But then something important still usually feels lost in translation when they have to go from abstractions back to words. And what is lost is the clarity gained by abstracting from words to abstractions. — apokrisis
In ordinary analysis the continuum R is connected in the sense that it cannot be split into two non empty subsets neither of which contains a limit point of the other. In smooth infinitesimal analysis it has the vastly stronger property of indecomposability: it cannot be split in any way whatsoever into two disjoint nonempty subsets. — SEP article, Continuity and Infinitesimal
I think that's the fundamental problem here, with Deleuze, and with the aesthetic approach to epistemology in general. Insofar as it purports to be a sub-representational account of thought, it cannot be represented - it literally cannot be thought or talked about. — Aaron R
I think this passage is explaining what I was trying to say... that if you have a cake for which the law of excluded middle fails, you can't just slice the cake. — Mongrel
No, but you can make the law of the excluded middle apply by imposing a rule which would, on that basis, arbitrarily split said cake. — StreetlightX
It appears that when you asked how many elements belong to the empty set and came up with one, you were already thinking in discrete terms.This is how you do it: Take a set, S. Then, you find the compliment of S, which just so happens to be the empty set, ∅ (S-S = ∅). Now that you’ve done this, you’re in a great position because the empty set plays a double role. Not only is it the compliment of S, it is also a subset of S, to the extent that every set contains the empty set. Note that the empty set is thus is both ‘inside’ and ‘outside of S, occupying exactly the paradoxical place which we said a rule for distinction would occupy.
Having done this, you can generate the entirety of the number line by asking how many elements belong to the empty set (=1), and then recursively asking how many elements belong to that set and so on ad infinitum. Ta da. You’ve now digitised the continuum. — StreetlightX
Zero, like negation, is a higher-order, reflexive rule about the continuum on the basis of which we can divide it, provided we cannot situate either negation nor zero properly in that continuum itself. — StreetlightX
It appears that when you asked how many elements belong to the empty set and came up with one, you were already thinking in discrete terms. — Mongrel
Doesn't strike me as intuitional to say that Zero is a higher-order, reflexive rule about the continuum on the basis of which we can divide it. In fact it makes close to Zero sense to me. — Mongrel
Um... what's the basis for this rule, then? — Mongrel
Take it up with math, not with me. — StreetlightX
This is how you do it: Take a set, S. Then, you find the compliment of S, which just so happens to be the empty set, ∅ (S-S = ∅). Now that you’ve done this, you’re in a great position because the empty set plays a double role. Not only is it the compliment of S, it is also a subset of S, to the extent that every set contains the empty set. Note that the empty set is thus is both ‘inside’ and ‘outside of S, occupying exactly the paradoxical place which we said a rule for distinction would occupy.
Having done this, you can generate the entirety of the number line by asking how many elements belong to the empty set (=1), and then recursively asking how many elements belong to that set and so on ad infinitum. Ta da. You’ve now digitised the continuum. — StreetlightX
Here is where things get complicated, but I'll try and do my best to explicate the ideas. If you recall that what's at stake is a 'critique of pure logic', then the idea is to introduce 'extra-formal’/‘real' constraints on the the exercise of what might otherwise be purely syntactic logical manipulations which might simply follow transitively from an established set of axioms. For Deleuze, intensive differences are precisely what force 'real life' (extra-formal) constraints of 'existence' on logic, making logic no longer a formal and arbitrary play of symbolic manipulation, but beholden to a specific existential situation, as it were. — StreetlightX
it seems to me our differences come down to whether or not one accepts or rejects pansemiosis. — StreetlightX
This is how you do it: Take a set, S. Then, you find the compliment of S, which just so happens to be the empty set, ∅ (S-S = ∅). Now that you’ve done this, you’re in a great position because the empty set plays a double role. Not only is it the compliment of S, it is also a subset of S, to the extent that every set contains the empty set. Note that the empty set is thus is both ‘inside’ and ‘outside of S, occupying exactly the paradoxical place which we said a rule for distinction would occupy. — StreetlightX
Having done this, you can generate the entirety of the number line by asking how many elements belong to the empty set (=1), and then recursively asking how many elements belong to that set and so on ad infinitum. Ta da. You’ve now digitised the continuum. — StreetlightX
The problem, of course, as with any digitisation, is whether or not 0 belongs to it. The answer is strictly undecidable. Wilden: "zero is not simply a number as such, but a rule for a relation between integers… zero is implicitly defined as a meta-integer, and indeed its definition is what provides the RULE for the series of integers which follow it.” Zero, like negation, is a higher-order, reflexive rule about the continuum on the basis of which we can divide it, provided we cannot situate either negation nor zero properly in that continuum itself. — StreetlightX
I don't know if you're using math metaphorically here, but the compliment of S is going to be relative to some set X. If X = S, then, yeah, the empty set is its complement. To say that the empty set is both inside and outside of S is a bit of cheat. It's a subset of S but not an element of S (in general). I don't doubt that your getting at something interesting about rules for distinction, though. — Hoo
