No. Kids will ask wha the highest number is. Takes them a while to see that there isn't one. — Banno
Notice that the existence (as a thought) of such an individual is here just assumed. — Banno
What a mess. So god is not the thing greater than everything, but the thing greater than the thing greater than everything. — Banno
Might be. — Banno
Okay, so you're not actually objecting to step (2) of the proof? — Leontiskos
I did fix the ugly: g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x). I asked you if it was acceptable, and did not yet get a reply. — Banno
The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere int he argument. — Banno
So the argument will not be of much use in convincing non-theists. — Banno
Klima is explicit that step (2) is a supposition and that step (1) is a definition, so I'm not sure what you're attempting to disagree with. — Leontiskos
Your misrepresentation is still there: (1) g=dfix.~($y)(M(y)(x)) (as well as the other lines of the proof where similar problems occur). — Leontiskos
g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) — Banno
I was wrong about the paper. Sorry for being so stubborn and impatient, and for unnecessarily derailing the thread. — Banno
Consider an analogous argument defining the highest number as that number which is higher than any other number. The definition is fine, except that there is no such highest number.
The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere in the argument. The task for the logician is to find out where.
Close, perhaps. This objection is specific to the argument at hand. The intrinsic limit needed is missing from g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x), which is "God is defined as the thought object x such that no y can be thought to be greater than x", and the objection is not that anything might fit this, as that nothing might fit this. The question is, is the idea of such an object coherent? It's analogous to defining a number x such that no number y can be greater than it. There an be no such number.Gaunilo of Marmoutier took this approach — Count Timothy von Icarus
Quite so. It would be a surprise if an argument could demonstrate the existence of something ex nihilo, as it were. And yes, what is assumed is a being of thought. But what supposedly pops out of the algorithm is something else. The move from ens rationis to ens reale only works if we already accept that "existing in reality" is a necessary property of the greatest conceivable being.if the issue is that the conclusion must be contained in the premises, that's a problem for all deductive arguments. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I'm gonna Pontifications from 30,000 feet again. The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere in the argument. The task for the logician is to find out where.
They must do this because existence cannot result from a deduction. It can only be presumed, either in the argument or in the interpretation. — Banno
To be sure, it is not clear that the definition g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) can be made coherently... — Banno
...it is not clear that [it] can be made coherently... — Banno
The generic flaw in ontological arguments is that if they are valid then they assume the conclusion somewhere in the argument. — Banno
So you can't just write g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) without a problem, becasue it may be that there is no greatest individual. — Banno
But if you manage that, you have the analogue of the transfinite numbers - no sooner have you defined g as the greatest, and then you can bring to mind something greater than g, and the problem repeats itself.
So even as there is good reason to think that it is not possible to make sense of "the largest number", it is difficult to see how to make sense of "the greatest individual". — Banno
IF the argument is valid, and it shows that something exists, then that must be assumed in the argument somewhere. That's how logic works. The problem isn’t just that the argument assumes its conclusion, since as Tim pointed out all valid deductive arguments do that. — Banno
(Some of my own philosophical arguments have been accused of something very like ‘begging the question’ – I concede the phrase was not used – simply because they were formally valid arguments for a conclusion the accusers thought was false. Their reasoning seems to have been something like this: if the conclusion of an argument can be formally deduced from its premises, then that conclusion is, as one might put it, logically contained in the premises – and thus one who affirms those premises is assuming that the conclusion is true. As R. M. Chisholm once remarked when confronted with a similar criticism, ‘I stand accused of the fallacy of affirming the antecedent.’) — Peter van Inwagen, Begging the Question
The argument becomes "God exists therefore god exists". — Banno
The move from ens rationis to ens reale only works if we already accept that "existing in reality" is a necessary property of the greatest conceivable being. — Banno
But I think real problem for ontological arguments is that they are unconvincing. I don't think anyone has been converted by an ontological argument, or that many people of faith feel their faith significantly bolstered by such arguments. — Count Timothy von Icarus
No.It sounds like you're saying that we can't have a being of reason if it isn't a being. Or in other words: we can't think of what doesn't exist. "X doesn't exist, therefore we cannot think of it." — Leontiskos
Yeah, it does, and that can be shown. But you wanted small steps.But the proof at hand does not assume that — Leontiskos
Not at all. I address it quite specifically:you simply overlook Klima's "ampliation" — Leontiskos
One of the points I made is that Klima does not make use of the "ampliation" in (1), and he ought. The point was repeated and expanded, here:Trouble is, that is not what g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) says. God is still a thought object, albeit the greatest thought object. — Banno
Following the analogue, the first transfinite number is
ω:=min{x∣x is an ordinal and ∀n∈N,n<x}
You need something like this, but with g for ω. But notice that ω is an ordinal, and is define as greater than any natural number. This avoids the contradiction that would result if ω were defined as greater than any other ordinal, or as a natural number greater than any natural number.
So you can't just write g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x) without a problem, becasue it may be that there is no greatest individual. You need god to be something else, not an individual or not a part of the domain or something, to avoid shooting yourself in the foot.
But if you manage that, you have the analogue of the transfinite numbers - no sooner have you defined g as the greatest, and then you can bring to mind something greater than g, and the problem repeats itself.
So even as there is good reason to think that it is not possible to make sense of "the largest number", it is difficult to see how to make sense of "the greatest individual". — Banno
Gaunilo of Marmoutier took this approach by positing an "island greater than which none can be conceived," in order to try to show that Anselm's argument can be used to demonstrate the existence of all sorts of things. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Banno is engaged in a form of concept denial, which he would need to flesh out. — Leontiskos
So you want me to flesh out your concept of god for you. — Banno
Your objection relies on the idea that some concepts cannot exist even as beings of reason — Leontiskos
And so far I am only looking at premise (1), no further. We can go on when this bit has been understood. — Banno
One of the points I made is that Klima does not make use of the "ampliation" in (1), and he ought. — Banno
Yep. Concepts that contradict themselves. Like "The largest number". — Banno
If you want to raise your own objection, go ahead. I've raised mine, with (1), and you have yet to address it.The problem with objecting to the two-place predicate M()() in premise (1) without looking at premise (3) is... — Leontiskos
I explained that, with the comparison to infinity and transfinite numbers given then quoted above. TO achieve the desired ampliation one needs to go a step past g:=ix¬(∃y)M(y,x), just as one can't get to infinity by iteratively picking the next highest number.Why don't you think he is making use of ampliation in (1)? — Leontiskos
Will someone be good enough to provide as an aid to navigation a simple proposition expressing exactly what they think Anselm proves? — tim wood
And the same service for Gyula Klima's paper? — tim wood
But that it was essentially the same conception of reference that was at work in his mind when he formulated his arguments in the Proslogion is clearly shown by his insistence against Gaunilo that his crucial description “that than which nothing greater can be thought of” is in no way to be equated with “greater than everything”. It is precisely the ampliative force, recognized as such by 12th-century logicians, that is missing from the latter, and is missed from it, though not described as such, by Saint Anselm in his response to Gaunilo’s objection. — Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 1
ω:=min{x∣x is an ordinal and ∀n∈N,n<x} — Banno
Anselm thinks he proves that the very idea of god shows that He exists. He's mistaken. Klima realises this, but still sees a use for such arguments in explaining to non-theists how theists think about the world. He is specifically advocating not becoming involved in the sort of discussion now occurring here, that the parties 'should not seek sheer “winning” in a debate'.Will someone be good enough to provide as an aid to navigation a simple proposition expressing exactly what they think Anselm proves? And the same service for Gyula Klima's paper? — tim wood
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.