Sure they have. To "refute" it you have to understand it, and most folks who try, don't. The right way is to breathe, relax, and then read it somewhat closely, It is an argument that says if you think a certain way and believe certain things, then certain conclusions follow (according to Anselm). Or, if you think and believe the moon is made of green cheese, then very likely mice would like it there. There is no refuting this kind of argument. And in his reply to his critic Gaunilo, Anselm made it clear he understood exactly the nature and kind of his argument - and better than almost all of his critics to date. — tim wood
The crux of the argument is in treating existence as greater or as having something to do with greatness. Expressed logically, the key premise of the ontological argument is: — TheMadFool
Nope. The crux, as you call it, lies in recognizing that the existence of God is presupposed in all the thinking that Christians do. And each of the religions in each its own way. Which of course is a way of saying that God certainly exists - just not, at all, in the way some people understand it. — tim wood
Refute what? And where do you imagine "ontological" came from or what it refers to? And it is not possible to get out of bed in the morning, nor into it at night, without presuppositions of various types and qualities.refute it — TheMadFool
Obviously, I have found Luther and Avicena and a couple of others. — Kakarrott
Refute what? And where do you imagine "ontological" came from or what it refers to? And it is not possible to get out of bed in the morning, nor into it at night, without presuppositions of various types and qualities. — tim wood
And perhaps the question would never arise if instead of the one word "existence," we had several for the several different kinds of existence. — tim wood
The crux of the argument is in treating existence as greater or as having something to do with greatness. — TheMadFool
Actually, the original notion from ancient philosophy, was that being is a good and that non-being was, therefore, an imperfection. I suppose you could argue against the idea that 'being is good', but if you're not inclined to find that intuition resonant, then probably there is no point in arguing it. — Wayfarer
I mean 4500 pages of brain-meltingly hard, interesting and greatly written (or maybe it is the translation, who knows) work of Thomas Aquinas must be, for now, the pinnacle of my search for interesting reading outside of the box (the book I have been mentioning in my guided tours for years, ironic.) But Avicenna's Medicine looks also incredible (despite it maybe being little non-philosophical) — Kakarrott
1. If greatest then exists
2. God is the greatest
Ergo,
3. God exists — TheMadFool
Presuppositions and premises not the same thing — tim wood
if in starting with God, you end with God — tim wood
The aspect of morality that's germane to the ontological argument is morality's ultimate vision viz. the world, people, ought to be a certain way and not how it is. If so, then the existence of morality is evidence for either the nonexistence or imperfect nature of the good. — TheMadFool
I know that I know nothing — Socrates
Socrates is the wisest — Delphic Oracle
God of the gaps is a theological perspective in which gaps in scientific knowledge are taken to be evidence or proof of God's existence. — Wikipedia
I think the quickest way to get up to speed is read all of Augustine and read Duns Scotus soon afterwards. — Valentinus
Now this [late medieval nominalist] philosophy was itself the legatee of the greatest of all disruptions carried out in the history of European thought, namely that of Duns Scotus who for the first time established a radical separation of philosophy from theology by declaring that it was possible to consider "being" in abstraction from the question of whether one is considering created or creating being. Eventually this generated the notion of ontology and an epistemology unconstrained by, and transcendentally prior to, theology itself.
John Milbank, Catherine Pickstock, and Graham Ward (eds.), Radical Orthodoxy: A New Theology (London: Routledge, 1999) p. 23.
...
According to Milbank, there was a generally agreed upon outlook in which human beings and the created order participated in the divine life, but this 'participatory ontology' became problematic with Scotus’ univocity of being. If it is true that we can apply the term “being” to God and to his creatures in the same way – which is what univocity means – then “being” becomes an overarching category in which God and creatures both share, and this will have profound implications for epistemology and ontology. If "being" is a genus under which both God and creatures are species, then God and creatures are different poles in the ontological scale, wide apart as they may be; and epistemologically, it follows that, rational creatures can know things in the same way God does (even if not as much as he does). 1 — Marcelo P. Souza
I disagree re: Kant. Otherwise, even if Anselm's OA is valid, it's clearly not sound.I don't know if Anselm of Canterbury was a medieval-era philosopher but check out his ontological argument. No one, till date, has been able to refute it ... — TheMadFool
Johannes Scotus Erigena — 180 Proof
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.