I responded personally only when you falsely and snidely insinuated regarding my acquaintanceship with the halting problem and the method of definition. — TonesInDeepFreeze
And deserved though quite slight sarcasm about your claim about Einstein. — TonesInDeepFreeze
I have no comment on Wittgenstein. — TonesInDeepFreeze
I actually said that it was not meant to be a snide comment — Shawn
To think that Einstein didn't have discussions about the import of the defining work of Godel, being his Incompleteness Theorems, would seem like a moot issue to profess skepticism over. — Shawn
this thread was mostly about why Wittgenstein or what Wittgenstein could have meant by claiming that Godel's Incompleteness Theorems are logical tricks. — Shawn
I will get decidedly personal at this point — TonesInDeepFreeze
You must mean that there's no point in you continuing. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Others can choose for themselves. — TonesInDeepFreeze
You must mean that there's no point in you continuing.
— TonesInDeepFreeze
No, you telling me at this point to simply 'shut up' won't happen, sorry. — Shawn
no point in trying to cow down other members, which in this case is your personalization of the issue. — Shawn
Amazing that you got that exactly backwards. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Like I said, I didn't get personal with you until you did with me. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Anyway, this thread was mostly about why Wittgenstein or what Wittgenstein could have meant by claiming that Godel's Incompleteness Theorems are logical tricks. — Shawn
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Remarks_on_the_Foundations_of_Mathematics
Particularly controversial in the Remarks was Wittgenstein's "notorious paragraph", which contained an unusual commentary on Gödel's incompleteness theorems. Multiple commentators read Wittgenstein as misunderstanding Gödel. In 2000 Juliet Floyd and Hilary Putnam suggested that the majority of commentary misunderstands Wittgenstein but their interpretation[8] has not been met with approval.[9][10]
Wittgenstein wrote:
I imagine someone asking my advice; he says: "I have constructed a proposition (I will use 'P' to designate it) in Russell's symbolism, and by means of certain definitions and transformations it can be so interpreted that it says: 'P is not provable in Russell's system'. Must I not say that this proposition on the one hand is true, and on the other hand unprovable? For suppose it were false; then it is true that it is provable. And that surely cannot be! And if it is proved, then it is proved that it is not provable. Thus it can only be true, but unprovable." Just as we can ask, " 'Provable' in what system?," so we must also ask, "'True' in what system?" "True in Russell's system" means, as was said, proved in Russell's system, and "false" in Russell's system means the opposite has been proved in Russell's system.—Now, what does your "suppose it is false" mean? In the Russell sense it means, "suppose the opposite is proved in Russell's system"; if that is your assumption you will now presumably give up the interpretation that it is unprovable. And by "this interpretation" I understand the translation into this English sentence.—If you assume that the proposition is provable in Russell's system, that means it is true in the Russell sense, and the interpretation "P is not provable" again has to be given up. If you assume that the proposition is true in the Russell sense, the same thing follows. Further: if the proposition is supposed to be false in some other than the Russell sense, then it does not contradict this for it to be proved in Russell's system. (What is called "losing" in chess may constitute winning in another game.)[11]
We usually know that a proposition is true because it is provable — Tarskian
If you look at what exactly Gödel's theorem says, There exist propositions in Russell's system that are (true and not provable) or (false and provable) — Tarskian
But if the system is sound, then the second disjunct is precluded. — TonesInDeepFreeze
It is possible to preclude the second disjunct if we assume or prove that PA is sound. I didn't say that PA itself proves that PA is sound. Virtually every mathematician (including Godel) regards PA to be sound. — TonesInDeepFreeze
What we do prove (in, for example, set theory) is that PA has model thus PA is consistent. — TonesInDeepFreeze
if PA is not sound, then it is actually unusable — Tarskian
However, proving soundness is even irrelevant. — Tarskian
Imagine that we prove soundness theorem. — Tarskian
No, because the proposition that proof implies truth is exactly what we are trying to prove. — Tarskian
If you look at what exactly Gödel's theorem says, There exist propositions in Russell's system that are (true and not provable) or (false and provable) — Tarskian
True but unprovable statements vastly outnumber the true and provable ones — Tarskian
The part that requires much proof is that the standard model is a model of PA. — TonesInDeepFreeze
"If a sentence P is provable from a set of sentences G, then all models of G are models of P" — TonesInDeepFreeze
If you look at what exactly Gödel's theorem says, There exist propositions in Russell's system that are (true and not provable) or (false and provable) — Tarskian
Where did Godel say that? — TonesInDeepFreeze
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Diagonal_lemma
Let T be a first-order theory in the language of arithmetic and capable of representing all computable functions, and F(y) be a formula in T with one free variable. Then there exists a sentence C such that
T ⊢ C ⇔ F (⌜C⌝)
Let T be a first-order theory in the language of arithmetic and capable of representing all computable functions. Then there exists a sentence G such that
T ⊢ G ⇔ ¬ Bew(⌜G⌝)
Let T be a first-order theory in the language of arithmetic and capable of representing all computable functions. Then there exists a sentence G such that
G is (true and not provable) or G is (false and provable)
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/G%C3%B6del%27s_incompleteness_theorems
First Incompleteness Theorem: "Any consistent formal system T within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out is incomplete; i.e. there are statements of the language of T which can neither be proved nor disproved in T." (Raatikainen 2020)
There are denumerably many of each. — TonesInDeepFreeze
http://www.sci.brooklyn.cuny.edu/~noson/True%20but%20Unprovable.pdf
We have come a long way since Gödel. A true but unprovable statement is not some strange, rare phenomenon. In fact, the opposite is correct. A fact that is true and provable is a rare phenomenon. The collection of mathematical facts is very large and what is expressible and true is a small part of it. Furthermore, what is provable is only a small part of those.
(1) If PA is consistent, then there is a true but unprovable sentence. — TonesInDeepFreeze
there is no need to prove soundness theorem — Tarskian
Soundness can also be defined without using model theory:
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Soundness — Tarskian
I am obviously not against using model-theoretical notions to define soundness — Tarskian
If you look at what exactly Gödel's theorem says — Tarskian
G is (true and not provable) or G is (false and provable)
This is somewhat equivalent to the alternative phrasing in which we assume consistency:
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/G%C3%B6del%27s_incompleteness_theorems
First Incompleteness Theorem: "Any consistent formal system T within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out is incomplete; i.e. there are statements of the language of T which can neither be proved nor disproved in T." (Raatikainen 2020) — Tarskian
not assume consistency — Tarskian
true and unprovable statements are non-denumerable. — Tarskian
In fact, by introducing the assumption "If PA is consistent", Gödel's theorem is no longer a theorem in PA. In that case, it is a theorem in PA + Cons(PA). That is not the same theory as PA. — Tarskian
That page relies on '|=' which is from model theory. — TonesInDeepFreeze
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Logical_consequence
The turnstile symbol ⊢ was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934–1935).
If PA is consistent, then there are true but unprovable sentences. So, trivially, by disjunction introduction, it follows that there are true but unprovable sentences or there are false but provable sentences.
Meanwhile, for the third time, my remark is correct: If we assume soundness, then the second disjunct is precluded. — TonesInDeepFreeze
There are not only finitely many of them, and there are not uncountably many of them (there are only countably many sentences in the language), so there are denumerably many. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.