• Belter
    89
    Frege's account to identity statements in natural language fails insofar it does not incorporate the meta-linguistic nature of these. In mathematics, an identity is an equality true for all possible values, meanwhile a equation is true for at leas one.
    Frege thought that natural language equalities such as
    (1) Venus is Hesperus
    are like mathematical identities, that is, they are informative tautologies (with other form that the redundant one "a = a"; for example "x + 2 = x + 4 /2").
    However, we can understand (1) both as
    (2) 'Venus' is (the Latin name of the planet) Hesperus;
    and
    (3) 'Venus' is (the Latin translation of the ancient Greek name) 'Hesperus'
    In (2) we assume that 'Hesperus' designates a planet, so any other name or defined description whit the same reference such as "the Evening Star" can substitutes it preserving its truth-value. But in (3), 'Hesperus' does not designate other thing than itself, so replacement is not possible.
    The Frege's puzzle is dissipated when we consider that natural languages identities have two "senses": they can be between two names and between a name and an object.
    Which do you think is the mistake in this analysis?

  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    Frege raised his puzzle with the statement
    1A) Hesperus is Phosphorus.
    So, even if that statement could be metalinguistically ambivalent, it is not so in the way your statement (3) is concerned, since "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" are words from the same language. However, perhaps there is a way of expressing the ambivalence you believe Frege overlooked if we consider 1A) above, rather than your statement (1)? Over to you on that score.

    Personally, I think Frege overlooked a different issue for his sense/reference distinction. His fundamental claim is that there can be no informative identity statements of the form
    4) A is A.
    But it is possible to construct a story (I'm thinking of Mark Twain's "Million Pound Bank Note") where it would make sense for someone to say something along the lines:
    5) Henry Adams is Henry Adams!
    and be expressing a discovery.
    There are also more mundane cases where someone might be expressing something informatiive with a statement along the lines
    6) Well, you know, John is John, so you shouldn't expect anything else from him.

    It may be that unpacking these examples will in fact lead in the direction of your ideas, though, but we'll see.
  • Belter
    89
    1A) Hesperus is Phosphorus.MetaphysicsNow

    This is a mistake but I think that it does not invalidates my argument. The same analysis can be made:

    (1) Hesperus is Phosporus
    A) (name-name) Hesperus is (other name than, synonym with) Phosporus
    B) (name-objetc) Hesperus is (the name of the planet) Phosporus

    Statements such as "John is John" in your example, insofar I understand them, presuppose information without that it is not possible to make sense of it (for example, "John is stubborn", etc.), so they are only apparent identities.
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k

    I don't understand what you're saying.

    (1) "Hesperus" = "Phosphorus"
    (2) Hesperus = Phosphorus

    (1) is just false, and (2) is the claim that "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" designate the same object.

    Other ways of switching around use and mention, such as

    (3) "Hesperus" = Phosphorus

    might not come out at all like you expect. We say things like this when the quotes indicate something fake about the name, like at the end of a Scooby-Doo mystery; or we end up with a start on Haddock's Eyes.

    So what is it Frege is getting wrong?

    (Btw, I don't think of names, unlike descriptions, as ever being translated, though they do get localized. It's an odd area.)
  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    Statements such as "John is John" in your example, insofar I understand them, presuppose information without that it is not possible to make sense of it
    Kind of my issue with Frege - the assumption is that syntax and semantics is the whole story for natural language, whereas it is not (although it might be for formal languages).

    Still not clear what mistake you think Frege is making though.
  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    Btw, I don't think of names, unlike descriptions, as ever being translated, though they do get localized. It's an odd area.

    Interesting ones are place names - London and Londres for instance: Kripke makes use of that in his A Puzzle About Belief.
  • BlueBanana
    873
    The issue is Hesperus is not Phosphorus. They are both Venus but that's like saying I'm a banana, Belter has eaten a banana, therefore I'm dead because I was eaten by Belter.
  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    What are you talking about?
    Bluebanana is a banana.
    Belter has eaten a banana.
    Therefore Belter has eaten BlueBanana

    That's just an invalid argument.

