• Need Logic Help
    43
    Dear Logicians,

    I would be hugely grateful if someone could help me out with this question.

    An argument was put forward here: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Iu3N9Q2B3Uk&t=5400s.

    This is apparently a logic error. See this explanation of why it's a logical error:

    Dillahunty makes a logical error here because he presents the argument “P1: X cares about objective logic, P2: X does not care about Y, C: Y is not included in objective logic”, but imagine the argument “P3: Lois Lane believes Superman can fly, P4: Lois Lane does not believe Clark Kent can fly, C: Clark Kent is not Superman”—the issue is that maybe Y really is part of objective logic but X doesn’t know it.

    Is it a logical error? If so, why? If not, why isn't a logical error?

    I would hugely appreciate your help with this, and please be thorough if you can be.

    Thanks so much!

    Sincerely,
    Need Logic Help
  • bongo fury
    1.7k


    A lot will depend on whether you think it beneficial to involve a logic of belief. If not, or else at least to help decide, let's make the parallel as clear as possible:

    P1: All logics that are objective are cared about by X
    P2: Logic Y is not cared about by X
    C: Logic Y is not objective

    P3: All men that are Supermen are believed by Lois Lane to fly
    P4: Man Clark Kent is not believed by Lois Lane to fly
    C: Man Clark Kent is not a Superman

    In both cases, there's no logical error except perhaps a choice-of-logic error: you might decide you must affirm both premises yet reject the conclusion. Because for example you are too polite to question P1/P3. Then you're gonna need a bigger (and more controversial) logic. But questioning P1/P3 is simpler.

    the issue is that maybe Y really is part of objective logic but X doesn’t know it.Need Logic Help

    And the simplest way to make that point is just to say that P1 fails. "There are more objective logics in heaven and earth than are cared about in X's philosophy." No need to get modal on his ass, and call it a (necessarily exotic) logical error, rather than a (simple) factual one.
  • T Clark
    14k
    “P1: X cares about objective logic, P2: X does not care about Y, C: Y is not included in objective logic”Need Logic Help

    How about this

    T Clark likes fruit. T Clark does not like apples. Therefore apples are not fruit.

    I guess the question is - does the statement "T Clark likes fruit," mean that he has to like all fruit or just fruit in general.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    Just to be clear, I'm not out to get Matt Dillahunty or anything. I genuinely just want to know the truth of the matter.

    So does P1 fail or does it not? If it fails, why? If not, why not?

    If P1/P2 are correct in what you laid out, then does C follow? If not, doesn't there need to be some error of logic?

    And if P3/P4 are correct in what you laid out, then does C follow? If not, doesn't there need to be some error of logic?
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    That's a good point. How do you think that the first premise could be more clearly stated?
  • T Clark
    14k
    That's a good point. How do you think that the first premise could be more clearly stated?Need Logic Help

    X cares about every aspect of objective logic.

    I think the problem here is that the statements are being made in everyday English. When I say "I like fruit," it doesn't necessarily mean I like absolutely all fruit. I really like green vegetables - brussel sprouts, cabbage, lettuce, green beans, lime beans, spinach, cauliflower, broccoli. I don't like okra or broccoli rab. Those are both perfectly reasonable statements for me to make.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    What if you say you like fruit, but then say that you don't like tomatoes, and then conclude that a tomato isn't a fruit? A tomato is in fact a fruit, apparently.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    I guess that we need to know exactly what argument Matt was presenting. Right? Or else we can't evaluate if it's logically solid or not logically solid.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    What if you say that you like ALL fruit, I mean, and not tomatoes, and then find out that tomatoes are fruit.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    Dillahunty makes a logical error here because he presents the argument “P1: X cares about objective logic, P2: X does not care about Y, C: Y is not included in objective logic”, but imagine the argument “P3: Lois Lane believes Superman can fly, P4: Lois Lane does not believe Clark Kent can fly, C: Clark Kent is not Superman”—the issue is that maybe Y really is part of objective logic but X doesn’t know it.Need Logic Help

    Dillahunty's argument
    P1: All things X cares about are things that are logically objective
    P2: No things X cares about are things identical to Y
    Ergo,
    C. No things that are logically objective are things identical to Y

    Tests for validity of Dillahunty's argument:
    1. Distributed middle term test: Passed
    2. Distributed conclusion test: Fail. The category "things that are logically objective", distributed in the conclusion, isn't distributed in the premises. It should be if the argument is to be valid.

