So I don't see Smith as overstepping the bounds of reason and landing in a puddle of nonsense. I see him as a victim of chance. Something extraordinarily unlikely happens, and it will challenge his otherwise orderly process of belief formation. — Srap Tasmaner
It's not a calculus, merely annotation. In propositional logic, "probably p" or "believed p" does not add up to p, but to (p v ~p) — unenlightened
It's been a while since I've looked at that dialogue. In my recollection, it's a conversation about knowledge, not certainty, though of course I might be mistaken. Perhaps you'll do me the favor of correcting my memory, by reminding me how the concept of certainty figures in that fine old legend.Here I think we are getting closer to what is going on in the Theaetetus. — Banno
I wouldn't call that certainty, just a framing assumption.One way we can be certain is when we take things as the bedrock of our discussion. In this sense, doubt is dismissed as not having a place in the discussion. — Banno
That sounds right to me.So, for example, this is not a discussion about the comparative benefits of diesel and petrol engines, and thinking it so is to misunderstand what is going on. Or, to use the all-pervasive example, one does not doubt that a bishop moves diagonally while playing chess. — Banno
I take it "absolute certainty" means something along the lines of: 100% certain, beyond the possibility of doubt, beyond the possibility of error, not possibly false, indubitable in any discursive context whatsoever.... I agree the concept seems fanciful. I'm inclined to say that nothing is absolutely certain in this sense, and that the term is another one of those philosopher's fictions that make a laughing stock of their art when it's employed as anything more than a foil.The problem here is the philosopher's game of putting "absolute" in front of "certainty" and thinking that this means something. Outside of philosophy, minds like ours always or almost always certain. Few folk check that they have an arm before they reach for the fork. It's not the sort of thing that one doubts, outside the philosopher's parlour. — Banno
I'm not sure how this coordinates with our discussion of certainty. In any case, it seems the answer depends on what you're ignorant of at the time you "learn that the cup is red".And here is where the logos differs from justification. Hanover brought this to mind elsewhere. When you learn that the cup is red (again), are you learning something about the cup, or something about the use of the word "red"? — Banno
Do you mean to say it does not "automatically follow", in the head of every person who learns that r justifies p? In other words, not everyone who learns that r justifies p will immediately infer that r justifies (p V q)?Well, one hand washes the other. When you learn that r justifies p, you learn more than just that r materially implies p; you learn a new way of using "r" and "p". It does not automatically follow that, if r justifies p, it justifies p v q. — Banno
It's a good first step; but so much more is involved. Consider the ancient distinction that splits knowing into knowing how... and knowing that..., and then pretends that knowhow has no place in philosophy.
Until it was pointed out that philosophers ought know how to use words.
To paraphrase, there are ways of knowing that are not exhibited in statements, but shown in what we do.
These are missing from Gettier. — Banno
IF (probably p) THEN (probably (p V q). — Cabbage Farmer
Epistemic paradoxes.In 1961 Henry Kyburg pointed out that this policy conflicted with a principle of agglomeration: If you rationally believe p and rationally believe q then you rationally believe both p and q. Little pictures of the same scene should sum to a bigger picture of the same scene. If rational belief can be based on an acceptance rule that only requires a high probability, there will be rational belief in a contradiction! To see why, suppose the acceptance rule permits belief in any proposition that has a probability of at least .99. Given a lottery with 100 tickets and exactly one winner, the probability of ‘Ticket n is a loser’ licenses belief. — SEP
Well let me ask you a question in return. If you have a reasonable belief p, and a reasonable unconnected scepticism q (say p - that aspirin is an effective painkiller, and q - that Bluebeard's treasure is buried on Easter Island), what is to be gained by forming the disjunction, (p v q) ? How does S advance his knowledge, or understanding or in any way profit from forming his disjunction? Does it enable a test of p, or the building of a deeper theory or something? — unenlightened
All you've did is criticise the tracking argument of epistemic closure, no? — Posty McPostface
I'm not sure it's valid.Yes, it certainly seems on the face of it that a deduction from probable p inherits (at least) the same probability.
IF (Improbably~p) THEN (improbably ~p v q)
This seems to be just as valid, only less probable. — unenlightened
This one has the same basic form asIF (probably p) THEN (probably (p v ~q). — unenlightened
I'm not sure this is valid either, for the same reasons as the first formula above.IF (Improbably~p) THEN (improbably ~p v ~q) — unenlightened
I have yet to see reason for concern.And these too. Does that worry you at all? It worries me. — unenlightened
This is interesting, but suggests primarily that a rational believer would not thus lump together such beliefs without constraint. It seems to me the problem should be resolved by recharacterizing the judgment informed by a grasp of the odds. Kyburg, or the designer of the "policy" Kyburg criticizes, has smuggled irrationally expressed beliefs into a rational person's head.In 1961 Henry Kyburg pointed out that this policy conflicted with a principle of agglomeration: If you rationally believe p and rationally believe q then you rationally believe both p and q. Little pictures of the same scene should sum to a bigger picture of the same scene. If rational belief can be based on an acceptance rule that only requires a high probability, there will be rational belief in a contradiction! To see why, suppose the acceptance rule permits belief in any proposition that has a probability of at least .99. Given a lottery with 100 tickets and exactly one winner, the probability of ‘Ticket n is a loser’ licenses belief. — SEP — unenlightened
Is there something in this article especially relevant to our case?
Surely someone better versed in the logic of probability than I could help us clear up this confusion. — Cabbage Farmer
IF (Improbably~p) THEN (improbably ~p v q) — unenlightened
IF (probably p) THEN (probably (p v ~q).
IF (Improbably~p) THEN (improbably ~p v ~q)
Well, the use of "probably" and "improbably" isn't very useful. Try replacing it with percentages, where (for example) "probably" is ">= 75%" and "improbably" is "<= 25%". — Michael
So far as I can see, that brings us right back to the beginning: How, according to you, is recourse to probabilistic analysis of Gettier's puzzles relevant to our evaluation of Gettier's arguments and our assessment of the conception of justified true belief as a criterion for knowledge? — Cabbage Farmer
Gettier's claim is that B(p) -> B(p v q) for all q. — unenlightened
I don't think it affects my argument; the implication conserves truth, and justification is no more truth than belief is. — unenlightened
If p is true then p ∨ q is true. Therefore, if there is strong evidence that p is true then there is strong evidence that p ∨ q is true. — Michael
That argument is invalid. — unenlightened
It is if you accept the principle that evidence is closed under entailment (or, more specifically, under disjunction introduction), which I do. Although clearly you don't. I honestly don't know how you go about convincing you of it. It's so obvious to me as to be pretty much axiomatic (like disjunction introduction itself). — Michael
No. The argument you presented is invalid. — unenlightened
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.