    Hesperus = Venus
    Venus = Phosphorus
    Therefore Hesperus = Phosphorus

    Is a valid and sound argument based on the transitivity of identity.
  • Belter
    89
    Hesperus = Venus
    Venus = Phosphorus
    Therefore Hesperus = Phosphorus
    MetaphysicsNow

    It is a valid argument on the assumption that 'Venus' in the first equality has the same linguistic function than in the second one.
    We can think the first as the name of a planet and the second as the name of itself, so only in "Hesperus=Venus" we can say "Hesperus is the Evening Star", but not in "Venus=Hesperus".
  • Belter
    89
    Still not clear what mistake you think Frege is making though.MetaphysicsNow

    My problem with Frege is his that he account natural languages equalities by reducting them to formal ones, so the problem of saying/showing emerges when we think about concrete examples.
  • Belter
    89
    Is a valid and sound argument based on the transitivity of identity.MetaphysicsNow

    The natural languages equalities with the name-object form are symmetrical preserving the linguistic function (saying/showing). For example, "'Venus' is Hesperus" can be transformed into "Hesperus is 'Venus'" but not into "'Hesperus' is Venus". That is, there are natural languages equalities which are identification sentences, in which a name or defined description designates an object and the other one to itself.
  • BlueBanana
    873
    Hesperus = Venus
    Venus = Phosphorus
    Therefore Hesperus = Phosphorus
    MetaphysicsNow

    BlueBanana = banana
    The banana Belter ate = banana
    Therefore I am the banana Belter ate, and therefore I am dead.
  • Michael
    15.6k


    False analogy. "Venus" is a proper noun that denotes a specific object, whereas "banana" isn't.
  • BlueBanana
    873
    The analogy is a valid one. In informal language "a is b" can mean "a=b" but also "a∈b". Hesperus is Venus but Venus isn't always Hesperus, and therefore the meaning of "is" in the context is closer to the latter one.

    Hesperus is a Venus in a specific state, and these states of existence are not specific objects but classes.

    The claim that "Hesperus = Venus" is as invalid as "BlueBanana = a banana".
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k

    I'm still not clear what you're saying.

    Everyone agrees these assertions achieve the same purpose:

    (1) Hesperus and Phosphorus are the same object.
    (2) "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" are different names for the same object.
    (3) "Hesperus" is another name for Phosphorus.
    (4) "Phosphorus" is another name for Hesperus.

    The puzzle to be solved is that names for the same object should be substitutable salva veritate. No problem saying

    (5) Phosphorus and Hesperus are the same object.

    But this is weird:

    (6) Phosphorus and Phosphorus are the same object.
    (7) "Phosphorus" is another name for Phosphorus.

    So you remember that that names are substitutable salva veritate only in extensional contexts -- it's practically the defining feature of extensional contexts -- and conclude that this is an intensional context somehow, thus akin to

    (8) Pat doesn't know that Hesperus is Phosphorus.

    You can't say this is equivalent to

    (9) Pat doesn't know that Hesperus is Hesperus.

    Everyone's clear on that much. But we don't have an obvious tip-off in sentences like (1)-(7) -- no propositional attitude verb like "know", no "that" clause.

    Frege's solution, you could say, is to say there's always something a bit like an intensional component: the sense (Sinn) rather than the reference (Bedeutung).

    It's not a solution everyone loves, because pure extensionality is much cleaner. [Insert a hundred years of discussion here.]

    For natural language, maybe there's a solution that just treats these types of statements involving names and identity as special. The thing is, Frege was really looking at mathematics, where it seems awkward to say that equations are just a special case. ("2 + 2 = 4" is exactly the same issue.) But hey maybe they are. Mathematics as a domain is a deliberate narrowing of what we might say.
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k
    Kind of my issue with Frege - the assumption is that syntax and semantics is the whole story for natural language, whereas it is not (although it might be for formal languages).MetaphysicsNow

    I was going to pass this by because you're kinda right, but there's more to say here, coming off my last post.

