The basic problems of consciousness are just things like the nature of it, how it interacts with the physical, or emerges from the physical structurally, whether it's contingent or necessary. PP answers a lot of those questions. — Wosret
to grant a robot qualia requires a change in its programming, not its matter. — tom
I we want to give a robot subjectivity - i.e. "what it is like" knowledge, we have to program it that way. Swapping out a hard-drive, or adding more memory is not going to affect the running of the program that achieves this. What particular hardware constitutes the robot is irrelevant, but panpsychics clain it is relevant! — tom
We know that the robot, as a robot, does not possess subjectivity because we programmed it that way. — tom
The hard problem may indeed be hard, but I think the problem of how to create knowledge - of any kind - is the fundamental problem. — tom
How do all the fundamental particle consciousnesses combine to create a unified consciousness, and why does that require a brain? i.e. how does a single unified consciousness emerge? This is the same question we have without panpsychism! — tom
Are atoms more conscious than fundamental particles? How about mobile phones?
Why are there no semi-conscious things. Or rather, there must be semi-conscious things, how do we identify them?
Why do I lose consciousness when I'm asleep, given that I am physically the same? Do my fundamental particles also sleep?
What I said was that experience 'can't be known in the third person'. — Wayfarer
But that can't be right, can it? After all, the claim that experience can't be known in the third person is itself a third person claim about experience. Maybe you think that's a cheap parlor trick, so consider the fact that you can convey truths to me about your experience, and I can convey those truths to others. We can come to know many things about your experiences without actually having had those experiences ourselves. How is that possible if experience cannot be known in the third person? — Aaron R
experience is not an object of cognition, in the way that an electron or particle or other object can be. We don't know experiences, we have experiences; so any experience has an inescapably first-person element, that is, it is undergone by a subject. So we can't objectify 'the nature of experience' in the way we can the objects and forces that are analysed by the natural sciences.
Now, in one sense we can be very clear about our own experiences - we certainly know what an unpleasant or pleasant experience is, and we know that some experiences have specific attributes, across a vast range of experiences. But in all cases, we know those things experientially - we know about those attributes, because they are the constituents of our experience, in a way very different from how we know and predict the behaviour of objects according to physical laws. — Wayfarer
we can also have third-person knowledge of the structure of experience in general. That's what Kant (who you seem fond of) was really after, wasn't it? He attempted to infer the structure of subjectivity via the transcendental method — Aaron R
Objectification is not naturalization. — Aaron R
we would not have any knowledge of our own experience — John
if you could have no third person knowledge of your own experience then you could not say anything meaningful about it. — John
I don't think we have knowledge of experience. I think knowledge is a facet of our experience. — Wayfarer
It is often commented, that 'the taste of an orange' can't be conveyed to one who hasn't eaten an orange.
I can send you an orange, and then you can taste it, but I can't send you 'the taste of an orange'. — Wayfarer
How can you say knowledge is a facet of our experience if you have no knowledge of experience? — John
If you know you have tasted oranges then you know something about your experience. — John
I can't stand outside experience, or reason, or knowledge, and comment on it 'from the outside'. — Wayfarer
I didn't say otherwise, but it's still a subjective experience, not an objective fact. — Wayfarer
You are making comments, which you do not take to be purely subjective, because you obviously think they are correct and not mere opinions. about the nature of experience. — John
My comments are not purely subjective, but they don't concern any object. — Wayfarer
I think his mistake is to believe that 'experience' is something that can be known in the third person. In other words, experience is not an object of cognition, in the way that an electron or particle or other object can be. We don't know experiences, we have experiences; so any experience has an inescapably first-person element, that is, it is undergone by a subject. So we can't objectify 'the nature of experience' in the way we can the objects and forces that are analysed by the natural sciences.
If you think that third person knowledge of experience is impossible then you need to explain how it's possible for you or anyone else to know (or say) anything about your (or anyone else's) experience. — Aaron R
experience is not an object of cognition, in the way that an electron or particle or other object can be. We don't know experiences, we have experiences; so any experience has an inescapably first-person element, that is, it is undergone by a subject.
...
...in one sense we can be very clear about our own experiences - we certainly know what an unpleasant or pleasant experience is, and we know that some experiences have specific attributes, across a vast range of experiences. But in all cases, we know those things experientially - we know about those attributes, because they are the constituents of our experience.
In regards to Kant, his philosophy implies only that the transcendental subject can't be an object of empirical cognition, not that it can't be an object of cognition tout court. — Aaron R
In the philosophy of Kant , the transcendental ego is the thinker of our thoughts, the subject of our experiences, the willer of our actions, and the agent of the various activities of synthesis that help to constitute the world we experience. It is probably to be identified with our real or noumenal self (see Kant, Critique of Pure Reason , A 492/B 520, where ‘the transcendental subject’ is equated with ‘the self proper, as it exists in itself’) ( see noumenal/phenomenal ). Kant called it transcendental because he believed that although we must posit such a self, we can never observe it.
it is striking the extent to which Kant's account of subjectivity is functional in nature. — Aaron R
There's a very real sense in which Dennett and his ilk can be seen as legitimate heirs to the Kantian tradition. — Aaron R
We don't share the same experience, we experience what we experience, each in our own way. — Cavacava
Perhaps the most important move in the scientific revolution was Galileo’s declaration that mathematics was to be the language of natural science. But he felt able to do this only after he had revolutionised our philosophical picture of the world. Before Galileo it was generally assumed that matter had sensory qualities: tomatoes were red, paprika was spicy, flowers smelt sweet. But it’s hard to see how these sensory qualities – the redness of tomatoes, the spicy taste of paprika, the sweet smell of flowers – could be captured in the abstract, austere vocabulary of mathematics. How could an equation capture what it’s like to taste spicy paprika? And if sensory qualities can’t be captured in a mathematical vocabulary, it seemed to follow that a mathematical vocabulary could never capture the complete nature of matter.
Galileo’s solution to this problem was to strip matter of its sensory qualities and put them in the soul. The sweet smell isn’t really in the flowers but in the soul of the person smelling them; the spicy taste isn’t really in the paprika but in the soul of the person tasting it. Even colours, for Galileo, aren’t really on the surfaces of objects but in the soul of the person observing them. And if matter had no qualities, then it was possible in principle to describe it in the purely quantitative vocabulary of mathematics. This was the birth of mathematical physics.
But of course Galileo didn’t deny the existence of the sensory qualities. Rather he took them to be forms of consciousness residing in the soul, an entity outside of the material world and so outside of the domain of natural science. In other words, Galileo created physical science by putting consciousness outside of its domain of enquiry.
The modern mind-body problem arose out of the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century, as a direct result of the concept of objective physical reality that drove that revolution. Galileo and Descartes made the crucial conceptual division by proposing that physical science should provide a mathematically precise quantitative description of an external reality extended in space and time, a description limited to spatiotemporal primary qualities such as shape, size, and motion, and to laws governing the relations among them. Subjective appearances, on the other hand -- how this physical world appears to human perception -- were assigned to the mind, and the secondary qualities like color, sound, and smell were to be analyzed relationally, in terms of the power of physical things, acting on the senses, to produce those appearances in the minds of observers. It was essential to leave out or subtract subjective appearances and the human mind -- as well as human intentions and purposes -- from the physical world in order to permit this powerful but austere spatiotemporal conception of objective physical reality to develop.
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.