Comments

  • Phenomenalism

    That's only fair, given the title of the thread.

    Phenomenalism is the view that physical objects cannot justifiably be said to exist in themselves, but only as perceptual phenomena or sensory stimuli (e.g. redness, hardness, softness, sweetness, etc.) situated in time and in space. In particular, some forms of phenomenalism reduce all talk about physical objects in the external world to talk about bundles of sense data.

    We see others (from the outside) as creatures with eyes and ears and noses and brains. If we check in their skulls, we don't expect to find a soul, not with the naked eye. We trust that a man without eyes is blind and that a man without a living brain is not present at all but only a corpse. This third-person POV lends an initial plausibility to what I'll call the enclosure theory.

    It starts plausibly enough, though not without cracks . Atoms or waves banging against sense organs and their nerve cells cause brain to put on a magic show for (or as) the ghost in the machine. This ghost knows what it means to say, even if the words are hard to find, because meaning, like sensation, is pure , immaterial, ghost stuff. The 'ghost' or 'soul' is 'behind' or hidden in the body in some strange way, perhaps in the pineal gland...just as meaningstuff is 'behind' or hidden in the words that carry it.

    At this point in the theory, 'we' still believe in the everyday world, but we've set something up by taking the ghost too seriously. Note that sensations and meanings are immaterial, so that the ghost is theorized to get only immaterial manifestations or appearances of the (once real) world.

    It becomes plausible (?) that only the ghost is real ! Despite its birth in a third-person point of view. We assumed that atoms/waves 'really' exist for all of us in one shared world, banging away at our individual nervous systems, so that a colorblind or nearsighted person will talk and act a little differently...see the 'same' things differently. But if the sense organs and the atoms and waves are all just entities in a dream (immaterial sensations organized by immaterial concepts), the whole theory of the 'dream' (of the veil-of-ideas) loses its plausibility. [Note that the sense-organs are presented as being created by the sense-organs, with the brain being the fantasy of the brain being the fantasy of the brain...if one doubts the real world that is.]
  • Please help me here....
    I compare any antiphenemenological stance to interplanetary civilizations; in a sense phenomenology is, to put it mildly, mundane, restricted to, let's just say, (a) special case(s). Mind you, I'm not disagreeing with ya.Agent Smith

    I think we're on the same page. A philosophy book should tell us about the/our world. It can do this be focusing on the 'how' of our seeing it, and phen. sometimes does this well (Heidegger's hammer is cool!). I'm mostly just griping that constructing the world from the inside out doesn't make much sense. Yet it's taken as the 'obvious' starting point. It's like 'well clearly Venusians run the world, but we don't know if it's through the CIA or the Girls Scouts of America.'
  • Please help me here....
    I'm glad you approve. It'll be good for your soul to return to your your Hegel, Heidegger and Derrida etc. :wink: : analytic philosophy is too anal, and if one keeps at it too long one disappears up one's own arse.Janus

    To be frank, I gave you the thumbs up to acknowledge what I perceived as your expression disinterest. I love literature and music and <everything else Romantics love> too, but when I do philosophy, it's because I feel like being fussy and careful with concepts, doing something like math, except concepts are more like living wood than cast iron. It's just not for me to argue for the glory of maintaining a respectable metaphysics. It's mostly not practical, and it' definitely a fussy or anal thing to do. But that makes it something like an art. I like when concepts fit together beautifully. Flower arrangement ? But that's Romantic.

    To me the philosophers from both (once-)feuding families all fit together. Brandom and Sellars are great, both arguably 'fixing' Hegel, removing the mystic bluster, keeping the crucial insight into the sociality and autonomy of reason. I take early Derrida to be a Husserl scholar making quasi-Rylean points against the core of phenomenological version of the myth of the given, but from more of an historical angle, tracing the superstition back to Aristotle, for instance.