    Say you want to approach the natural language issue by looking at the pragmatics -- when do we have a use for statements like "Hesperus and Phosphorus are the same object"? That looks fruitful. You'd start by noting that there's "no point" in telling someone that "Hesperus is Hesperus" (which probably isn't quite true), and go from there.

    But something about that isn't quite right. The reason we feel there are different uses for "Hesperus is Hesperus" and "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is precisely because we feel they don't contain the same information. So it is with "4 = 4" and "2 + 2 = 4". It's that sense that these two equations carry different information -- they "say different things" -- that drives their different uses. So the semantics drives the pragmatics here.

    We could then circle back to Frege and look at the truth conditions, either in terms of possible worlds or in terms of verification, and confirm that there's a semantic difference.
  • Dawnstorm
    242
    But something about that isn't quite right. The reason we feel there are different uses for "Hesperus is Hesperus" and "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is precisely because we feel they don't contain the same information. So it is with "4 = 4" and "2 + 2 = 4". It's that sense that these two equations carry different information -- they "say different things" -- that drives their different uses. So the semantics drives the pragmatics here.Srap Tasmaner

    I don't think it's quite that simple.

    Take your sentence (3): "Hesperus" is another name for Phosphorus.

    First, look at the word "another" and it's reference. If there's "another" name, there has to be a default name that the speaker would expect the hearer to know (pragmatics). But given a context such as "What's Hesperus?" the speaker won't know which name this is until s/he arrives at "Phosphorus". That is "Phosphorus" in that sentence does pragmatic double duty: it tells you which object it is, but it also raises the topic of that planet having the name "Phosphorus". That's exactly why ["Hesperus" is another name for "Hesperus".] is weird. It has everything to do with "another", and little with Hesperus/Phosphorus. The weirdness can go away if we take care of this in context:

    A: What's "Hesperus"?
    B: "Hesperus" is another name for Phosphorus.
    A: Hm? So what's another name?
    B: Huh?
    A: Other than "Hesperus".
    B: *flat tone of voice* "Phosphorus" is another name for Phosphorus.
    A: *embarrassed* Oh.

    Note that the word "another" no longer refers forward, now. The default name ("Hesperus") has been brought up in the exchange before and is the obvious referent for "another" here. The syntax is different from the earlier sentence. And the misunderstanding in this exchange is derived from A not noticing the double duty "Phosphorus" is doing in the early sentence.

    **

    A second (but to me less interesting) complication is that the planet Venus has the respective names in specific contexts only: even if you see the same object, you can't see the Evening Star in the morning - if you activate all its denotations and connotations (which you don't have to, but which you activate is a matter of pragmatics). Even though "Hesperus" and "Phosphoros" refer to the same planet, they're not complete synonyms, though they may be functional synonyms in many context (in most of which, we'd use "Venus" these days with overwhelming likelihood).
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k

    Agree completely that the use of "another" implies some stuff I was ignoring, much of which you described nicely.

    There are so many ways to do this. Some run into the issue you and @BlueBanana raise that these terms are only (supposed to be) used in certain situations.

    (1) You can call me "Pat".
    (2) You can call the Morning Star "the Evening Star".

    (1) might turn out only to apply in a range of situations, not all, or not, but it's tempting to say (2) is just, well, if not wrong, then really weird.

    Whether the use of a particular name (or nickname or description) is appropriate may not change the truth conditions of sentences it's used in, appropriately or not. I think if my son pointed at Venus of an evening and said, "Look, the Morning Star has risen," that would be true if a bit arch.
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k
    More weirdness with definite descriptions. A run in baseball is only "the go-ahead run" if the game is tied before the run scores. If the game's not tied, that description just doesn't seem to have a reference.

    With Venus, we cross into territory where the object is persistent and the description can be capitalized into a Name. Maybe others feel the description still bleeds through, but I wish I had a clearer example.

