JTB is the appendix of the philosophical world. Appendix as in that small, useless organ that is attached to our intestines. It keeps hanging around for no particular purpose and just pops up every now to cause trouble. — T Clark
Vogel seems to think that there's a difference between Al's and Betty's epistemic circumstances. — Agent Smith
So, on the ground, as a person in the world of those scenarios, I wouldn't consider having said one or both of them knew where there car was as some big error should it turn out that the car is not there. Because when I say 'know' it doesn't mean 'cannot possibly be revised stuff'. — Bylaw
But knowledge about the world is never infallible. What we hold to as something known can change over time. — Fooloso4
The situation would change if the crime rate was so high that it was reasonable to expect that one's car would be stolen, in which case one would presumably take extra precautions, or expect trouble. — unenlightened
An induction based on logic, reason, and memory, but an induction none-the less. — Philosophim
Pretty soon you'll get to the Gettier problem. — T Clark
The problem is set by the similarity between the two, which suggests that their epistemic classification should be the same, and the difference in their circumstances (i.e. the fact that Betty’s car has been stolen), which strongly suggests that it is different. So the fact that Betty’s car has been stolen makes me classify her as believing and rather than knowing. Conclusion – knowledge is not just about the psychological state of the knower. Hence, for example, how confident they each are is irrelevant. — Ludwig V
I have to say, the only alternative to the JTB that I've come across is the "knowledge first" idea. That might have something so recommend it, but I haven't caught up with it yet. — Ludwig V
Quite right. I’m not sure whether you think that induction can never result in knowledge because it is always uncertain or not. — Ludwig V
Your point that Al has no justification for believing that his car has been stolen is a good one. Until she discovers that her car has been stolen, the same is true of Betty, of course. That’s a key problem, of course. Justification can be less than conclusive. — Ludwig V
Seems to me that there is a play on two senses of "know" going on here — Banno
1. Someone (call him Al) has parked his car on Avenue A (out of sight now) half an hour ago. Everything is normal, the car is still there, Al has a good memory. Does he know where his car is?
2. Every day, a certain percentage of cars gets stolen. Does Al know, right now, that his car has not been stolen and driven away since he parked it?
3. Meanwhile, in a parallel universe with a similar crime rate, Betty has parked her car on Avenue B half an hour ago. Betty is cognitively very similar to Al (just as good a memory, just as much confidence about the location of her car). Her car, unfortunately, was stolen and driven away. Does Betty, who believes that her car is on Avenue B where she parked it, know that her car is on Avenue B?
4. Having answered all three questions, would you like to revise your answer to any of them?
5. Why? — Ludwig V
And the distinction between "knowing" and the feeling of knowing. When I follow the proof of a theorem I know the theorem is true according to the rules of the game, and I have a feeling of knowing. But when I park my car out of sight I only feel that I know where it is. So it is conditional knowledge. Most of life is lived in a complex of probabilities.
But then I have the feeling of knowing what I have written is of no consequence in this forum — jgill
This problem was devised by Jonathan Vogel.
1. Someone (call him Al) has parked his car on Avenue A (out of sight now) half an hour ago. Everything is normal, the car is still there, Al has a good memory. Does he know where his car is?
2. Every day, a certain percentage of cars gets stolen. Does Al know, right now, that his car has not been stolen and driven away since he parked it?
3. Meanwhile, in a parallel universe with a similar crime rate, Betty has parked her car on Avenue B half an hour ago. Betty is cognitively very similar to Al (just as good a memory, just as much confidence about the location of her car). Her car, unfortunately, was stolen and driven away. Does Betty, who believes that her car is on Avenue B where she parked it, know that her car is on Avenue B?
4. Having answered all three questions, would you like to revise your answer to any of them?
5. Why? — Ludwig V
A posteriori, he does, but not as a necessary fact. — Wayfarer
Lets try another tact — Philosophim
I tried googling Vogel's paradox. Null result — Agent Smith
Try ChatGPT on Vogel's paradox! — javi2541997
1. Someone (call him Al) has parked his car on Avenue A (out of sight now) half an hour ago. Everything is normal, the car is still there, Al has a good memory. Does he know where his car is?
2. Every day, a certain percentage of cars gets stolen. Does Al know, right now, that his car has not been stolen and driven away since he parked it?
3. Meanwhile, in a parallel universe with a similar crime rate, Betty has parked her car on Avenue B half an hour ago. Betty is cognitively very similar to Al (just as good a memory, just as much confidence about the location of her car). Her car, unfortunately, was stolen and driven away. Does Betty, who believes that her car is on Avenue B where she parked it, know that her car is on Avenue B?
4. Having answered all three questions, would you like to revise your answer to any of them?
5. Why? — Ludwig V
But then I have the feeling of knowing what I have written is of no consequence in this forum. :roll: — jgill
Show □(p→q) → □p→□q is invalid
The statement □(p→q) → □p→□q is not always true in modal logic, and thus it is invalid. A counterexample can be constructed by considering a model where p is true at some possible world w, q is true at another possible world v, and there is no path from w to v. In this model, □(p→q) is true at world w (because there is no world where p is true and q is false), but □p→□q is false at world w (because there is no path from w to a world where q is true).
Me: But □(p→q) → □p→□q is valid
ChatGPT: You are correct. The statement □(p→q) → □p→□q is actually valid in modal logic. I apologize for my previous response. This can be shown using the following argument:
Suppose □(p→q) is true at a world w and □p is true at w. Then, at all possible worlds v accessible from w, p is true (by the definition of □p), and thus either q is true at v or p is false at v (since □(p→q) is true at w). But since p is true at w and there is a path from w to v, it follows that p is true at v. Therefore, q is true at v (since p is true at v and □(p→q) is true at v), and hence □q is true at w. Since this argument holds for any world where □(p→q) is true and □p is true, we can conclude that □(p→q) → □p→□q is valid in modal logic.
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.