    As to 'dissappearing up one's own arse,' avoiding this is one motive against theories of the private mind that would make up-our-own-arses the only safe hiding place from doubt. Some would build a little world up there, with exactly one citizen, speaking a language made just for him, within which concepts always conveniently mean just what he thinks they mean. Is this not a bunker metaphysics ? Not even the NSA can peek in. And the only things allowed in are those I can't be wrong about.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    Some time later: it’s actually pretty good. First I read only the posted excerpt, hence the disagreement, only later the whole link, which helps the context of the post.Mww

    :up:

    Nice to hear !
  • The unexplainable
    And through all that, the subject remains the subject: the limit of your world.Tate

    From my POV, it's on you to distinguish this 'limit' from a mere nothingness, a mere 'I think' tag that's added to every fact. As the self shrinks to a point without extension, to the mere field of vision itself, to some synonym for being itself, inexplicably flickering on a causal nexus it plays no role in?
  • Is there an external material world ?
    It is when philosophers began attempting to take account of meaningful human experience that things went awry.creativesoul
    :up:

    Some of them made serious mistakes. I'll grant you that readily.

    Biological machinery is internal. Oranges are external. Meaningful experience involving oranges consists of both, internal and external things.creativesoul

    Of course I agree, as a matter of common sense and ordinary language. But personally I wouldn't want all philosophers to have to take so much for granted...even if most of the time we get silly talk from this license.
  • Phenomenalism
    When you think about it, ideas and sensations are the most familiar thing to us.Olivier5

    To put it jokingly, it's when we don't think about it...that they seem closest to us. What I mean by this joke is that we take the Cartesian 'veil-of-ideas' for granted, thanks to an unquestioned kneejerk inheritance.
  • Is there an external material world ?
    The absurdity of the question is readily apparent to anyone and everyone first hearing it.creativesoul

    I grant that most people, even philosophers, see its practical nullity. But it really seems to be a big part of the tradition that we work from the ghost outward, with only the ghost truly, securely known, leaving all the rest a mere hypothesis, however likely.

    So the challenge is to make its absurdity apparent to philosophers locked deep in the idea that they are locked deep in a pineal gland which itself is a mere dream of a pineal gland which is itself ....
  • Phenomenalism
    I'm fine with that, because it does not imply an observer.Olivier5

    I like Sellars and Popper for trying to figure out how to talk about the world without having to talk about anything mystical or hidden like sensation or experience. These concepts are fine for everyday use, but they've led philosophers to strange, questionable positions.
  • Please help me here....
    Right you are! Good job!Agent Smith

    Phenomenology can be good, but it often leans into the usual ghost story. Why is that bad ? The ghost story, in most of its forms, is obsolete -- has been shown to be wrong or incoherent. Because it's outlandish and daring, it's supposed to be sophisticated, but believers are quick to tell you that 'practically' they are just like everyone else. So it's a bad theory that serves no purpose, hackneyed poetry basically, 'describing ' the world by denying it ... insisting it cannot be described, does not exist, etc.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    Yep, it doth not make any sense at all!Agent Smith

    :up:
  • The unexplainable
    Sounds like you've got some identity issues.Tate

    Oh it's a good topic for humor, but your man Wittgenstein gave me the idea.

    Or imagine that it were usual for human beings to have two characters, in this way: People's shape, size and characteristics of behaviour periodically undergo a complete change. It is the usual thing for a man to have two such states, and he lapses suddenly from one into the other. It is very likely that in such a society we should be inclined to christen every man with two names, and perhaps to talk of the pair of persons in his body. Now were Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde two persons or were they the same person who merely changed? We can say whichever we like. We are not forced to talk of a double personality.

    I speculate that it's just far more efficient to assign one 'player' to each body, more with the grain of our biology perhaps. It would be challenging as well to praise or rebuke (or marry or imprison) the correct 'player' if more than one locus of responsibility, one player, was associated with the same body.

