And there is a formalistic definition of truth, a statement is true in a theory when that statement holds in every model of that theory. Like "swans are birds" is true because there are no swans which are not birds, but "swans are white" is false because there are swans which are not white.
I would posit that axioms can be considered to be correct when they entail the intended theorems about the object you've conceived.
Whether you have true premises is a different issue. When you stipulate axioms, you treat them as true. Are they true? Upon what basis can they be considered as such?
How would you compare Peano Arithmetic and Robinson Arithmetic, for example? Which one is true? Is one "more true" than another? What about propositional logic and predicate calculus? These aren't rhetorical questions btw.
However, it seems to be something quite different to claim that all[/ claims are true only relative to stipulated systems and that none are more true than any other. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Are any of these more true than any other? — Count Timothy von Icarus
claims are true only relative to stipulated systems and that none are more true than any other. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I don't think logical pluralists are committed to that.
Everyone agrees what follows from what stipulations.
In effect this is a way of massaging the "complete generality" predicate in the OP's argument. You can restore a sense of "complete generality" by using lemmas, by speaking about something ultra specific and formalised you can guarantee that it works in that way for that system, the latter applies without exception. Applies without exception in the sense that "fdrake is sitting drinking tea now" is true at time of writing, and thus applies at that time without exception forever. Only "now" for those refined systems is a new lemma, allowing them to better specify their intended conceptual content.
Do they? Isn't the question one of the questions at issue whether anything follows from anything else? — Count Timothy von Icarus
Do they? Isn't the question one of the questions at issue whether anything follows from anything else? — Count Timothy von Icarus
Am I getting something wrong here? — Srap Tasmaner
those three points determine a unique plane, — Srap Tasmaner
Nice. That cleared something that I was puzzling over. A Great Circle is defined by only two points on the surface. It can do this becasue it is a straight line. So as on a plane, a line can be defined by two points and a circle by three.We're just taking a section of the sphere, without any further reference to the point A, which has already done everything needed to guarantee that its coplanar subsets are circles. In particular, we did not need to project A onto the plane that sections the sphere. (We can project it onto that plane, using the obvious orthogonal projection, or anything we like.) — Srap Tasmaner
I don't think that's an issue at stake at all.
It could be, and I believe Gillian Russel lectures as if, there are valid arguments even if there are no principles which hold in complete generality. Because she specifies what context she's speaking in
Per Russell it is "the claim that there are no laws of logic, i.e., no pairs of premise sets and conclusions such that premises logically entail the conclusion." — Count Timothy von Icarus
like thinning, cut, and the sequent forms of conjunction elimination. The
reason is this: a natural interpretation of the claim that there is no logic is that
the extension of the relation of logical consequence is empty; there is no pairing
of premises and conclusion such that the second is a logical consequence of the
first. This would make any claim of the form Γ |= φ false, but it would not
prevent there from being correct conditional principles.10
A note about vocabulary: arguments are often said to be neither true nor false, but
rather valid or invalid. This is correct as far as it goes, but a principle containing a turnstile
as its main predicate can be regarded as a sentence making claim about the relevant argument.
Such a claim will be true if the argument is valid, false if it is not. Hence the nihilist can be
said to believe that there are no true atomic claims attributing logical consequence.
Either φ is true in a model M, or it is false. In the first case, φ∨¬φ is true in M because of the truth-clauses for ∨. In the second case, ¬φ is true in M because of the truth-clause for negation, and
so again φ ∨ ¬φ is true in M. So either way it is true in the model, and—since M was arbitrary—it is true in all models. So φ ∨ ¬φ is a logical truth...
So we examine our simple proof and realise that our assumption that the sentence could only be true or false is violated by the monster*. Hence our culprit is the assumption that sentences can
only be true and false. Still, perhaps there are some sentences which can only be true or false—sentences in the language of arithmetic might be like—and our result would hold for these. Our new theorem reads: for any φ which can only be true or false, φ ∨ ¬φ is a logical truth. Just as the geometry teacher dubs polyhedra which satisfy the stretchability lemma simple, so we could give a name to sentences which meet our assumption. Perhaps bivalent would be suitable. Then we can retain the proof above as a proof of:
For all bivalent φ, φ=>φv~φ
A Great Circle is defined by only two points on the surface. It can do this becasue it is a straight line. So as on a plane, a line can be defined by two points and a circle by three. — Banno
But... P & P => Q entails Q in propositional logic, who is denying this?
