• TheMadFool
    13.8k
    Curry's paradox as attributed to Haskell Curry (1900 - 1982) and Martin Hugo Lob (1921 - 2006):

    Formal proof:

    The main statement is: If this sentence is true, then P2

    Let P1 = if this sentence is true then P2

    Further translation yields P1 = P1 > P2

    1. P1 = (P1 > P2)....assume
    2. P1 > P1......Id
    3. P1 > (P1 > P2)....1 Id
    4. (P1 & P1) > P2....3 Exp
    5. P1 > P2............4 Taut
    6.P1....from 1, 5
    7. P2....5, 6 MP

    Informal proof:

    The statement P1 = If P1 then P2. Assuming P1 means both P1 and if P1 then P2 are true. Apply modus ponens and P2 is true which means if P1 then P2 is true. We know then that P1 is true because P1 = P1 > P2. Use modus ponens one more time and we get P2.

    The paradox is that P2 can be any imaginable proposition.

    As another way of proving anything, distinct from the more familiar ex falso quodlibet, I'd like some opinions on this paradox.
  • Pfhorrest
    4.6k
    "If P1 then P2" translates to "P2 or not P1", so assuming P1 = "if P1 then P2" is just assuming that P2 (or else self-contradiction), and of course you can prove any P2 by starting from the assumption that either it is true or there is a contradiction (because even if there is a contradiction, that will let you prove anything too).

    Consider for example: "If this sentence is true then I am the Pope of Mars." That just means "I am the Pope of Mars or this sentence is false." If we believe that sentence, then we disregard "this sentence is false" and so conclude that I am the Pope of Mars. If we instead assume I am not the Pope of Mars (because there is no such thing and I'm not even Martian-Catholic anyway), we can conclude that "this sentence is false", from which we can conclude anything, including that I am the Pope of Mars anyway, and also that I am not the Pope of Mars, at the same time if we want. You're basically just baking in an ex falso quodlibet into the premise.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    You're basically just baking in an ex falso quodlibet into the premise.Pfhorrest

    Where is the contradiction?
  • Michael
    15.8k
    1. P1 ≔ P1 → P2
    2. P1 → P2 ↔ ¬P1 ∨ P2
    3. P1 ≔ ¬P1 ∨ P2

    This sentence is false or I am a woman.

    I think that assuming P1 to be true is to assume that I am a woman. Is that really a paradox?
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    This sentence is false or I am a woman.

    I think that assuming P1 to be true is to assume that I am a woman. Is that really a paradox?
    Michael

    Curry's paradox begins as an assumption of the equivalence between the sentence P1: if this sentence is true then P2 which in logic is the following: P1 = P1 > P2. The conditional P1 > P2 is proven first (see the OP). Proving P1 > P2 amounts to proving P1; after all they are equivalent. Then using modus ponens we can prove P2. The claim to the title of a paradox lies in such statements being capable of proving, literally, anything, even contradictions.
  • Michael
    15.8k
    P1 is equivalent to “this sentence is false or P2”, so I think assuming P1 is to assume P2, not to prove it.
  • A Seagull
    615
    Formal proof:

    The main statement is: If this sentence is true, then P2

    Let P1 = if this sentence is true then P2

    Further translation yields P1 = P1 > P2

    1. P1 = (P1 > P2)....assume
    2. P1 > P1......Id
    3. P1 > (P1 > P2)....1 Id
    4. (P1 & P1) > P2....3 Exp
    5. P1 > P2............4 Taut
    6.P1....from 1, 5
    7. P2....5, 6 MP

    Informal proof:

    The statement P1 = If P1 then P2. Assuming P1 means both P1 and if P1 then P2 are true. Apply modus ponens and P2 is true which means if P1 then P2 is true. We know then that P1 is true because P1 = P1 > P2. Use modus ponens one more time and we get P2.

    The paradox is that P2 can be any imaginable proposition.

    As another way of proving anything, distinct from the more familiar ex falso quodlibet, I'd like some opinions on this paradox.
    TheMadFool



    Why do you claim that this is a 'proof'?