    In another passion (can't remember where), Wittgenstein discusses the idea of personalities as mere patterns of behavior, (understood to be) trading bodies. Descartes sought to be presuppositionless, but these examples show how difficult that is, how 'thrown' we are into inherited interpretive habits that we've never been able to question...not until a madman or a philosopher shows up and teaches us how. Perhaps it's like genetic mutation, almost always a bad thing, but sometimes lucky.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    But it seems to me that you want the solipsist to explain what it means to exist whilst simultaneously claiming that other minds and mind-independent objects can be known to exist, which is clearly special pleading.Michael


    I grant the possibility of the last actual rational agent, dying of radiation poisoning, deciding not to bother writing a sad poem about his self-annihilating species.

    I don't expect philosophers to ever finish clarifying what it means for something to exists. I have suggested that a minimal, neutral understanding of 'external world' is that which (the) 'I' can be wrong about, and this is basically the appearance-reality distinction. The epistemological solipsist says that it is wrong for any rational agent to assume this dichotomy,for things might be different than they appear. Despite appearances, there might 'really' only be appearances.

    I take it that you don't accept my 'translation,' but what else could a solipsist be denying of any interest ? Isn't the appearance distinction itself the target ? And is it not absurd to be cautious about this distinction ? Be careful ! One can be wrong about the possibility of being wrong...
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    What norms; what is a norm and from whence do they arise?Mww

    That's a good question, and, as you might expect, philosophers haven't forgot to speculate. But as philosophers, their speculations are already subject to the very norms they make explicit. Our minimal situation seems to include, along with us of course, shared conceptual and inferential norms (language/logic) and a 'world' or shared situation we can be wrong and therefore right about.

    I'm on a Brandom kick lately, and I'm hoping you'll enjoy what he makes/takes of Kant.


    As I understand his work, Kant’s most basic idea, the axis around which all his thought turns, is that what distinguishes exercises of judgment and intentional agency from the performances of merely natural creatures is that judgments and actions are subject to distinctive kinds of normative assessment. Judgments and actions are things we are in a distinctive sense responsible for. They are a kind of commitment we undertake. Kant understands judging and acting as applying rules, concepts, that determine what the subject becomes committed to and responsible for by applying them. Applying concepts theoretically in judgment and practically in action binds the concept user, commits her, makes her responsible, by opening her up to normative assessment according to the rules she has made herself subject to.

    The responsibility one undertakes by applying a concept is a task responsibility: a commitment to do something. On the theoretical side, what one is committed to doing, what one becomes liable to assessment as to one’s success at doing, is integrating one’s judgments into a whole that exhibits a distinctive kind of unity: the synthetic unity of apperception. It is a systematic, rational unity, dynamically created and sustained by drawing inferential consequences from and finding reasons for one’s judgments, and rejecting commitments incompatible with those one has undertaken. Apperceiving, the characteristically sapient sort of awareness, is discursive (that is, conceptual) awareness. For it consists in integrating judgments into a unity structured by relations of what judgments provide reasons for and against what others. And those rational relations among judgments are determined by the rules, that is the concepts, one binds oneself by in making the judgments. Each new episode of experience, paradigmatically the making of a perceptual judgment, requires integration into, and hence transformation of the antecedent constellation of commitments. New incompatibilities can arise, which must be dealt with critically by rejecting or modifying prior commitments. New joint consequences can ensue, which must be acknowledged or rejected. The process by which the whole evolves and develops systematically is a paradigmatically rational one, structured by the rhythm of inhalation or amplification by acknowledging new commitments and extracting new consequences, and exhalation or criticism by rejecting or adjusting old commitments in the light of their rational relations to the new ones.
    ...
    But the minimal unit of responsibility is the judgment. It is judgments, not concepts, that one can invest one’s authority in, commit oneself to, by integrating them into an evolving constellation that exhibits the rational synthetic unity of apperception. Accordingly, in a radical break with his predecessors, Kant takes judgments to be the minimal units of awareness and experience. Concepts are to be understood analytically, as functions of judgment—that is, in terms of the contribution they make to judgeable contents. To be candidates for synthesis into a system exhibiting the rational unity characteristic of apperception, judgments must stand to one another in relations of material consequence and incompatibility. So if one is to understand judging also as the application of concepts, the first question one must ask about the contents of those concepts how the use of one or another concept affects those rational relations among the judgeable contents that result. This methodological inversion is commitment to the explanatory primacy of the propositional.
    ...
    I read Hegel as taking over from Kant commitment both to a normative account of conceptual doings, and to a broadly pragmatist approach to understanding the contents of our cognitive and practical commitments in terms of what we are doing in undertaking those commitments. I see him as taking an important step toward naturalizing the picture of conceptual norms by taking those norms to be instituted by public social recognitive practices. Further, Hegel tells a story about how the very same practice of rational integration of commitments undertaken by applying concepts that is the synthesis at once of recognized and recognizing individual subjects and of their recognitive communities,
    is at the same time the historical process by which the norms that articulate the contents of the concepts applied are instituted, determined, and developed. He calls that on-going social, historical process “experience” (Erfahrung), and no longer sees it as taking place principally between the ears of an individual.
    — Brandom
    https://sites.pitt.edu/~rbrandom/Texts/From_German_Idealism_to_American_Pragmat.pdf
  • The unexplainable