Set theory probably has the problem that it builds in the distinction SX hopes to derive. It's weakness is that its brackets that bound possibility are themselves so definite and unexplained as features of the world. — apokrisis
So set theory could be naturalised by recognising the opposed brackets as standing for complementary poles of being - the opposed limits you need to arrive at to have the third thing of the individuated something that can now stand between. — apokrisis
As I see it, math is machine-like. "Here are formal definitions. Here are rules of inference. See how these definitions are related in terms of those rules of inference." The formal definitions tend to have intuitive appeal of course, but we're aren't allowed to use intuition directly. The ghost of intuition must be incarnated in the symbolism. — Hoo
As I see it, the formal definition of "set" tries to capture the intuition of "gathering up into a unity." All things as things are unities. The tail and the nose and the fur and so on have been gathered up as the dog, for instance. It's as there is always already a logical circle drawn around any particular thing, perhaps giving it its thing-hood, cutting it out from the background automatically. But then sets are also (intuitively) the extension of properties, which surely inspired the axiom of extensionality. — Hoo
I think we get this from writing R as (-inf, inf). — Hoo
I like dialectic. That's the process. The thesis swells (via anti-thesis then synthesis, repeat) and becomes more capable.I would argue that it is dialectic or dichotomistic metaphysics. That is what presents us with our "binary" choices. We can posit the axiom of continuity - having identified it as one of two choices. Reality could be fundamentally discrete or continuous. Well, let's pick continuous for the sake of argument and run with that, see where it leads. — apokrisis
The AC is often stated as the existence of a choice function. Are you sure you don't have another axiom in mind? I think the logical use of equality keeps things distinct in math generally, not just in set theory. We simply have x = y or not (x = y). All of x's properties are "naked" if we have the eyes to see it. Of course complicated deductions are not obvious, so some properties are invisible, although "already there" in some sense. (The relationship of time and classical logic is probably quite deep. )Well the relevant axiom is the axiom of choice. It starts by presuming individuated (crisp and not vague) things, events, properties, whatever. And given that is the case, forming collections becomes trivial in being trivially additive and subtractive. One can construct any unity (or deconstruct it to leave behind "nothing"). — apokrisis
The AC is often stated as the existence of a choice function. Are you sure you don't have another axiom in mind? I think the logical use of equality keeps things distinct in math generally, not just in set theory. — Hoo
How would it be established? Our most predictive/manipulative theory based on the real numbers? Or on geometric intuition of flow? — Hoo
That's right. Once you have axioms, you are good to go with the deductions. It all unfolds mechanically in a predestined fashion.
But what is the meta-theory about forming axioms - the semantic residue animating the unfolding syntax? — apokrisis
We can posit the axiom of continuity - having identified it as one of two choices. Reality could be fundamentally discrete or continuous. Well, let's pick continuous for the sake of argument and run with that, see where it leads. — apokrisis
So, as a philosophical axiom, we cannot just pick any axiom, it must be self-evident. We have evidence that objects are bounded, and "object" may be defined in such a way that an object is necessarily bounded, so we could pick an axiom such as "objects are bounded".
With respect to continuity though, as I stated earlier in the thread, that some aspect of reality is continuous, is implied through observations of reality, and inductive reason. Since it is implied, that some aspect of reality is continuous, this is not self-evident, we cannot pick continuity as an axiom. The assumption of continuity must be justified. — Metaphysician Undercover
But anyway, are bounds not self-evidently continuous? So if there are (discrete) objects, then continuity is also an aspect of your axiom of object boundedness? — apokrisis
A dotted line makes a non-continuous boundary. — Metaphysician Undercover
We simply assume that boundaries are continuous, as a mathematical type of axiom, an ideal which has not been justified. Then the boundaries which are shown to us do not fulfill the qualifications of the ideal, so we deny that they are boundaries. Now the ideal boundary must be justified as a true example, or it should be dismissed as not properly representing the boundaries which we know of. — Metaphysician Undercover
What I have in mind is the assumption that you can just pick out individuals and throw them into different contexts freely. But what if that identity was contextual? — apokrisis
So let me see if I have this straight, the position you're arguing. It is useless to seek self-evident axioms, as there is no such thing, because meaning is context dependent. Therefore we should only use mathematical axioms, as apokrisis suggests, which have crisply defined, and fixed meaning within a mathematical system. This entails that anything which is logically possible is also true.We can't get the metaphysical/philosophical axioms that MU mentions because meanings are context dependent. — Hoo
You are contradicting your proposed axiom though. The axiom was that boundaries are continuous. I objected, saying that this is not self-evident. How does proposing two types of boundaries, continuous and non-continuous, help to solve the issue? — Metaphysician Undercover
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.