    Dillahunty's argument is invalid.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    Thanks! This is interesting. Curious to see what the other users in this thread think of your breakdown!

    Can you explain the two tests that you performed?
  • bongo fury
    1.7k
    So does P1 fail or does it not? If it fails, why?Need Logic Help

    Because,

    "There are more objective logics in heaven and earth than are cared about in X's philosophy."bongo fury

    If not, why not?Need Logic Help

    Because all of them are cared about by X.

    If P1/P2 are correct in what you laid out,Need Logic Help

    Assuming you mean, if they are a fair presentation of the premises actually being asserted,

    then does C follow?Need Logic Help

    Sure.

    If not,Need Logic Help

    I take it you mean, if they are the actual premises being asserted, but C doesn't follow,

    doesn't there need to be some error of logic?Need Logic Help

    Yes. But there isn't. C follows, unless you want to get bogged down in a bigger and more controversial logic (one of belief). I've presented the premises in such a way that you can dispute them, rather than the logic.

    And if P3/P4 are correct in what you laid out, then does C follow? If not, doesn't there need to be some error of logic?Need Logic Help

    Likewise.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    Thanks! This is interesting. Curious to see what the other users in this thread think of your breakdown!

    Can you explain the two tests that you performed?
    Need Logic Help

    Dillahunty's argument
    P1: All things X cares about are things that are logically objective
    P2: No things X cares about are things identical to Y
    Ergo,
    C. No things that are logically objective are things identical to Y

    Tests for validity of Dillahunty's argument:
    1. Distributed middle term test: Passed
    2. Distributed conclusion test: Fail. The category "things that are logically objective", distributed in the conclusion, isn't distributed in the premises. It should be if the argument is to be valid.

    Dillahunty's argument is invalid.
    TheMadFool

    Distributed middle term test: The middle term, the term missing in the conclusion ,the inferential link between the major and minor terms in the conclusion, must be distributed i.e. there must be a premise that makes a statement about ALL members of the middle term. In Dillahunty's argument, the middle terms is "all things X cares about" and it's distributed premise 1 (P1).

    Distributed conclusion test: Every term distributed in the conclusion must be distributed at least once in the premises. The term "things that are logically objective" is distributed in the conclusion but it isn't in any of the premises. Ergo, Dillahunty's argument is invalid.

    That's all there is to it.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    Thanks! Are these two tests commonly performed in logic?

    Would every logician agree that these tests are solid ones to perform, or would there be any contention on that?
  • Bartricks
    6k
    I don't see an error (though I have not watched the video).

    If it is true that Tom cares about all objective truths, and also true that Tom does not care about Y, then we can conclude that Y is not an objective truth.

    If all As are Bs (if all objective truths are cared for by Tom), and C is not a B, then C is not an A.

    The superman example is different. Lane believes Superman can fly. Lane does not believe Clark Kent can fly. Ok. What follows from that is not that superman isn't Clark Kent, but that Lane believes Superman can fly and believes that Clark Kent can't.
    1.p
    2.q
    3. Therefore p and q.

    Of course, as those beliefs are about one and the same person, they can't both be true. But that's a different point.

    So I think the youtube commentator doesn't know what he's talking about and has compared dilahunty's argument to a quite different and obviously invalid one.
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    Thanks for replying!

    Superman is in the category of people who Lois believes can fly.

    Clark Kent isn't.

    Therefore, Clark Kent isn't Superman.
  • Bartricks
    6k
    Yes, if those premises are true, that follows.
    Those premises are not equivalent to these, however:
    1. Lane believes Kent can't fly
    2. Lane believes Superman can fly

    Note: Clark Kent is in the class of people Lane believes can fly (because he is superman and the person of superman is in the class of people she believes can fly), she just doesn't realize this.

    This is valid:

    1. Kent can't fly
    2. Superman can fly
    3. Therefore kent isn't Superman

    This isn't

    1. Lane believes Kent can't fly
    2. Lane believes Superman can fly
    3. Therefore Kent isn't superman

    This is:

    1. Lane believes Kent can't fly
    2. Lane believes superman can fly
    3. Therefore lane believes Kent can't fly and believes superman can fly

    If - if - Dilahunty made this argument:

    1. If P then Q
    2. Not Q
    3. Therefore not P

    Then his argument was valid. And it sounds as if he did.(if x is an objective truth, then I will care about it; I don't care about it; therefore it is not an objective truth).
  • T Clark
    14k
    What if you say that you like ALL fruit, I mean, and not tomatoes, and then find out that tomatoes are fruit.Need Logic Help

    You're making this a lot more difficult than it needs to be. Logic is supposed to be a tool to help find the truth, not a game to find the most obscure, trivial, and convoluted examples possible.

