On the other hand, in the wake of the Tractatus and Carnap and the rest, we got possible-world semantics; so you could plausibly say that a picture showing how things could be is a picture showing how things are in some possible world, this one or another.
The feeling of "claiming" is gone, but was probably mistaken anyway. In exchange, we get a version of "truth" attached to every proposition, every picture. Under such a framework, this is just how all propositions work, they say how things are somewhere, if not here. Wittgenstein's point could be adjusted: a picture does need to tell you it's true somewhere -- it is -- but it can't tell you if it's true here or somewhere else. — Srap Tasmaner
On this account, both "Berlin" and "2+2=4" are names. Indeed, if a proposition is considered to be a statement with a truth value, then any proposition is just the name of either the true or the false. Assuming bivalency, of course.“What would Frege say about comprehending a singular term?” — J
I was a bit puzzled by this so I asked ChatGPT o1-preview the following question — Pierre-Normand
And every other attempt to define truth collapses too. For in a definition certain characteristics would have to be stated. And in application to any particular case the question would always arise whether it were true that the characteristics
were present. So one goes round in a circle. Consequently, it is probable that the content of the word " true " is unique and indefinable — The Thought: A Logical Enquiry
Just so you know, I'm not going to read that. — Srap Tasmaner
Is there then something between assertion and non-assertion? — Leontiskos
Ok. Whatever else you might think about truth, it's pretty hard to disagree with Tarski. Is that what you want to do? — Banno
An assertion can be displayed, perhaps as an integral part of a proposition, without being an “actual assertion. — J
Forgive my extemporising. — Banno
On this account, both "Berlin" and "2+2=4" are names. Indeed, if a proposition is considered to be a statement with a truth value, then any proposition is just the name of either the true or the false. — Banno
So far as existence is defined, it is defined in terms of the universal quantifier. — Banno
Unless these philosophers explain WHY thought MUST reflect reality (via "logic"), it doesn't seem to have any force to me, except as, ironically, unsupported assertions. — schopenhauer1
For in a definition certain characteristics would have to be stated. And in application to any particular case the question would always arise whether it were true that the characteristics
were present. So one goes round in a circle. Consequently, it is probable that the content of the word " true " is unique and indefinable — The Thought: A Logical Enquiry
Does this amount to pointing out that any definition of “truth” would have to be true, thus opening up the regress? — J
From the other side, once you "grasp" the truth of a situation, have you any choice but to affirm it? This would seem to be somewhat closer to the sense of assertion intended. In other words, Moore's paradox is a simple impossibility: to see the truth of a situation or a proposition is to believe it. — Srap Tasmaner
But I want to make a bit of a different point. On my (admittedly limited) understanding of the Tractatus, one thing a picture is entirely incapable of depicting is that it is true. A picture can show how things might be, and things may indeed be that way, but the picture cannot include itself in its depiction and vouch for its own accuracy.
Just so, my belief that a picture is accurate does not count as evidence that it is. — Srap Tasmaner
We have talked some -- whether we should have or not, I'm not sure --- about whether there's some sense in which propositions are self-asserting. In these terms, whether a picture at least inherently claims that things stand as it shows, even if it cannot itself substantiate that claim. — Srap Tasmaner
After a close read of Kimhi's section 2.5 I see him doing the exact same thing that Srap and I were doing. He says that both a declarative sentence and an asserted declarative sentence "display" force, but whereas the first is "a mere display" the second is "a self-identifying display." — Leontiskos
...what is Kimhi trying to argue here?