    Thanks.

    It seems to me that 'I think' is an implicitly or explicitly added tag to whatever 'I' say. I could be weird and say that @Pie claims P. As I see it, it only makes sense to invent and track a self if there's a community who's keeping score. Of course we have individual bodies, but was it logically necessary to assign a single 'soul' or 'ghost' or 'tag' to each body ? This is another problem with Descartes. Why is it 'I' think rather than 'we' think or 'it' thinks ?
  • Phenomenalism
    But it also follows that "the set of all true claims" is also a representation, a "map". It would be the map of an omniscient, supernatural entity.Olivier5

    OK, but He wouldn't need the map ? For Him, I believe P would also just be P.

    Our human maps are gross simplifications of their territory, always. That's why they are useful to us, feeble humans. There is such a thing as "too much information".Olivier5

    I totally agree that actual maps strip away confusing complexity.

    I can imagine a least squares regression line serving metaphorically as a map. I don't want to study 20,000 data points. Give me the gist.

    The world is the real thing, the ground of being. It is.Olivier5

    In my opinion, 'it is' is...on to something. That's what I like about 'the world is all that is case.' It's tempting to say more, but it seems to me that one always says too much. It's also hard to define truth. Its grammar is so brutally simple and absolute, that we always say too much. Because a warranted statement can be false, and an unwarranted statement can be true. It's as if all we can productively talk about is warrant.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)


    This sounds a bit like 'if you think a thesis is incoherent or ambiguous, it's your fault! ' Please recall that I've offered a theory of the minimal epistemic situation. It does not make sense for a philosopher to assert, as a philosopher, that there isn't necessarily a world to make an assertions about, for this assertion is either about a world (ours) or just fundamentally confused.



    Recall also that we discussed the ambiguity of 'exist' earlier. Do you not recall ?

    OK, but debating what 'exists' means is fair game, no?Pie

    Yes.Michael

    It's seems absurd to forbid philosophers the further clarification of fundamental concepts. Indeed, your solpisist makes claims about (further clarifies) the limitations of (the concepts) knowledge and reason...which either exceed him into an 'external' world, lending his claims their force...or fail to concern us, because he's not talking about you and me and any potential rational agent ?
  • The unexplainable

    Correct me if I'm wrong. I was very passionate about the TLP once, but I haven't studied it recently.
    Anything I can see, is not the I that sees it. Nor is anything the I can think the 'I' itself. The 'I' is like the field of vision, not an object in the field. Even the concept of the 'I' is never it. The 'I' is Sartre's nothingness, basically, a similar thought. We have almost a negative theology here.
    How, then, did we ever come up with the concept/word 'I' ? What are its primary uses ?

