Is this is a meta-ethical analysis of consequentialists theories in particular or do you think that deontology and virtue ethics are prone to the same meta-ethical problems? — Soylent
I don't see how the truth conditions of moral statements are any more problematic than those of any other kind of claim. — The Great Whatever
If that's a problem for the realist, then it's a problem for anyone who believes in truth conditions about anything.
Sure, but the difference is that the realist can't make sense of his truth-conditions whereas the non-realist can. The subjectivist can say that the statement "X is immoral" is true if the speaker doesn't approve of X, and so we know what "X is immoral" means; it means that the speaker doesn't approve of X. But what can the realist say? — Michael
Meta-ethics is prior to normative ethics. Before we can discuss whether or not the the moral value of X is determined by duty or by consequences we have to determine what it means for X to be moral (or immoral). — Michael
If someone tells me that some X is immoral then they are usually telling me not to do X — Michael
But then you just have the problem of, when do you know someone approves of something? — The Great Whatever
There's also the fact that semantically, things like 'X is wrong' just don't mean the same thing as I don't approve of X
What are the truth conditions for the claim "X is immoral" under moral realism? If you don't know what those truth conditions are then you don't know what it means for the claim to be true. — Michael
They don't just mean that. But that's exactly the point I've been making.
Moral claims mean a lot of things – do a lot of things.
What are the truth conditions of "X approves of Y?" How are those any less mysterious than the truth conditions of the sentence this is supposedly translated from? — The Great Whatever
But meaning and doing are different. If I say, 'you didn't take out the garbage,' one thing I can do with such a statement is imply that I don't like someone. But that is not what the sentence means. It means that the addressee didn't take out the garbage.
We're discussing what it means for X to be immoral. Obviously to engage in any (successful) discussion on what a claim means there must be some common understood language else we'd never get anywhere. So for the sake of argument I'm assuming – reasonably, I would say – that we all understand and agree on the meaning of "X approves of Y". But we can't say this about the meaning of "X is immoral" because the meaning of "X is immoral" is the very thing being questioned. The subjectivist has made an attempt to translate this claim into one that is presumably understood and agreed upon. Can the realist make such an attempt? — Michael
It can mean either. Which one it means in this context depends on what you're trying to do with the claim.
I asked because your analysis seems biased towards a meta-ethical analysis that presupposes morality as consequentialist. — Soylent
"X is immoral" they are often telling others how to behave. — Michael
What do you mean, that meaning is the very thing being questioned? — The Great Whatever
Why is it more questionable than "X approves of Y?"
If knowing English is what it takes to understand English sentences, where does the subjectivist get off saying no one can understand the English sentences he thinks are problematic because of his metaphysical prejudices?
No, it can't mean either. That is not what those English words mean. I claim that 'You didn't take out the trash' means that the addressee didn't take out the trash, not that it means something else. One can of course use the meaning of the words to imply something that is not strictly said by the sentence.
This makes no sense. We have to have a common understood language, yes. We call this language English. That same language that lets us understand what "X approves of Y" means lets us understand what "X is immoral" means.
I mean that we're actively asking the question "what does 'X is immoral?' mean?" and trying to answer it. That's what meta-ethics is.
Because we're questioning it. If we were questioning the meaning of "X approves of Y" then the meaning of "X approves of Y" would be questionable.
I don't understand this.
The meaning of a sentence isn't simply to be understood only as what follows from combining the (most prominent) dictionary-definition of its component words. Language doesn't work like that.
And the statement "X is immoral" is used to express one's disapproval, to report on one's disapproval, to prohibit behaviour, and/or to report on a rule.
The problem is when one then says that this rule is non-constructed or that moral properties are something other than the traditional empirical properties that we're familiar with. — Michael
Once you adopt realism you attempt to subtract the empirical use of language from the meaning of the phrase, but as the meaning of the phrase is its empirical use there's nothing meaningful left. — Michael
Recall that you chastised the moral realist for trying to push the question back rather than resolve it. What makes the anti-realist's answer any different? — The Great Whatever
Even if unilluminating the moral realist at least doesn't express gross semantic ignorance in saying that 'murder is wrong' means that murder is wrong, rather than something else.
Competent speakers of English understand what 'X is immoral' means. It means that X is immoral. The subjectivist must deny this, and say that it instead means something else.
I didn't say it was. However, contrary to your claim, 'you didn't take out the trash' doesn't sometimes mean, something else. One can imply something else by exploiting the meaning of the sentence; but that doesn't mean the sentence means whatever you want it to imply in any context.
What is 'ordinary?' Everyone is perfectly familiar with moral properties
Except the objectivist is honest about how people use the phrase, whereas the subjectivist makes up other meanings to suit his philosophical agenda.
