What they both have in common is that the full sentence appears truth-apt (since it has a subject and a predicate) until, of course, the content of the sentence is analyzed and the subject is found to not support the predication. It's a category mistake (as Michael earlier noted).
Then we are using "grounded" in a different way. I mean that the subject is resolved and supports the predication, whatever it may be. In this case, the subject doesn't support the grounded predication and so the sentence isn't truth-apt. (BTW, this was essentially Gilbert Ryle's solution to the liar-style sentences rather than Kripke's.)
Self-reference is generally fine. For example, "this sentence has ten words". The truth or falsity of this doesn't depend on the subject being truth-apt, only that its words can be counted. That is a valid predication and so the sentence is truth-apt.
If you agree the sentence is ungrounded, that entails that it is true, which contradicts being ungrounded.
— MindForged
It doesn't entail that since the sentence doesn't support truth predication (because, in turn, the subject of the sentence doesn't support grounded predication). But you're treating it as if it does.
whereas sentences (such as what the Liar refers to) are arguably truth-bearers — MindForged
The same inattention to grammar is the source of such paradoxes as 'the Liar ', 'the Class of Classes ...' and 'Impredicability'. When we ordinarily say 'That statement is false ', what we say promises a namely-rider, e.g. '... namely that to-day is Tuesday'. When we say 'The current statement is false' we are pretending either that no namely-rider is to be asked for or that the namely-rider is '... namely that the present statement is false'. If no namely-rider is to be asked for, then 'The current statement' does not refer to any statement. It is like saying 'He is asthmatic' while disallowing the question 'Who?' If, alternatively, it is pretended that there is indeed the namely-rider, '... namely that the current statement is false', the promise is met by an echo of that promise. If unpacked, our pretended assertion would run 'The current statement {namely, that the current statement [namely that the current statement (namely that the current statement ...'. The brackets are never closed; no verb is ever reached; no statement of which we can even ask whether it is true or false is ever adduced. — Gilbert Ryle, Heterologicality
"This sentence is ungrounded" is not applying a truth-predicate to itself, it merely asserts (as the solution purports) that it's ungrounded (which means it's true). — MindForged
The same inattention to grammar is the source of such paradoxes as 'the Liar ', 'the Class of Classes ...' and 'Impredicability' (Ryle)
[..]
Thus the liar sentence is not truth-apt. It doesn't actually assert anything
So the issue is with impredication (what I earlier called self-predication), — MindForged
The issue as I see it is not impredication, but whether the sentences in question have a truth-apt use.
The same inattention to grammar is the source of such paradoxes as 'the Liar ', 'the Class of Classes ...' and 'Impredicability'. — Gilbert Ryle
"This sentence is an English sentence" would ordinarily be unpacked as, "The sentence 'This sentence is an English sentence' is an English sentence". The inner sentence is not being used as an expression but is only being mentioned. If it were used as an expression, then infinite recursion would result.
Now consider a similar unpacking for the liar sentence, "The sentence 'This sentence is false' is false". For the outer 'false' to be predicable of the inner sentence, the inner sentence must be an expression. But since it is only being mentioned, it doesn't support truth predication. So it's a category mistake. Whether a category mistake or an infinite recursion, no truth-apt use is available for the liar sentence.
A far as I can tell, Ryle's argument is that the sin of the Liars family of paradoxes is that they make use of impredicative definitions, they are part of the thing they are defining, and that by doing this you can never get down to a truth-apt sentence because it the subject expands indefinitely. — MindForged
Many of the Paradoxes have to do with such things as statements about statements and epithets of epithets. So quotation-marks have to be employed. But the mishandling which generates the apparent antinomies consists not in mishandling quotation-marks but in treating referring expressions as fillings of their own namely-riders. — Gilbert Ryle, Heterologicality
His claim is that the impredication never gets anywhere, and so when run against "This sentence is an English sentence", it would, when you ask for the "namely-rider" come out (as per your Ryle's quote): "Namely, the current sentence{namely, the current sentence etc. — MindForged
Try this: "The sentence 'Snow is white is true' is true". The inner sentence is clearly true, we can predicate truth there. If "snow is white" is true, we can validly assert that "The sentence 'snow is white is true' is a true sentence" — MindForged
Ryle is arguing against cyclic expressions (fillings of their own namely-riders), but he is not arguing against mentions of the referring expression (where quotation-marks have to be employed). As he says in the same paper:
Yes, an infinite expansion results if the subject is always a truth-evaluable expression (as is indicated with the nested brackets). But that's not how we ordinarily use that sentence. Instead the referring expression is only mentioned (which I unpacked and indicated with quotation-marks in my previous post), not used as an expression. That's the use-mention distinction.
As explained in my previous post, that specific use would result in a category mistake for the liar sentence, since a mention of the referring expression would not be truth predicable.
For the outer 'false' to be predicable of the inner sentence, the inner sentence must be an expression. But since it is only being mentioned, it doesn't support truth predication.
That's fine. There's nothing wrong with nested expressions. The problems only arise with cyclic expressions.
This is not a use-mention issue, the inner sentence is capable of being true even if it's only being mentioned. — MindForged
Consider the sentence, "'Snow' has four letters and is cold". Snow is mentioned, but that mention is not something that can be cold, only the snow itself is. So the "is cold" predication is a category mistake (specifically, a use-mention error). However we could apply an interpretive rule and say that in such circumstances, the "is cold" predication disquotes the mention and so is really saying that snow is cold. This would unpack as, "'Snow' has four letters and snow is cold". Such a rule would tolerate the above sentence and allow it to be truth-apt.
Now compare that with "'2+2=4' has three numbers in it and is true". My claim is that the mention of '2+2=4' is not something that can be true, but the expression (or use) of '2+2=4' is. If so, then the truth-predication disquotes the mentioned expression and uses it. This would unpack as, "'2+2=4' has three numbers in it and 2+2=4".
Since "This sentence is an English sentence" doesn't contain a truth-predicate, the referring expression is only mentioned, not used (i.e., only the surface aspects of the sentence are referred to). Whereas in the liar sentence, the truth-predication disquotes the mention and uses the referring expression. Thus it is cyclic.
I know that's the contention but you haven't explained why truth and falsity predicates are subject to a different set of rules than other predicates which can apply to quoted sentences. — MindForged
" '2+2=4' is true"
On your view, does this work? — MindForged
This sentence is true. — MindForged
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.