The cases approach allows us to say more about what logical nihilism amounts to: it is the view that for any set of premises Γ and conclusion φ whatsoever, there is a case in which every member of Γ is true, but φ is not. — p.4
On the interpretations conception then, logical nihilism is the view that for every argument, Γ φ, there are interpretations of the non-logical expressions in Γ and φ which would make every member of Γ true, but φ not true. — p.5
She adopts the interpretations approach, but for simplicity. She gives the impression that her argument might be made using the other two approaches. She proceeds to show how P →Q,Q ⊨P is truth-preserving if the interpretation includes only T; but not if it includes both T and F. That is, it is a logical law under one interpretation, but not under another. She then shows how the law of excluded middle is a logical law in the interpretation (T,F), but not in (T,F,N).On (the universalist) approach, logical nihilism would be the view that for any argument, there is an assignment which makes all the premises true without making the conclusion true. — p.5
In effect the nihilist doubt machine gets going by noticing that there's arbitrary degrees of contextual variation — fdrake
1) Gillian is in Banf.
2) Therefore, I am in Banf.
to
1) Gillian is in Banf
2) I am Gillian
3) Therefore, I am in Banf — fdrake
you can tell it to sod off by specifying the exact mess you're in — fdrake
Has it been fixed? The "sophist" would say no, and can quibble endlessly. They might ask you to specify what exactly "I am Gillian" means; what 'I' means; what a name is; what the predication of amness means (all difficult questions). They might splice (1) and (2) into different contexts, pointing out that (1) is a third-person description and (2) is a first-person description, and that it is not clear that these two discrete contexts can produce a conclusion that bridges them. "Shit-testing" seems to have no limits and no measure. — Leontiskos
Logical nihilism is not a claim about what is true in classical extensional logic. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Can you? There is an idea that floats around, according to which one can give quibble-proof arguments. I don't think this is right. I'd say the idea that there is some quibble-proof level of exactness won't cash out. — Leontiskos
Let x belong to the field of real numbers.
Stipulate that x+1=2
therefore x=2-1
therefore x=1
There is an interesting question about the great circle, but the method which outright denies that the great circle is a circle can outright deny anything it likes. It is the floodgate to infinite skepticism. I think we need to be a bit more careful about the skeptical tools we are using. They backfire much more easily than one is led to suppose. — Leontiskos
Russell's approach is largely telling logical nihilists not to throw the baby out with the bathwater — fdrake
the great circle might be taken as a countermodel for Euclid's definition of a circle — fdrake
Our dispute was similar to the former - we both have the same pretheoretical intuitions about what a circle is. Agreeing on Euclid's and on the great circle's satisfaction of it. And we'd probably agree on the weird examples containing deleted points too, they would not be circles even though if you drew them they'd look exactly like circles. — fdrake
and I kept asking you to repair it. — fdrake
Whereas your examples do not insist on taking the conceptual content of what's said for granted, indeed they're attempting to distort it. Allegorically, the logic of shit testing is that of a particularly sadistic genie - taking someone at their word but exactly at their word, using whatever pretheoretical concepts they have. The logic of your sophist is closer to doubting the presuppositions which are necessary for the original problem to be stated to begin with. — fdrake
Where's the issue? — fdrake
To be clear you would have been compelled to deny the great circle was a circle by only using Euclid's definition of it verbatim, I would not have! — fdrake
To take a few, you haven't defined the operations, commutativity relations, numbers, variables, etc. — Leontiskos
fdrake, what is the confusion here, do you think? Is it to do with the commensurability of differing logical systems? If logical monism is the view that all logical systems are commensurable, then there is presumably some notion of translation that works between them all. I find that difficult to picture. Perhaps all logics might be found to be variations on Lambda Calculus or some other "foundational" logic, in which case there would be one true logic, begging for some wit to find a logic that is not based on that foundation. — Banno
begging for some wit to find a logic that is not based on that foundation. — Banno
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.