As a meta-ethical analysis, where did this idea that morality is about telling others how to behave come from? — Soylent
Deontology and virtue ethics would disagree with that foundation. Deontology and virtue ethics would stand as a principled (universal, non-relative) theory, that prescribes personal action specific to the character of the agent (relative).
I don't understand the criticism. For one, realism, nihilism, and relativism aren't theses about moral language. Realism is constituted in part by a claim about moral language, and relativism may be depending on which of the several ways that term is used you are intending to pick out here, but these views are primarily about the metaphysics of ethics. For another, people argue realism or nihilism or relativism because the way these are defined (again, depending on what you mean by relativism), they are all mutually exclusive. You can't be any two at once, so of course the decision is treated as exclusive. Third, adopting one of these views does not rule out having other metaethical views as well. So it is odd to think that adopting one of these views is simplistic on the grounds that they do not cover the full complexity of moral language. They aren't even supposed to do that. It's like complaining about the electrician because he didn't fix your sink.The usual approach to meta-ethics is to argue for a single understanding: realism or nihilism or relativism, and so on. This is far too simplistic and fails to consider the complexity of moral language. — Michael
I don't understand the criticism. For one, realism, nihilism, and relativism aren't theses about moral language. — Postmodern Beatnik
For another, people argue realism or nihilism or relativism because the way these are defined (again, depending on what you mean by relativism), they are all mutually exclusive. You can't be any two at once, so of course the decision is treated as exclusive.
Third, adopting one of these views does not rule out having other metaethical views as well.
So it is odd to think that adopting one of these views is simplistic on the grounds that they do not cover the full complexity of moral language. They aren't even supposed to do that. It's like complaining about the electrician because he didn't fix your sink.
I think it is a mistake to tie these questions so closely together. It is completely possible to think both that there are real moral facts, but that our moral language does not concern itself with them. That is, one could be a non-cognitivist about actual moral language while nevertheless thinking that there are moral facts that we ought to be thinking and talking about.They make claims about what it means for X to be immoral, which is to make a claim about what "X is immoral" means. — Michael
But the views are defined more precisely than this. Robust moral realism is the conjunction of three claims:I wouldn't say that this is exactly correct. Realism and nihilism are mutually exclusive, as realism argues that some X is inherently immoral whereas nihilism argues that no X is inherently immoral, but nihilism and relativism are not mutually exclusive as the claims "X is not inherently immoral" and "X is non-inherently immoral" are compatible. — Michael
There is no contradiction. Just because one cannot be both a realist and a nihilist doesn't mean that one cannot be both a nihilist and, say, a non-cognitivist (the cognitivism/non-cognitivism debate also being a metaethical one). Indeed, one can be both a nihilist and a non-cognitivist (as most non-cognitivists are). And as I already alluded to, one could have a view on which one was a hermeneutical non-cognitivist (our moral language does not involve making truth-apt assertions) and a revolutionary realist (there are moral facts, and so our moral language ought to be revised so as to be about them). Again, these are just two possible examples.Leaving aside the fact that this seems to contradict your immediately prior claim that "you can't be any two at once" — Michael
And my point is that no one has ever said that adopting any single metaethical view thereby rules out all other metaethical views (just the ones that are inconsistent with the one already adopted). That's why I said "I don't understand the criticism" rather than "I think your claim is mistaken."I'm not saying that these views rule each other out. I'm actually saying the opposite; that they're compatible — Michael
Please cite a professional moral philosopher who does this and where they do it. Even a robust realist—who must address multiple issues in defending his view—nevertheless does not cover all aspects of metaethics simply in virtue of being a realist.People do indeed try to argue for just a single meta-ethical view and claim that this meta-ethical view successfully makes sense of (all) moral claims. — Michael
I think it is a mistake to tie these questions so closely together. It is completely possible to think both that there are real moral facts, but that our moral language does not concern itself with them. That is, one could be a non-cognitivist about actual moral language while nevertheless thinking that there are moral facts that we ought to be thinking and talking about. — Postmodern Beatnik
But the views are defined more precisely than this. Robust moral realism is the conjunction of three claims:
The semantic thesis: Moral assertions are truth-apt.
The alethic thesis: Some such assertions are true.
The metaphysical thesis: Those such assertions that are true are made true by objective features of the world, independent of subjective opinion.
Constructivists—including the sort of relativist I take it you mean to be discussing—deny the metaphysical thesis. Nihilists deny both the metaphysical and alethic theses (with error theorists accepting the semantic thesis and non-cognitive nihilists denying it). This can then be further complicated by whether one is a fictionalist about (certain parts of) ethics and what sort of fictionalist one might be (a hermeneutical fictionalist or a revolutionary fictionalist). One can also be a non-cognitivist about the origins of morality (aka "sentimentalism") while nevertheless being a cognitivist about moral language. One can also be an error theorist about some discourses while not being an error theorist about other discourses. And of course, that's just the tip of the iceberg.