    Sartre devotes a great deal of effort to establishing the impersonal (or “pre-personal”) character of consciousness, which stems from its non-egological structure and results directly from the absence of the I in the transcendental field. According to him, intentional (positional) consciousness typically involves an anonymous and “impersonal” relation to a transcendent object:

    When I run after a streetcar, when I look at the time, when I am absorbed in contemplating a portrait, there is no I. […] In fact I am plunged in the world of objects; it is they which constitute the unity of my consciousness; […] but me, I have disappeared; I have annihilated myself. There is no place for me on this level. (Sartre 1936a [1957: 49; 2004: 8])

    The tram appears to me in a specific way (as “having-to-be-overtaken”, in this case) that is experienced as its own mode of phenomenalization, and not as a mere relational aspect of its appearing to me. The object presents itself as carrying a set of objective properties that are strictly independent from one’s personal relation to it. The streetcar is experienced as a transcendent object, in a way that obliterates and overrides, so to speak, the subjective features of conscious experience; its “having-to-be-overtaken-ness” does not belong to my subjective experience of the world but to the objective description of the way the world is (see also Sartre 1936a [1957: 56; 2004: 10–11]). When I run after the streetcar, my consciousness is absorbed in the relation to its intentional object, “the streetcar-having-to-be-overtaken”, and there is no trace of the “I” in such lived-experience.

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/#TranEgoDiscInte
  • Phenomenalism
    Maps have to represent something... What's the use of a map about nothing?Olivier5

    Exactly. That's the point I've been making. What does the map represent ?

    Let me repeat my theory. The world is something like the set of true claims. If we try to jam the map metaphor into this new context, we might say that the 'map' is our set of warranted but defeasible claims. But we can also just drop the representation metaphor (maps, lenses, mirrors).
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    It doesn’t seem to be anything like what is usually meant, which concerns the existence of objects that are independent of my mind.Michael

    I'm asking you make some kind of sense of this 'independent of my mind' that's better than 'something I can be wrong about, something I can misunderstand or perceive.' A philosopher making claims about knowledge in general and not just his knowledge seems to be talking about public concepts, external to his understanding of them.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)


    The ghost story remark was meant to emphasize that it's superfluous. Inferences have assertions as inputs and assertions as outputs. To be sure, James can assert that "the stoplight was red," but the ghostly redness-in-itself does not appear in our reasoning, except as a sort of phlogiston.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    What.....you don’t? That can’t be right; you’ve already admitted to it, calling it “one and universal”.Mww

    Nice try !

    I do believe that norms govern our claims, yes indeed, but neither of us is foolish enough to infer from this that the dove can fly in a vacuum. The possibility of translation from German to English need not force us to take 'meaning' to have (its only) existence in some ghost, 'behind' the signifiers.
  • The unexplainable
    think it's probably a mistake to take Wittgenstein as advocating any particular metaphysics. I've been taking him as just exploring the mechanics of climbing the ladder.Tate

    To me, he destroys the theory that meaning is private (to name just one result.) I just happen to be interested in clarifying what it means to mean something, how we do and how we ought to settle beliefs, etc. The 'big' insight for me was something like the intrinsic publicity of meaning, what it means to be 'in' a language with others, the way that very notion of the 'I' is a token caught up in a public, worldly 'game.' I think the realization starts around Hegel, and its enemy or the superstition it opposes is the ghost story criticized by Ryle (and the later Wittgenstein.)
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    As I keep saying, we can make claims about things that don’t exist, and about things that do exist but that cannot be known to exist.Michael

