is about commonly experienced events, not claims about extraordinary events like NDE's, or sighting Bigfoot or UFOs or being abducted by aliens.Janus

    You obviously haven't been paying attention to my argument. You’re assuming from the outset that consciousness surviving clinical death is extraordinary and therefore requires some special, elevated evidential bar. That’s not an epistemic principle; that’s a value judgment shaped by your worldview. Something is only “extraordinary” relative to what you’ve decided is normal. And that’s the problem: if your definition of “normal” is restricted to materialist assumptions, then yes, anything suggesting consciousness can function without a brain will look exotic by definition. That’s not a property of the event; it’s a property of your frame.

    Now, here’s the other issue: when you have thousands of accounts from all over the world, across centuries, cultures, ages, and belief systems—many with independently corroborated, veridical details—that’s no longer a “rare anomaly.” That’s a recurring phenomenon. Recurring phenomena don’t get treated like outliers in any other domain—they get studied. The sheer volume and consistency of the data moves it out of the “extraordinary claim” category and into “common human experience under specific conditions.”

    And if you want to put NDEs in the same box as Bigfoot or UFO abductions, you’re ignoring the key difference: veridical perception—accurately describing events, objects, or conversations that occurred while the brain was offline, and which were later confirmed by independent witnesses. Bigfoot sightings don’t produce that kind of hard, checkable correlation. Alien abduction stories don’t emerge under conditions of continuous medical monitoring with surgical logs and witness testimony from trained professionals. NDE cases often do.

    In other words, the “extraordinary claim” dodge doesn’t work here because the claim is supported by volume, variety, and verification. At that point, the intellectually honest move isn’t to wave it off as too weird to take seriously; it’s to confront the fact that maybe it isn’t weird at all. Maybe the only extraordinary thing is our refusal to recognize a pattern staring us in the face.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    Why do we have brains if we don't need them for complex experiences?Apustimelogist

    But NDEs don’t claim the brain is useless, they suggest that in certain extreme conditions, consciousness can occur without normal brain activity. That’s a very different claim. The brain might be a kind of interface or transceiver, not the sole producer of consciousness. Damage the radio, and you can’t hear the broadcast, but that doesn’t mean the signal isn’t still there.
  • Sam26
    2.9k
    I wouldn't be writing a book if I hadn't thought through this material.
  • Janus
    17.4k
    You obviously haven't been paying attention to my argument. You’re assuming from the outset that consciousness surviving clinical death is extraordinary and therefore requires some special, elevated evidential bar.Sam26

    From my perspective it's an extraordinary event simply because I have never experienced such a thing, and none of the many hundreds of people I have known personally have ever claimed to have an NDE.

    And if you want to put NDEs in the same box as Bigfoot or UFO abductions, you’re ignoring the key difference: veridical perception—accurately describing events, objects, or conversations that occurred while the brain was offline, and which were later confirmed by independent witnesses.Sam26

    How do I know the corroborations of those witnesses do not consist in misremembering, collusion or fabrication? I don't have any "horse in the race"―if it turns out that my consciousness survives the death of the body, I'll deal with it then. In the meantime I might be convinced if I experienced an NDE myself or perhaps even if sometime whose veracity I trusted sufficiently told me they had such an experience. But even then I might think there could be some other explanation, because after death survival of personal consciousness seems so implausible given what is known about the brain.

    I'll confess I'm not all that interested simply because I cannot do anything about whatever turns out to be the reality anyway. I guess one advantage of believing in the survival of consciousness, like the belief in God, is that you cannot be proven wrong―if there is no consciousness after death you will never know you were wrong.

    The brain might be a kind of interface or transceiver, not the sole producer of consciousness. Damage the radio, and you can’t hear the broadcast, but that doesn’t mean the signal isn’t still there.Sam26

    The brain is almost infinitely more complex than a radio or a computer, and yet the radio or computer can receive much more information than the brain. If the brain were merely a transceiver why would it need to be so complex?
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.