...
Just because one cannot be both a realist and a nihilist doesn't mean that one cannot be both a nihilist and, say, a non-cognitivist (the cognitivism/non-cognitivism debate also being a metaethical one). Indeed, one can be both a nihilist and a non-cognitivist (as most non-cognitivists are).
Please cite a professional moral philosopher who does this and where they do it.
Let's take a simpler example. Suppose that agent subjectivism is true: statements of the form "x is permissible/obligatory/wrong" mean something like "I approve of/demand/disapprove of x." Just because language developed this way doesn't mean that there are not actual moral facts of which we are ignorant, however. And if we discovered them, we would need to either come up with new words to talk about them or reappropriate our moral language for them. As we have other ways of expressing approval, demands, and disapproval, and as one might think that the new discourse ought to replace the old discourse, it is not entirely bizarre to think the second option (the revisionary one) might be advocated by some.I can't make sense of this. — Michael
You are bewitching yourself with language here (and mistaking the project of metaethics at the same time). One task of metaethics is to explain the meaning of "X is immoral." It is not a task of metaethics to explain what it means to be immoral, however, unless we are using the latter expression to stand in for something more complicated that does not present the same surface difficulties (such as the alternative usage of "mean" in the second expression"). Metaethics is about the meaning of moral expressions, about whether or not a certain type of fact exists, and about the relationship between the facts and our expressions. But there is no presupposition in the subject itself that the expressions must line up with the facts in one of only two ways.Furthermore, to suggest that an explanation of the meaning of "X is immoral" can differ from an explanation of what it means to be immoral seems comparable to suggesting that an explanation of the meaning of "X is a bachelor" can differ from an explanation of what it means to be a bachelor — Michael
Again, it doesn't. What I am suggesting is that you are hunting snipe. For any two views that are not mutually exclusive, no one says you can't hold them both at the same time. And for any views that are mutually exclusive, it would be a mistake for you to argue that they can be held at the same time. And of course, it has long been recognized that different views might be appropriate for different discourses (or contexts of discourse). In short, I don't see you as having any real targets in your sights.I'm not sure how this runs contrary to what I've said. — Michael
Sure. Let's start with David Hume. He is a non-cognitivist about the origins of morality (this is his sentimentalism, which says that morality is more properly felt than judged and that the origin of morality is in the passions). Nevertheless, he is a constructivist about moral practice (our moral sentiments influence us to adopt various personal and interpersonal moral practices, with varying degrees of compliance). He is also a moral naturalist of sorts (what we count as virtuous and vicious relates directly back to our nature, though our circumstances also play an important role and nature is not the external imposition that Aristotle would have it be). Furthermore, he is a cognitivist about moral language (though morality begins in the sentiments, our primary use of moral statements has come to be the expression of propositions). He is then an error theorist insofar as he thinks those statements have come to be reinterpreted as presupposing the existence of facts that go beyond what is actually the case (so the majority of moral practices are justifiable, but the common justification is mistaken—complete with a few mistaken practices as a result). While he is both a constructivist and an error theorist, he does not adopt them both in relation to any single discourse or praxis (thus he is not violating the "no two at once" rule). Similarly, he is both a cognitivist and a non-cognitivist, but about different things (the origins of morality and moral expressions). He may also be open to the possibility that not all moral expressions are cognitive (as are nearly all cognitivists; it is the non-cognitivists about moral language who are more likely to take a universal approach here—though they need not).I'd be interested in which professional moral philosophers have argued in favour of multiple meta-ethical approaches to explain morality and moral language. — Michael
Suppose that agent subjectivism is true: statements of the form "x is permissible/obligatory/wrong" mean something like "I approve of/demand/disapprove of x." Just because language developed this way doesn't mean that there are not actual moral facts of which we are ignorant, however. — Postmodern Beatnik
As we have other ways of expressing approval, demands, and disapproval, and as one might think that the new discourse ought to replace the old discourse, it is not entirely bizarre to think the second option (the revisionary one) might be advocated by some.
You are bewitching yourself with language here (and mistaking the project of metaethics at the same time). One task of metaethics is to explain the meaning of "X is immoral." It is not a task of metaethics to explain what it means to be immoral, however, unless we are using the latter expression to stand in for something more complicated that does not present the same surface difficulties (such as the alternative usage of "mean" in the second expression"). Metaethics is about the meaning of moral expressions, about whether or not a certain type of fact exists, and about the relationship between the facts and our expressions. But there is no presupposition in the subject itself that the expressions must line up with the facts in one of only two ways.
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.