Simply working from Boynton, he seems to be saying that if the declarative sentence, "The cloud is raining," does not display an assertion, then it is impossible to say under what conditions the cloud would be raining or not raining. That if "the cloud is raining" and "the cloud is not raining" do not display different assertions, then they could not be associated with different truthmakers. This looks like the same argument that Wittgenstein gives in Rombout 60-62. — Leontiskos
That is what Wittgenstein tries to show by means of this analogy: the difference between (Wittgenstein’s conception of) Fregean assertion and Wittgenstein’s own idea of a sentence saying that its Sinnw is true. In Tractatus a sentence cannot take a meta-position and compare the Sinnw it shows with the world. Therefore, the sentence cannot acknowledge its own truth. A sentence cannot ‘check’ whether it corresponds to the world and decide upon the truth of the claim it makes, there are no extra-linguistic acts attributed to sentences. Nevertheless, every sentence aims at truth. A sentence is a picture of reality and as such it already makes a claim about what reality looks like. That is what 4.022 expresses: a sentence depicts a situation and says that this situation is the case. Sentences are not completely neutral phenomena; in showing a situation, they already ‘support’ that situation. It would be incorrect to ascribe intentions to sentences, but a sentence depicts a possibility and embodies that possibility in the same time: the possibility may in fact not obtain, but the ‘proposal’ the sentence makes is that it does obtain. In representing a possibility, the sentence more or less puts the truth of this possibility under consideration.
<<4.2 The meaning of the sentence is its agreement or disagreement of the possibilities of the existence and non-existence of states of affairs.>>
It is not asserted in the Fregean sense, for this agreement is not assertion. Whether it is actually true, or whether it corresponds to reality, seems to be irrelevant to Wittgenstein, at least for logical considerations. It may be part of the natural sciences or of interest to someone, but it is not relevant when formulating the limits of our thought. The actual truth of a sentence can only be established by a subject, and it is already mentioned that a subject does not belong to logic. — Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein on the Judgment Stroke, by Floor Rombout, 63
As I understand it, 0th level terms - a,b,x - name individuals. Included amongst those individuals are propositions, which in turn name a truth value. So (2+2=4)=(5-3=2)= ⊤. These all name the same individual. So "Berlin" might name the city, and "2+2=5" might name the false.
...
On this account, both "Berlin" and "2+2=4" are names. — Banno
The judgment stoke occurs once in the expression, at the beginning. It affirms the whole expression, not each individual line separately. — Banno
Frege doesn't write
⊢p⊃q
⊢p
⊢q
such that each is within it's own intensional bracket; he writes
⊢(
p⊃q
p
q) — Banno
My bolding. — Banno
Instead of writing the whole inference, consisting of the three assertions “ ⊢ p”, “ ⊢ (p ⊃ q)” and “ ⊢ q” , Russell and Whitehead propose an abbreviation containing the assertions of the two atomic propositions connected by an implication: “ ⊢ p ⊃⊢ q”. Frege would consider this a category mistake; in the Begriffsschrift it is not possible to have a judgment stroke within the scope of a conditional.
...
A reason why Russell and Whitehead consider this abbreviation acceptable can be found in their explanation of syllogisms:
<<It should be observed that syllogisms are traditionally expressed with ‘therefore’, as if they asserted both premises and conclusion. This is, of course, merely a slipshod way of speaking, since what is really asserted is only the connection of premises with conclusion.[36]>>
Where in Frege the premises and the the conclusion, as well as the connection between them need to be asserted in order to constitute an inference, this demand is dropped [by Russell and Whitehead]. What is asserted in [Russell's] syllogism is the connection between premises and the conclusion, not the sentences themselves. This seems to be an explanation for allowing for an abbreviated form, but in order to conclude so, it has to be considered whether a syllogism is an inference. — Rombout, 44-5
"Berlin" correlates to "2+2" (or "4") and "Berlin is a city" correlates to "2+2=4." — Leontiskos
'assertoric force follows if a proposition expressed by an indicative clause is presented as relevant in a context made up of a subset of the hearer's factual assumptions." — frank
Who are you quoting? Certainly not Frege. Assertoric force does not depend on the hearer. — Leontiskos
I feel like I'm stuck in an Abbot & Costello routine! If this really represents what Frege would say to me when I ask him whether he comprehends the word printed on that slip of paper he found on the beach, I could only reply, "Well, yeah, but Herr Frege, I'm not asking about extension or objects or what's permissible or impermissible in your philosophy. Have pity on a fellow beachcomber and just tell me whether you understand the word on the paper or not." — J
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.