    Indeed, sir, indeed. But claiming that X doesn't exist is a claim about something, about our 'external' 'world.' What is the target of the claim 'God doesn't exist' or 'the world doesn't exist'? What's it about ? If not our shared situation ? Which I claim is fundamental, however underspecified..for the rest is absurdity. "It is not the case that we are in a shared situation. (Our shared situation fails to include a shared situation.)" It's the nature of concepts and rationality to do target this 'space of reasons.' ES makes the claim about our shared situation that we should not assume we are in a shared situation.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    As I keep saying, we can make claims about things that don’t exist, and about things that do exist but that cannot be known to exist. Your arguments just don’t seem to address the claim being made by solipsists, which is just about the limitations of knowledge.Michael

    Are the limitations of knowledge part of the (external) world ?
  • Aristotelian logic: why do “first principles” not need to be proven?
    "Inference or proof is parasitic; it requires knowledge by other means which it can then use to extend what is known."Sam26
  • Antinatalism Arguments

    Fair enough. The right amount/kind of desire can be fun though. Dopamine, immersion in the game.
  • The unexplainable
    5.632 The subject does not belong to the world but it is a limit of the world.Tate

    I know that line from his early work, and that's something we can talk about. But I'm especially coming from the point of view of his later work (PI and OC) (just to elucidate the 'antithetical' comment, not to end the discussion.)
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)


    Does it makes sense, in your view, for a mathematical realist to deny an external world ?
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    I don’t know what you mean by asking who it’s true for. It’s just either true or false.Michael

    My point has been that the minimal version of the world (of the 'external') as opposed to the self (the 'internal') is something we can be wrong about.

    Is the 'self' understood as something that can believe things, make claims, or not ?
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    he just argues that it cannot be known to be true.Michael

    To me this is a claim about the very world that supposedly cannot be known to exist. 'All rational minds ought to assent to the logical/normative impossibility of their proving that there is something beyond them.' If epistemological solipsism is aimed at elucidating a self-transcending concept, what's it doing ? "If others exist, they are bound by such norms." This is a statement about the 'external' world, a claim that should be valid after the death of the philosopher making it. It doesn't matter if the others exist. The (external) world is such that, if there are rational agents in it, they are bound to acknowledge that they cannot be certain that there is a world.

    The 'external' world here is basically a public concept or set of concepts, about which claims are made.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    A mathematical antirealist will reject the independent existence of mathematical entitiesMichael

    He or she will say that such entities don't exist independently...which is true of or a fact about what world ? And for who ? Our world, for us, those jointly subject to the same rational-conceptual norms. And it's not just those who are contingently alive now, but also for those who might be here in the future or in a hypothetical scenario.
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    Sure we do, but it is never necessary that we do, with respect to the aforementioned minimally rational intelligible epistemic situations.Mww

    Do you believe in some kind of wordless angelic 'language' of 'pure' concept, unsoiled by the filthy outerworld ? I suggest that no particular language is necessary but that some language is.

    Can’t blame the late Renaissance or Enlightenment folks that removed the deistic impediment to human intellectualismMww

    I love the moderns, and I think some of them embraced the veil-of-ideas paradigm for good reasons, such as to escape 'inner lights' and innate ideas that 'proved God.' As long as sensations reports are kept in the same causal nexus as worldly objects affecting sense organs, there's no problem. But it's absurd to doubt the sense organs and our separate human bodies then babble about a 'self' that's made only of babble and sensations.

    'Experience' is a ghost story (See Sellars' 'myth of the given.')
  • Antinatalism Arguments

    I think we basically agree. My point was just that we can consciously choose unconsciousness. A person can risk death to protect their child. A person can stand up against a tyrant, make a grand speech, knowing it'll lead to the guillotine. Duels were common once. In short, it's part of our calculations, and I suspect that death is often thought of as a deep sleep, as a sort of zero state, neither good nor bad.
  • Phenomenalism
    It's like Hotel California: you can check out any time you want, but you can never leave representation.Olivier5

    So all we ever have is map map map ?

    But why the representation metaphor then ?
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    And root 2 is irrational even if I’m the only man alive. It’s even irrational even if nobody is alive.Michael

    I basically agree, and it seems to be a truth about something external to our epistemological solipsist, for it doesn't die with him or need him around. And "we can't know there's a world" seems to be about the world in the same way.