    What are the axioms and processes of inference for the logical system in which this 'proof' takes place?

    You seem to be assuming that 'truth' has a significance outside of the logical system of the proof.

    Whereas in fact 'truth' for a logical system is merely a label to indicate that the deduced theorem is consistent with the axioms and rules of inference of the system.
  • Pfhorrest
    4.6k
    Where is the contradiction?TheMadFool

    "This sentence is false."

    If P1 is "not P1", assuming P1 assumes a contradiction.

    So if P1 is "not-P1 or P2", assuming P1 assumes either a contradiction or P2.

    And "If P1 then P2" is logically equivalent to "not-P1 or P2", so if P1 is "if P1 then P2", same situation.

    P1 is equivalent to “this sentence is false or P2”, so I think assuming P1 is to assume P2, not to prove it.Michael

    :100:

    A loose more idiomatic way of phrasing P1 would be "If I'm right, P2" or "Unless I'm wrong, P2." That's basically just a way of asserting P2.
  • A Seagull
    615
    Where is the contradiction? — TheMadFool
    "This sentence is false."

    If P1 is "not P1", assuming P1 assumes a contradiction.

    So if P1 is "not-P1 or P2", assuming P1 assumes either a contradiction or P2.

    And "If P1 then P2" is logically equivalent to "not-P1 or P2", so if P1 is "if P1 then P2", same situation.

    P1 is equivalent to “this sentence is false or P2”, so I think assuming P1 is to assume P2, not to prove it. — Michael
    :100:

    A loose more idiomatic way of phrasing P1 would be "If I'm right, P2" or "Unless I'm wrong, P2." That's basically just a way of asserting P2.
    Pfhorrest

    This is what happens when you play with words without meaning or logic...you end up with nonsense.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    P1 is equivalent to “this sentence is false or P2”, so I think assuming P1 is to assume P2, not to prove it.Michael

    Agreed, using the implication equivalence. However this doesn't refute the argument because...

    ~P1 v P2 := P1. Assuming P1 means ~~P1. and so we get P2.

    The idea is to prove the conditional P1 > P2 and this is achieved by assuming P1 := ~P1 v P2 := P1 > P2 which basically is roughly speaking a compound proposition since it contains both P1 and P1 > P2. It oddly reminds me of the loaded question fallacy an example of which is "have you stopped stealing?"

    Anyway, once the conditional P1 > P2 is proven we can use modus ponens since P1 > P2 is logically equivalent to P1.

    No contradiction I'm afraid.

    P1 > P2 := ~P1 v P2

    1. P1 > P1 := P1 > (~P1 v P2)
    2. ~P1 v (~P1 v P2)......1 imp
    3. (~P1 v ~P1) v P2.....2 assoc
    4. ~P1 v P2...............3 taut

    No contradiction.
    This is what happens when you play with words without meaning or logic...you end up with nonsense.A Seagull

    Would you like to read the above replies.
  • Pfhorrest
    4.6k
    I don't think anyone is saying that the proof is invalid, just that it's conclusion is trivial. All conclusions of valid arguments are baked into their premises, that's how truth preservation works, but the conclusion of this argument is so transparently baked into the premise that it's not really surprising or a paradox that it can be proven. Or that "anything can be proven this way", because consider for comparison an argument that "From 'If TRUE then P' we can prove P, for any P". That's correct, but it's hardly surprising, because 'if TRUE then P" is pretty much just asserting P.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    I don't think anyone is saying that the proof is invalid, just that it's conclusion is trivial. All conclusions of valid arguments are baked into their premises, that's how truth preservation works, but the conclusion of this argument is so transparently baked into the premise that it's not really surprising or a paradox that it can be proven. Or that "anything can be proven this way", because consider for comparison an argument that "From 'If TRUE then P' we can prove P, for any P". That's correct, but it's hardly surprising, because 'if TRUE then P" is pretty much just asserting P.Pfhorrest

