As we are all familiar with, morality is about oughts. I regard the fundamental premise of morality to be a dissatisfaction, even a deep sadness, about what is - the status quo. Thus, it (morality) is basically a list of of oughts and ought nots which, if anything, is an attempt to change things, presumably, for the "better".
I'm aware that there are a couple of moral theories with illustrious origins but, if I've understood anything it's that none of them are adequate to cover all the bases. I consider this state of affairs regrettable to say the least and would like to proffer, first, an explanation as to why this is and second, to demonstrate that any attempt to construct a moral theory is doomed from the outset.
Firstly, why is there no moral theory that is inconsistency-free? To answer that we need to return to the basics - the ought/ought not nature of morality. In this regard, that which is germane to this discussion is the fact that "ought" has two types meanings:
1. ought: simply expresses a desire/wish but lacks force in the sense it implies a certain course of action. For instance "it ought to rain" expresses the simple desire or wish for rain as expressed as "wish it would rain"
2. ought: indicates the obligatory nature of something. For example, "we ought to help the poor" means that it's obligatory to help the poor.
It is my contention that the oughts of morality are type 1 oughts and are wishes/desires that are not linked in any way to obligations, either to do or not to do an act. Why I say this is will be explained in the next paragraph. Type 1 oughts arise from, not careful deliberation, but from imperfect moral intuitions and are thus necessarily rough guidelines intended to cover most, but not all, cases.
Why are moral oughts not, as I claim here, obligatory; they are, at best, simply our wishes/desires for something better. This is because an essential aspect of morality is responsibility and to be responsible for one's actions, one must be free; in other words, there can be no obligations to act or not to act in certain ways in morality. To be morally responsible, we must be free. To be free, there mustn't be obligations. If there mustn't be obligations, the oughts of morality mustn't be obligatory. Ergo, to be morally responsible, the oughts of morality mustn't be obligatory.
If moral oughts can't be obligatory then the very first premise of all moral theories, that moral oughts should be obligatory in the sense of a type 2 ought, contradicts the other vital principle of morality I mentioned, the principle that to be moral agents, freedom is necessary. Ergo, if one wishes to construct a moral theory that makes us obligated to do good and not bad as all moral theories so far have tried to, it would effectively relieve its adherents of any moral responsibility since they would lack the freedom to do anything but good.
In summary:
1. Moral oughts are simply wishes/desires for something better and can't be obligations for freedom is essential to morality
2. Any moral theory that attempts to make the good obligatory and the bad prohibitory, like all moral theories so far, is self-refuting because, as I said, freedom is an essential ingredient for moral responsibility
Comments... — TheMadFool
There is a quote from a certain holy book that says something akin to (and i'm purposely leaving out details), "in the after life these types of people although still are going to be in the after life, will be judged/discerned for their conduct here on earth."
Basically that particular holy book doesn't absolutely require good behavior but based on numerous variables will recieve rewards based on things like suffering and productivity and the list goes on and on.
Some philosophies/religions view these things as you don't have to do these good things but there are rewards for people who go the extra mile. — christian2017
There is a quote from a certain holy book that says something akin to (and i'm purposely leaving out details), "in the after life these types of people although still are going to be in the after life, will be judged/discerned for their conduct here on earth."
Basically that particular holy book doesn't absolutely require good behavior but based on numerous variables will recieve rewards based on things like suffering and productivity and the list goes on and on.
Some philosophies/religions view these things as you don't have to do these good things but there are rewards for people who go the extra mile.
— christian2017
Judging, as an aspect of morality, makes sense only if we're free and thus can be held accountable. That said, paradoxically, the self-refuting character of judgement vis-a-vis morality is evident in the reward it promises and the punishment it threatens which effectively negate our freedom. Which red-blooded human can deny paradise or accept hell? — TheMadFool
There is a quote from a certain holy book that says something akin to (and i'm purposely leaving out details), "in the after life these types of people although still are going to be in the after life, will be judged/discerned for their conduct here on earth."
Basically that particular holy book doesn't absolutely require good behavior but based on numerous variables will recieve rewards based on things like suffering and productivity and the list goes on and on.
Some philosophies/religions view these things as you don't have to do these good things but there are rewards for people who go the extra mile.
