Why didn't you include that explicitly in the argument in the first place? If your objective here is not to put an argument in what you know to be it's best formulation to scrutiny, but just some sort of test of our critical thinking skills, then I don't agree with your purpose here, and wish to take no further part. I don't feel like playing a game of 'spot the shortcomings in my knowingly inadequate argument'. — Sapientia
It is wrong to allow gratuitous suffering caused by food production practices
Gratuitous suffering caused by food production practices is preventable if and only if it is possible to adopt a vegan diet
Therefore a vegan diet ought to be adopted by all those who are in a position to adopt a vegan diet — Michael
I added another term to the implication for the purpose of addressing this issue. I currently stands as:
i) It is wrong to allow gratuitous suffering caused by food production practices
ii) Gratuitous suffering caused by food production practices is preventable if and only if it is possible to adopt a vegan diet
iii) There are those who are in a position to adopt a vegan diet.
Therefore, a vegan diet ought to be adopted by those who are in a position to adopt a vegan diet. — Soylent
As I said before, if you want the first premise to be "one ought make gratuitous suffering preventable iff one can make gratuitous suffering preventable" and if you want as the conclusion "one ought adopt a vegan diet iff one can adopt a vegan diet" then you must have as the second premise "one makes gratuitous suffering preventable iff one adopts a vegan diet". — Michael
It is wrong to allow X is logically equivalent to ought not X. — Soylent
not X = Y
And some can Y (Z)
Therefore, ought Z
So "it is wrong to allow gratuitous suffering" is logically equivalent to "one ought not gratuitous suffering". Obviously that makes no sense. Previously I interpreted this as "one ought prevent gratuitous suffering" but you didn't like this one. Is "one ought make gratuitous suffering preventable" not the correct interpretation? — Michael
But Y in "not X = Y" is "adopting a vegan diet is possible". So "some can Y" is "it is possible for some to adopt a vegan diet".
And if "Z" is "it is possible for some to adopt a vegan diet" then "one ought Z" is "one ought make it possible for some to adopt a vegan diet". Which is the conclusion I said follows and which differs from "one ought adopt a vegan diet". — Michael
If ¬Pa (= O¬a)
and ¬a = b
and c
then, d — Soylent
Another step is still needed to get back to "ought adopt a vegan diet".
I'm not sure I understand your objection. D is derived (entailed?) from A, B, and C as per modus ponens. — Soylent
P1 is a hypothetical premise wherein the affirmation of D is supported by the affirmative conjuction of A, B and C (which were independently affirmed throughout the larger argument). — Soylent
That's not the form though, it's:
P1 (A & B & C) → D
P2 A
P3 B
P4 C
C1 D — Soylent
And I'm questioning P1. What justifies the material implication? D certainly can't be derived from A, B, and C. So it must be something else. — Michael
For clarification, you're question the soundness and not validity — Soylent
Using your example above, let A be "2 > 1", let B be "3 > 2", let C be "4 > 3", and let D be "5 > 6".
P1 (A ∧ B ∧ C) → D
P2 A
P3 B
P4 C
C1 D
So:
P1. If 2 > 1 and 3 > 2 and 4 > 3 then 5 > 6
P2. 2 > 1
P3. 3 > 2
P3. 4 > 3
C1. 5 > 6
Have I shown that 5 > 6? — Michael
If you want me to justify the soundness of the premise then that's fine, but acting as if the argument is invalid is silly. — Soylent
P14 is NOT and argument, it is a premise. — Soylent
If ¬Pa (= O¬a)
and ¬a = b
and c
then, d — Soylent
d follows from the transitive property applied to O¬a wherein ¬a = b and some b is c.
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.