    Well, I humbly beg to disagree. Paradoxes usually aren't trivial since they indicate something unsolvable or unexpected; paradoxes reveal either errors in our intuition or major issues with the system that generates them. Curry's paradox is comparable in effect to contradictions in making everything provable, a proposition and its negation. That is a problem, a big one, isn't it?
  • A Seagull
    615
    This is what happens when you play with words without meaning or logic...you end up with nonsense. — A Seagull
    Would you like to read the above replies.
    TheMadFool

    I would prefer you to admit that you can't answer my questions nor respond sensibly to my comments.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    I would prefer you to admit that you can't answer my questions nor respond sensibly to my comments.A Seagull

    Perhaps you'd like to hear it straight from the horse's mouth...Curry's paradox
  • A Seagull
    615
    I would prefer you to admit that you can't answer my questions nor respond sensibly to my comments. — A Seagull
    Perhaps you'd like to hear it straight from the horse's mouth...Curry's paradox
    TheMadFool

    It is nonsense for the reasons cited above.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    It is nonsense for the reasons cited aboveA Seagull

    :up: :ok:
  • Andrew M
    1.6k
    The main statement is: If this sentence is true, then P2TheMadFool

    The problem with the Curry sentence is that it's not evaluable and thus not truth-apt. The truth value of the antecedent depends on the truth value of the sentence. But the truth value of the sentence depends on the truth value of the antecedent (and consequent). So the sentence has a circular dependency.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    The problem with the Curry sentence is that it's not evaluable and thus not truth-apt. The truth value of the antecedent depends on the truth value of the sentence. But the truth value of the sentence depends on the truth value of the antecedent (and consequent). So the sentence has a circular dependency.Andrew M

    The sentence can be either true or false.

    If it's false then it's antecedent is false and that means the entire sentence evaluates to true.

    If it is true, well, then it's true.
  • Andrew M
    1.6k
    You're just plugging in values to see what happens. That's not the same as evaluating the sentence. It has the same issue as the Liar and Truth Teller sentences.

    Another way of stating it is that each of those sentences are ungrounded. There is nothing that determines their truth or falsity (i.e., they don't meaningfully assert anything).
  • Pfhorrest
    4.6k
    To assume P1 as a premise is to assign P1 the truth value of "TRUE", and we can therefore substitute "TRUE" for P1 anywhere it occurs within P1 itself without changing the evaluation of the whole of P1.

    So P1: "If P1 then P2" evaluates to "If TRUE then P2". Necessarily TRUE (that's what it means), therefore P2.

    So yeah, you can use this to "prove" any P2, but that's just because you're transparently baking P2, whatever it is, into the single premise of the argument. This isn't a paradox, it's just a really useless trivially valid argument, the cogency and therefore soundness of which depends entirely upon the truth of P2, which is what's in question.

    A useful argument shows the answer to a controversial question follows from uncontroversial premises. The whole reason why question-begging or circular reasoning is problematic is because it puts a controversial position into the premises, and thus can't be used to convince anyone who doesn't already accept that. This is merely a very transparent case of doing exactly that.


    (Additionally, to assume P1 is false is to assign P1 the truth-value of "FALSE", which makes P1 evaluate to "if FALSE then P2" and the assumption of the falsehood of P1 equivalent to: "not(if FALSE then P2)", which is equivalent to "FALSE and not-P2".)
  • A Seagull
    615
    The sentence can be either true or false.

    If it's false then it's antecedent is false and that means the entire sentence evaluates to true.

    If it is true, well, then it's true
    TheMadFool

    The problem is that there is no well-defined or logical process for determining whether a statement is 'true' or 'false'. And without such a process one has to resort to some arbitrary or even random process; with the result that one ends up in some meaningless la la land.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    You're just plugging in values to see what happens. That's not the same as evaluating the sentenceAndrew M

    How would you evaluate a conditional sentence in a way different to the way I did the Curry's sentence?
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    So yeah, you can use this to "prove" any P2, but that's just because you're transparently baking P2, whatever it is, into the single premise of the argument.Pfhorrest

    Ok

    This isn't a paradox, it's just a really useless trivially valid argumentPfhorrest

    :chin:

    If we can prove any P2 then it has to be a paradox, right?
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    The problem is that there is no well-defined or logical process for determining whether a statement is 'true' or 'false'.A Seagull