— christian2017
Judging, as an aspect of morality, makes sense only if we're free and thus can be held accountable. That said, paradoxically, the self-refuting character of judgement vis-a-vis morality is evident in the reward it promises and the punishment it threatens which effectively negate our freedom. Which red-blooded human can deny paradise or accept hell? — TheMadFool
1. ought: simply expresses a desire/wish but lacks force in the sense it implies a certain course of action. For instance "it ought to rain" expresses the simple desire or wish for rain as expressed as "wish it would rain" — TheMadFool
Why are moral oughts not, as I claim here, obligatory; they are, at best, simply our wishes/desires for something better. This is because an essential aspect of morality is responsibility and to be responsible for one's actions, one must be free; in other words, there can be no obligations to act or not to act in certain ways in morality. To be morally responsible, we must be free. To be free, there mustn't be obligations. If there mustn't be obligations, the oughts of morality mustn't be obligatory. Ergo, to be morally responsible, the oughts of morality mustn't be obligatory. — TheMadFool
Ergo, if one wishes to construct a moral theory that makes us obligated to do good and not bad as all moral theories so far have tried to, it would effectively relieve its adherents of any moral responsibility since they would lack the freedom to do anything but good. — TheMadFool
You're confusing freedom with randomness. — Echarmion
All moral philosophies recognise that moral duties can be and are shirked. — Echarmion
1. Moral oughts are simply wishes/desires for something better and can't be obligations for freedom is essential to morality
2. Any moral theory that attempts to make the good obligatory and the bad prohibitory, like all moral theories so far, is self-refuting because, as I said, freedom is an essential ingredient for moral responsibility — TheMadFool
1. Moral oughts are simply wishes/desires for something better and can't be obligations for freedom is essential to morality
2. Any moral theory that attempts to make the good obligatory and the bad prohibitory, like all moral theories so far, is self-refuting because, as I said, freedom is an essential ingredient for moral responsibility — TheMadFool
Randomness essentially doesn't favor any option among those available and freedom too means all options are equal in value. — TheMadFool
The difference between randomness and a good person and a bad person is in the first case, good and bad are equiprobable at 50%, in the second case probability of good is > 50% and in the third case the probability of bad > 50%. What do you think? — TheMadFool
That, in my humble opinion, is freedom. Rejecting a valuation system that makes you have a preference. — TheMadFool
law is identical to moral obligation maybe never, but ought to run alongside. — tim wood
Reason, not free will. Perhaps you'll offer your understanding of freedom and free will. Per Kant, freedom is just the freedom to do your duty, as reason discovers your duty to you. I, myself, sometimes like to look at expensive wristwatches online. Some of them I desire, covet, lust after, would like to own, and could buy (buy, that is, in theory). That is, you might say I am free to do all of those things. Kant would say - did say - that in none of these am I free. (Alas, I have not to hand his terminology!)1. If there's moral responsibility then free will is essential — TheMadFool
Better: if morality is made obligatory, is it still morality? Depends on who's doing the making. Self-legislation (again, per Kant) in accord with reason and duty just is (the exercise of) freedom. If imposed from without, then it sounds like law, which is not morality.2. If morality is made obligatory then, free will isn't essential
Just plain not so.3. morality is made obligatory (by all moral theories).
I don't see why freedom would mean that all options are equal in value. Isn't selecting an options regardless of and specific value an expression of freedom? — Echarmion
I think that the idea of good or bad people and freedom don't mix well. If we take freedom seriously, it means there aren't good or bad people, only good or bad decisions. That's, incidentally, another key concept to remember when discussing freedom - freedom is about making decisions. If you decide to follow a rule, that's freedom. — Echarmion
Yes, but that means those options available to you are, in your eyes, equal in value. Had it been that some options were more valuable than others, then you would prefer those over others and so, since the choices you make are determined by the value of the options, you are, in every sense of the word, compelled to make those choices. No freedom there. — TheMadFool
In other words morality is meaningless if one is obligated to be moral. — TheMadFool
Given this is so, any moral theory that builds itself up on the premise that people should be obligated to do good and prohibited from doing bad is self-refuting for it amounts to coercion and this, in the worst way possible, nullifies moral responsibility which I referred to in a previous paragraph. — TheMadFool
Therefore, my insistence that we must be free from any and all obligations and therefore my attempt to tease out a distinction in the meaning of ought. The actual moral ought that we should be guided by is the one that expresses simply a wish/desire which doesn't carry the weight of duty i.e. isn't an obligation; we should be wary of the other moral ought which is, good intentions notwithstanding, of the obligatory kind that, as I've mentioned, voids a fundamental moral principle, the principle of moral responsibility. — TheMadFool
So, the moral freedom I recommend isn't random in the sense that there are absolutely no guidelines to morality and we act on whims, but is based on moral oughts that are nothing more than the wishes/desires of people to be good and not bad, possessing no power to force our hands to be moral and not immoral. — TheMadFool
But that's the thing. I am not compelled. I can make the less valuable choice. Of course you could make a semantic argument that, by definition, the choice I end up making was the one I valued most. But then the freedom lies in assigning the vakued — Echarmion
I can't make any sense out of either of these premises. I understand what your point is, I just don't believe either (1) or (2) is true. It may be true that some people believe "oughts" are derived from "wishes/desires," but that would make them arbitrary and capricious. What you might consider moral and obligatory might conflict with what I consider moral and obligatory. How would we arrive at any consensus if there weren't good (objective) reasons to suppose that generally love is better than hate, or that murder (as opposed to justifiable killing) is always wrong.
One contention we might be consider is that oughts are derived from that which we value. We value love much more than hate, because we see the outcomes of love over hate. We also value truth-telling generally over lying, because we see the outcome in relationships (business, friends, and family relationships).
Finally, it's correct to assume that freedom is an essential ingredient of morality. However, freedom must be seen in the correct context, that is, it's the power to do otherwise. To say that one should generally keep one's promises doesn't take away one's freedom to not keep one's promises. The freedom to do otherwise is still present, it's just that it's not generally the best course of action - the best moral action. Why? Because we see that in our daily lives keeping promises promotes the good in a variety of ways. — Sam26
Please note that the moral oughts I find morally relevant are the wishes/desires of people; they are simply recommendations concerning moral thought/speech/behavior and not the other kind of moral ought we see cropping up in moral theories. They are sourced from moral intuitions rather than from full rational analysis of morality and are rough guidlines to serve most moral issues and are not the laws that moral theories are so fond of. — TheMadFool
It appears as well you haven't glanced at any ancient thinking on the subject. I'm thinking Greek, but there are other ancient worlds of morality/ethics in addition to theirs. (@Wayfarer?) — tim wood
You didn't address my argument which disputes your premises. All you did was repeat yourself. Your proofs are irrelevant if the premises are false, which I believe is the case. — Sam26
Actually the OP expresses a re-statement of the so-called 'boo/hurrah' theory of ethics, which is emotivism - that all ethical statements express is what we like (hurrah!) or don't (boo!) — Wayfarer
So, even if such moral oughts are only desires/wishes, they aren't simply approving hurrahs and disapproving boos in the sense of being reflexive emotions sans thinking. — TheMadFool
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.