    ADDED: Sometimes it refers to a possible run because you can do the math. Announcers talk this way: if your team's down by one with a runner on base, they might describe the player coming up to bat as "the go-ahead run". You still can't score the go-ahead run if you're already ahead.
  • Dawnstorm
    242
    Whether the use of a particular name (or nickname or description) is appropriate may not change the truth conditions of sentences it's used in, appropriately or not. I think if my son pointed at Venus of an evening and said, "Look, the Morning Star has risen," that would be true if a bit arch.Srap Tasmaner

    Well, true. But focussing on the sentence's truth condition may itself be missing the point. I don't know your son (or even if you have one), so I'm not trying to get personal here. But your son might say the sentence in full knowledge of this thread and intend it as a rib, because you care about things he does not, in which case the word choice "Morning Star" indicates irony, but you won't find the irony if you focus on the referential object and truth condition. That could cause a hiccup in the conversation, which could have been expected (or even intended) - a sort of private in-joke thematising differences in outlook.

    It's not that easy to do something like this in a formal system like maths.
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k

    That's all dead on. Sometimes when he and I sit on the front porch, I teach him a little philosophy.

    With "the go ahead run" I was imagining the case of someone learning about baseball and misusing that phrase as meaning "run".

    "Did we score another go-ahead run, Daddy?"
    "No, sweetie, this one was tacked on -- only the first one this inning was the go ahead run."

    So there's your hiccup.

    (The example I really wanted to use was, "Did we score another equalizer, Daddy?" but I don't even know if football announcers still say, "It's the equalizer!" like Toby Charles did.)
  • Dawnstorm
    242
    Heh. I don't know much about sports and very little about baseball, so I was staring at your post and didn't really understand it, until the edit. So basically, if you're already ahead you can make a go-further-ahead run, except that nobody says that. (My confusion stemmed from an instinctive association of "go ahead" with "give the go-ahead", so I was sort of expecting some sort of rule bound complication...)

    The thing about language is that it's complex, but easy to use. Easy to use, hard to analyse - to the extent that sometimes analysing it can make you less effective at using it because you start seeing problems that should be there but aren't. Describing language as a formal system is still useful (especially in second language learning), but, IMO, it's important to realise that language isn't actually a formal system: it's a type of social behaviour that uses cues from outside to resolve formal ambiguities (famous example: "We saw her duck.") and in this way uses these ambiguities for versatility. On writing boards, they tell you that "you must know the rules to break them." But I think that's the wrong way round: "you must know the rules to follow them" - if you're literate you can write. When it comes to language, right/wrong is often open to negotiation, and the things that are not open to negotiation are usually not talked about (if you're ever bored look up the difference between nominative-accusative languages and ergative-absolutive languages and see how often that comes up).
  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    @BlueBanana
    BlueBanana = banana
    The banana Belter ate = banana
    Therefore I am the banana Belter ate, and therefore I am dead.

    Nope,
    BlueBanana = a banana
    The banana Belter ate = a banana
    Therefore I am the banana Belter ate, and therefore I am dead.

    Invalid argument. "BlueBanana = banana" is not a statement - ever heard anyone say something like "John is identical to cabbage, therefore John is identical to the cabbage" and thought they were on to something?
  • MetaphysicsNow
    311
    @BlueBanana
    My problem with Frege is his that he account natural languages equalities by reducting them to formal ones, so the problem of saying/showing emerges when we think about concrete examples.
    With this, however, I agree.
  • Belter
    89
    I'm still not clear what you're saying.Srap Tasmaner

    The method of substitution salva veritae is valid, for example, in mathematical equations (x-5= y+2; y=3-x; => x=3-x +2+5 => x=5). In natural languages identities, the principle of substitution is not valid when names are designating to themself. In "Hesperus is Phosphorus", a priori, we can not know which member plays the role of showing. In mathematics, both terms, a priori, designates the same reference ("x" and "y" designate numerical values).
    If neither "a" nor "b" are showing in natural language indentities, but saying, then "a=b" => "a=a". But we do not use natural language identities to say non-informative tautologies but to make identifications between words (synonymy relation) and a word and an object (reference relation).
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k
    But we do not use natural language identities to say non-informative tautologies but to make identifications between words (synonymy relation) and a word and an object (reference relation).Belter

    Okay, I think I understand what you're saying now.

    Frege analyzes "Hesperus is Phosphorus" as asserting the identity of the objects picked out by the names "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" -- they refer to the same thing.

    On your analysis, "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is one of these:

    (1a) "Hesperus" refers to Phosphorus.
    (1b) "Phosphorus" refers to Hesperus.
    (2) "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" are synonyms.

    At least one of the names is implicitly being mentioned rather than used, and that blocks substitution. But it blocks substitution only within the quotation marks, so you still need a way to block

    (1a') "Hesperus" refers to Hesperus.
    (1b') "Phosphorus" refers to Phosphorus.

    and this you get by arguing that we don't (cannot?) know which of (1a) or (1b) is intended. (Is "intended" right? Or is it that there is no "fact of the matter" as to which analysis is right?)

    If we're unable to use (1a) or (1b), we must take "Hesperus is Phosphorus" as (2).

    (2) asserts the synonymy of the names used; Frege asserts the identity of the things named.

    But what is the meaning of a name?

    If the meaning of a name is its reference, then asserting two names have the same meaning is asserting they have the same reference, refer to the same object. Isn't that exactly where Frege starts?

    Sorry, still a little confused.
  • Belter
    89
    If we're unable to use (1a) or (1b), we must take "Hesperus is Phosphorus" as (2).Srap Tasmaner

    Thank you for your exposition of my argument. However, I think that (1a') and (1b') have not equivalent to the a=a identities of Frege. They are with the form: 'a'=a and 'b'=b, so the properties of the equality relation are not the same.
  • Srap Tasmaner
    5k

    I wouldn't have even thought of "... refers to ..." as being an identity relation. It's clearly not. A symbol is not the thing it symbolizes. I don't think Frege anywhere suggests that reference is an identity relation.

    How about this one?

    (1a'') "Hesperus" refers to Venus.

    Frege's approach here is to say that this has the same truth value as (1a) and (1a'), but that there are real semantic differences between these sentences. The referring expressions in each refer to the same object, the planet Venus, and that's what determines truth value; but each expression specifies or determines the reference in a different way -- i.e., they have different senses but the same reference. Anyway, that's where Frege lands, as I understand it.
  • Belter
    89


    Thank for your analysis. My claim is just that. The "Hesperus is Phosphorus" sentences are only apparent "identities", but actually they are identification assertions (fixation of a reference, extensional interpretation) and synonymy ones (fixation of sense, intentional interpretation).
  • Srap TasmanerAccepted Answer
    5k

    Frege's view is that "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" have different senses but refer to the same object. Since he splits meaning into two "components", it's not clear if you and he agree on what "synonymy" means here.

    Still not sure where you stand, sorry.
  • Belter
    89
    Frege's view is that "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" have different senses but refer to the same object.Srap Tasmaner

    Yes. But he also said that it is an identity sentence, and "synthetic a posteriori". My view is that "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is not a true "identity", and it has two "analytic" senses (commented above; in kantian sense) neglected by Frege. Thus, Frege wrote the following (On sense and reference):

    The reasons that seem to favour it are the following: a = a and a = b are obviously sentences of
    different cognitive value: a = a holds a priori, and, following Kant, should be called
    analytic, while sentences of the form a = b often contain valuable extensions of our
    knowledge and cannot always be justified a priori.


    He thought that "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is not "analytic" but "synthetic a posteriori". I arrive to the same conclusion than Frege (we must distinguish sense and reference, for concepts and sentences as a hole) but by other way (supposing that a=b is "analytic" so it is a "linguistic" or "conventional" equality sentence).
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.