    Truth tables can be used to explore all possibilities.
  • Pfhorrest
    4.6k
    It doesn't prove every P2 simultaneously, so it's not a paradox as in it gives rise to a contradiction. It proves whatever you plug in for "P2" in the premise, but in a ridiculously trivial way. It's only half a step removed from being the argument "P2. Therefore P2", which can also prove anything you plug in for P2. It's literally "If this sentence is true then P2. Therefore P2", which only proves P2 from the assumption that that sentence is true. "Therefore" means "given the preceding is true, we can conclude the following", so "Given that 'If this sentence is true then P2' is true, we can conclude P2", which is valid but almost as trivial as "P2. Therefore P2", which is also a valid but useless argument, and not a paradox.
  • A Seagull
    615
    The problem is that there is no well-defined or logical process for determining whether a statement is 'true' or 'false'. — A Seagull
    Truth tables can be used to explore all possibilities.
    TheMadFool

    Sure, but that doesn't mean that they are 'true'.
  • Andrew M
    1.6k
    How would you evaluate a conditional sentence in a way different to the way I did the Curry's sentence?TheMadFool

    By constructing an algorithm for evaluating it. Here's a Curry sentence from Wikipedia:

    If this sentence is true, then Germany borders China.

    The sentence can be represented algorithmically as follows:

    bool result = theCurrySentence() is true
    
    bool theCurrySentence()
    {
      if (theCurrySentence() is true)
      then
        {
        if (germanyBordersChina() is true)
        then
          return true
        else
          return false
        }
      else
        return true
    }
    

    When running this algorithm, the function theCurrySentence() will never return a truth value. So the sentence it represents is not truth-apt.

    Truth tables can be used to explore all possibilities.TheMadFool

    That assumes that the sentence is truth-apt in the first place. Which is always a potential issue when formalizing natural language sentences.
  • BlueBanana
    873
    The step 6 doesn't make sense. I assume you meant to include P1=(P1=(P1>P2)) somewhere, but that's not actually true, because "this sentence" would then refer to two different sentences. Thus you have never shown P1 to hold.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    Sure, but that doesn't mean that they are 'true'.A Seagull

    Using truth tables we can evaluate any logical statement, including the Curry statement.

    It doesn't prove every P2 simultaneouslyPfhorrest

    What do you mean by "simultaneously"? Some propositions are time-independent e.g. mathematical propositions which don't change with time.

    I don't know how you can say that a logical statement that can prove anything is trivial. That's like saying that ex falso quodlibet which is spoken of in very dramatic and threatening terms as the principle of explosion which does exactly the same thing- prove anything.

    if (germanyBordersChina() is true)Andrew M

    There shouldn't be "if" in the above statement.

    The step 6 doesn't make sense.BlueBanana

    Unfortunately I have no expertise in that area. I know of the basic inference rules of natural deduction and there's no valid step among those rules. The wikipedia article claims the step is a substitution which is intuitive enough to pass any evaluation. After all, if P1 := (P1 > P2) then I can substitute one for the other.
  • Andrew M
    1.6k
    if (germanyBordersChina() is true)
    — Andrew M

    There shouldn't be "if" in the above statement.
    TheMadFool

    That is there simply to make the return values explicit (per the truth table for p --> q) and doesn't affect the logic. But if you prefer, the algorithm can be simplified to the following:

    bool result = theCurrySentence() is true
    
    bool theCurrySentence()
    {
      if (theCurrySentence() is true)
      then
        return (germanyBordersChina() is true)
      else
        return true
    }
    

    The problem is that theCurrySentence() function can't be evaluated until the antecedent is evaluated. But the antecedent can't be evaluated until theCurrySentence() function that it calls is evaluated. So nothing gets evaluated and no truth value is returned. The algorithm just endlessly loops.
  • ep3265
    70
    P1 = (P1 > P2)TheMadFool

    Doesn't the equality cause for an infinite regress in variables or am I not understanding?

    You could easily say:

    (P1>P2) = ((P1>P2)>P2)

    and furthermore for infinity by your definition.
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment