• Mark S
    291
    I am preparing a paper presently titled “How Morality as Cooperation Can Help Resolve Moral Disputes” for submission to a peer-reviewed journal that focuses on biological and cultural evolution and its insights into prosocial behaviors. The editor has OK’d the abstract but has not yet seen the paper. Before I submit it, perhaps some here could comment on the extracts below —the parts most relevant to moral philosophy, a subject I have studied only superficially.


    How Morality as Cooperation Can Help Resolve Moral Disputes
    Oct 11, 2025

    Abstract:
    There is a growing scientific consensus that the primary reason cultural moralities exist is that they solve cooperation problems. This paper proposes how insights from evolutionary game theory and moral psychology into the origins and functions of cultural moral norms can help resolve disputes about their enforcement. Case studies include “homosexuality is evil” and “abortion any time after conception is wrong”. Revealing the shameful origins of these two norms in exploitation of outgroups to increase the benefits of cooperation for ingroups could help groups decide if they will be enforced. Starting with The Golden Rule, “do not kill”, and the above disputed norms as examples, I show how a behavior’s morality can be categorized as descriptively moral, universally moral, and immoral (within a morality as cooperation framework) based on if they solve or create cooperation problems within groups and between groups. Reasons are given for why rational people might prefer to advocate the three principles implied by this categorization as a moral reference for refining cultural moral norms. No claims are made that all rational people will or somehow ought (except as an instrumental ought for achieving their goals) to advocate for morality as cooperation’s implied principles. Such claims are assumed to be beyond science’s domain.

    I make four main claims that may not have previously been explicitly stated. First, virtually all the contradictions and strangeness of past and present cultural moral norms can be explained by evolutionary game theory and moral psychology as parts of cooperation strategies. Second, cultural moral norms are those norms whose violation is commonly thought to warrant punishment of at least reputation damage. Third, these explanations imply three cultural-independent moral principles that define what is descriptively moral, universally moral, and immoral within the framework of morality as cooperation. Fourth, the ultimate source of our moral psychology and cultural moral norms lies in cooperation strategies that are as innate to our universe as the simple mathematics on which evolutionary game theory is based.

    ….
    To illustrate how this perspective can be culturally useful, I will explain what this perspective reveals about 1) the Golden Rule and “do not kill”, 2) the sometimes fervently defended norms “abortion is wrong from the moment of conception” and “homosexuality is evil”, 3) the strange norm “eating pigs is morally wrong”, and 4) “women must be subservient to men” and “slaves must obey their masters”.


    These categories define three culture-independent moral principles:
    1) Descriptively moral behaviors solve cooperation problems in groups but may exploit, and thereby create cooperation problems with, outgroups.
    2) Universally moral behaviors solve cooperation problems without exploiting others.
    3) Immoral behaviors create cooperation problems.


    Why might people prefer the proposed morality as cooperation principles as references for understanding and refining cultural moral norms?

    1) Based on their explanatory power for the superficially chaotic data set of past and present cultural moral norms, these moral principles are arguably true in the usual scientific sense, making them uniquely valuable as objective references for resolving disputes about cultural moral norms.
    2) These principles reveal that cultural morality is not a mysterious burden (Blackford 2015) but rather a powerful means for increasing the benefits of sustained cooperation with family, friends, and community.
    3) They will be more harmonious with our moral sense than other options because, for the most part, the cooperation strategies they employ are already encoded in the biology underlying our moral sense.
    4) In addition to its material benefits, increased cooperation can reliably trigger innate psychological rewards, feelings of well-being and moral elevation (Haidt 2003; Von Hippel, W. 2018), that evolved to help motivate cooperation with family, friends, and larger ingroups.
    5) By defining only moral ‘means’ (cooperation strategies) and not ‘ends’ (the goals of that cooperation), these principles are compatible with common ultimate moral goals from moral philosophy. Variations of well-being for all and Stoicism’s personal eudaimonia are goals that could be well served by refining cultural moral norms to more effectively solve cooperation problems.

    Implications for moral philosophy

    The morality as cooperation scientific consensus explains why cultural moralities exist. This is not a philosophical claim about what morality ought to be. Answering moral philosophy’s ‘ought’ questions such as “How should I live?” and “What are my obligations?” requires assumptions about imperative moral oughts and ultimate moral goals that are beyond science’s domain.

    However, some philosophers might find that the emerging understanding of what moral means ‘are’ provides useful insights into what moral means ought to be.

    For example, consider the ultimate source of our moral psychology and cultural moral norms. That source is not in our semi-random biological and cultural evolution. These evolutionary processes merely encoded morality. The ultimate source of cultural moralities is in evolutionary game theory. Evolutionary game theory is independent of biology or culture because it is as innate to our physical reality as the simple mathematics it is based on. Perhaps a culture, species, and time independent definition of what cultural moralities ‘are’ could be useful?

    Conclusion and recommendations for further work

    Morality as cooperation implies three moral principles that, with insights from game theory and moral psychology, may be culturally useful for helping to resolve disputes about cultural moral norms.

    However, work is needed to 1) more firmly establish that the three moral principles proposed here are grounded in robust science, 2) explore how kin altruism, hierarchies, network reciprocity, group selection, rule of law, and money economies (none of which are addressed in this paper) help solve cooperation problems and how to use that knowledge to refine cultural moral norms to better meet human needs and preferences, and 3) integrate morality as cooperation into moral philosophy’s toolkit for resolving disputes about enforcing cultural moral norms.
  • L'éléphant
    1.7k
    First, congratulations on your submission. Not an easy thing to write for publication.

    I make four main claims that may not have previously been explicitly stated.Mark S

    First, virtually all the contradictions and strangeness of past and present cultural moral norms can be explained by evolutionary game theory and moral psychology as parts of cooperation strategies.Mark S
    Not all. Tyrannical moral laws were part of the past (and present). There was no "cooperation" strategy, except the laws made by the one person in power. There were also tribes, nation, communities that had become extinct because morality was to serve the almighty being, to the detriment of the population.

    Second, cultural moral norms are those norms whose violation is commonly thought to warrant punishment of at least reputation damage.Mark S
    Good.

    Third, these explanations imply three cultural-independent moral principles that define what is descriptively moral, universally moral, and immoral within the framework of morality as cooperation.Mark S
    Good.

    Fourth, the ultimate source of our moral psychology and cultural moral norms lies in cooperation strategies that are as innate to our universe as the simple mathematics on which evolutionary game theory is based.Mark S
    The veil of ignorance as a hypothesis should counter evolutionary game theory in one way. The VOI theory wants to bring up the least advantaged members of society without the members knowing their own talents and abilities. If wages are the measure of equality, would you agree to equal wages for both non-productive and highly productive members of your society?
  • Mark S
    291
    First, virtually all the contradictions and strangeness of past and present cultural moral norms can be explained by evolutionary game theory and moral psychology as parts of cooperation strategies.
    — Mark S
    Not all. Tyrannical moral laws were part of the past (and present). There was no "cooperation" strategy, except the laws made by the one person in power. There were also tribes, nation, communities that had become extinct because morality was to serve the almighty being, to the detriment of the population.
    L'éléphant

    Hi L'éléphant, thanks for commenting.

    Since “cultural moral norms are those norms whose violation is commonly thought to warrant punishment of at least reputation damage”, a tyrant can try to impose tyrannical moral norms, but may fail, because that would require convincing the population that violators deserve punishment. Moral norms are what a culture says they are.

    Of course, tyrants can dictate laws and claim, like a current politician does, that anyone who opposes him has violated the norm “don’t criticize the tyrant” and has acted immorally. While tyrants can make a law and he can punish violators, it does not make the law a cultural moral norm.

    Tribes and nations could become extinct because, for example, their cultural moral norms focused on cooperating to increase the general welfare rather than cooperating to defend against or attack their neighbors. Morality as cooperation is about what moral means are, and is silent about what the goals of that cooperation (such as general happiness or exterminating the group’s perceived enemies) ought to be.

    Counterexamples of cultural moral norms that might not be parts of cooperation strategies are always welcome. In the OP, I write:

    To illustrate how this perspective can be culturally useful, I will explain what this perspective reveals about 1) the Golden Rule and “do not kill”, 2) the sometimes fervently defended norms “abortion is wrong from the moment of conception” and “homosexuality is evil”, 3) the strange norm “eating pigs is morally wrong”, and 4) “women must be subservient to men” and “slaves must obey their masters”.Mark S

    That is, I explain how all of these moral norms are, surprisingly to me when I was looking for counterexamples, parts of known cooperation strategies. Almost all contradictions and strangeness in past and present cultural moralities are due to different definitions of favored ingroups and disfavored or exploited outgroups, different ethnic marker norms, different strategies, and emphasis on different ultimate goals for moral behavior.

    The veil of ignorance as a hypothesis should counter evolutionary game theory in one way. The VOI theory wants to bring up the least advantaged members of society without the members knowing their own talents and abilities. If wages are the measure of equality, would you agree to equal wages for both non-productive and highly productive members of your society?L'éléphant

    I am in awe of Rawls’ VOI theory. It is a wonderful heuristic for designing a society without exploitation of others (without creating cooperation problems). Consider two cases.

    Case 1 - If the non-productive members of society are free-riders who could help others and not harm them but self-interestedly choose not to, then yes, they are creating cooperation problems and that is immoral in the morality as cooperation framework. They deserve punishment of at least reputation damage.

    Case 2 - - If the non-productive members of society are doing the best they can, then in a moral society (again in the morality as cooperation framework) they would be helped by others and not deserve punishment.

    But you asked if, regardless of their contribution to the public good, all deserved the same wages. If giving everyone the same wages creates cooperation problems (as I expect it would by demotivating hard work) then that would be immoral (in the morality as cooperation framework).

    I don’t remember that Rawls claimed that everyone should (in effect) get the same reward regardless of contribution. To the extent that Rawls VOI does advocate behaviors in the designed society that create cooperation problems rather than solve them, then yes, morality as cooperation does contradict VOI.

    But I would disagree that VOI can “counter” morality as cooperation. The scientific truth of morality as cooperation is in a different domain of knowledge from morality based on assumed ethical premises.
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.