    This is from Wikipedia:

    A fallacy of division is an informal fallacy that occurs when one reasons that something that is true for a whole must also be true of all or some of its parts.

    An example:

    • The second grade in Jefferson elementary eats a lot of ice cream
    • Carlos is a second-grader in Jefferson elementary
    • Therefore, Carlos eats a lot of ice cream
  • Need Logic Help
    43


    And how exactly does the fallacy of division apply to Matt's argument?

    Why isn't Bartricks correct that Matt didn't commit any error?
  • bongo fury
    1.7k
    I guess that we need to know exactly what argument Matt was presenting. Right?Need Logic Help

    And there may be no incontrovertible fact about this matter. But you'd have to be disingenuous or mad to think that P1 was best formulated as,

    P1: All things X cares about are things that are logically objectiveTheMadFool

    rather than the other way round. That way, of course the whole argument is invalid. And you wouldn't need any medievalisms (about distributed middles) to show it. Just use a Venn diagram.

    Whereas actually,

    C follows, unless you want to get bogged down in a bigger and more controversial logic (one of belief).bongo fury

    Or unless you have chosen a bizarre and foolish presentation of P1. Then you are bogged down in a spurious and inexplicable representation of what was said. Which is no better than a spurious injection of modal logic.



    If it is true that Tom cares about all objective truths, and also true that Tom does not care about Y, then we can conclude that Y is not an objective truth.Bartricks

    Yes.

    If - if - Dilahunty made this argument:

    1. If P then Q
    2. Not Q
    3. Therefore not P

    Then his argument was valid.
    Bartricks

    Yes, and he probably did. See above.



    The superman example is different.Bartricks

    Please not. You're inviting the enthusiasts for modal logic to show off, and end up perpetuating the silly libel of a logical error.



    thinking in the same way as Aristotle (roughly 2 millennia ago) and Gottlob Frege (approximately a century ago). That's like going to a modern pharmacy with a prescription made out by none other than HippocratesTheMadFool

    No, it's like knowing what you're talking about.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    No, it's like knowing what you're talking about.bongo fury

    I don't deny the exceptional utility of classical logics and its spinoffs (Aristotle, Frege, Peirce, et al) but, seriously, they fail to capture some of the nuances and subtleties of nature, no? What's up with so-called temporal logic, fuzzy logic, paraconsistent logic, multi-valued logic, etc? Nobody in faer right mind would've taken the trouble to invent them if traditional two-valued predicate logic could handle the complexities inherent to thinking about reality. Just saying...
  • T Clark
    14k
    And how exactly does the fallacy of division apply to Matt's argument?Need Logic Help

    I think I've laid out my argument pretty clearly. I'll leave it at that.
  • tim wood
    9.3k
    Thanks! Are these two tests commonly performed in logic?Need Logic Help

    For validity
    1. Negative premise => negative conclusion
    2. Negative premises (both) => no valid conclusion
    3. Undistributed middle => no valid conclusion
    4. Illicit major: predicate distributed in conclusion, not in premise => no valid conclusion
    5. Illicit minor: subject distributed in conclusion, not in premise => no valid conclusion

    Or another way, from this site,
    https://sites.oxy.edu/traiger/logic/primer/chapter8/testing-syllogisms-validity-rules.html
    which looks pretty good.

    If a syllogism is valid, then the middle term is distributed at least once.
    If a syllogism is valid, then if a term is distributed in the conclusion, it must be distributed in a premise.
    If a syllogism is valid, it does not have two negative premises.
    If a syllogism is valid, then it has a negative premise, if and only if it has a negative conclusion.
    If a syllogism is valid, then if its premises are universal, then its conclusion is universal.

    The last one in this second list is faulty.
    Given

    All m are p
    All s are m

    Two conclusions (not just one) are possible

    All S are P
    Some S are P

    This runs into problems with existential import, but the argument is valid. Clearly if all s are p, then some of them are.

    Validity not to be confused at all with truth, accuracy, or even usefulness.

    This logic could/should be taught 5th grade to ten or eleven-year-olds. Search Amazon for a well-reviewed logic textbook, then Abebooks for a cheap copy. And this worth a look.
    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/square/
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.