    It’s “independent” in the sense that we can be wrong when we do maths, but mathematical entities don’t have some “external” existence in the way that atoms or Platonic ideas are said to have.Michael

    This is problematic. You are retreating into figurative uses (putting them in quotes ) of the words I'm asking you to clarify in the first place. Independent of the subject might as well be 'external,' unless the spatial metaphor is important.

    Not everyone says that atoms are "external." Consider Mach's weird views, which are adjacent to solipsism. Platonism is widely challenged. The main point is that those setting beliefs together rationally understand that they can be right or wrong.
  • Please help me here....
    I'd rather preserve my mental resources for more creative, poetic pursuits, in the interest of intensifying the richness of the stream of imagery that is my phenomenal life.Janus

    it's just too anal.Janus

    :up:
  • Our Minimal Epistemic Commitment (Fixing Descartes' Cogito)
    Not it doesn't. It says that knowledge of other minds (and an external world) is impossible.Michael

    I know...so what do you make of external world ? How do you cash that out ? It's 'outside' the self, different from the self.

    Maths and logic are something "other" than the subject, but I don't think it right to think of them as being "external" (in the sense that the material world is said to be external).Michael

    In what sense, then, are they external ?

    That's a false dichotomy. It's not a case of either a) mathematical realism is true or b) I am maths.Michael

    We don't need Platonism. That would be one of those claims that could be right or wrong. It suffices to see that math is normative, that a proof that is irrational is also a proof that all mathematicians as such ought to regard it as such, recognizing a fact about the real number system, independent of any metaphysical theory of something 'behind' this system.
  • Antinatalism Arguments
    Death is the ending of life, not a state.unenlightened

    I don't think it's such a bad metaphor. It's like the difference between a surgery without or without general anesthesia. Is it absurd to prefer the anesthesia ?
  • Please help me here....
    The external world, for us, is an inferential extrapolation from the repetition and commonality of experiences of everyday things. We have very good reason to think that it exists, but we only know what it is for our inferential imaginations, nothing beyond that.Janus

    I dispute that. Only normative rationality and shared premises could support such a bold claim, yet you make the existence of anything outside your dream a mere hypothesis. We might just as well say that we have very good reason to think @Janus is not an artificial intelligence, utterly incapable of the feeling and sensation it's been designed to prioritize. The 'inside' and the 'outside' are interdependent concepts.


    There is thus a polar opposition between mind and matter, an oppos-tion which is often brought out as follows. Material objects are situated in a common field, known as ‘space’, and what happens to one body in one part of space is mechanically connected with what happens to other bodies in other parts of space. But mental happenings occur in insulated fields, known as ‘minds’, and there is, apart maybe from telepathy, no direct causal connection between what happens in one mind and what happens in another. Only through the medium of the public physical world can the mind of one person make a difference to the mind of another. The mind is its own place and in his inner life each of us lives the life of a ghostly Robinson Crusoe. People can see, hear and jolt one another’s bodies, but they are irremediably blind and deaf to the workings of one another’s minds and inoperative upon them.

    What sort of knowledge can be secured of the workings of a mind? On the one side, according to the official theory, a person has direct knowledge of the best imaginable kind of the workings of his own mind. Mental states and processes are (or are normally) conscious states and processes, and the consciousness which irradiates them can engender no illusions and leaves the door open for no doubts. A person’s present thinkings, feelings and willings, his perceivings, rememberings and imaginings are intrinsically ‘phosphorescent’; their existence and their nature are inevitably betrayed to their owner. The inner life is a stream of consciousness of such a sort that it would be absurd to suggest that the mind whose life is that stream might be unaware of what is passing down it. ... Besides being currently supplied with these alleged immediate data of consciousness, a person is also generally supposed to be able to exercise from time to time a special kind of perception, namely inner perception, or introspection. He can take a (non optical) ‘look’ at what is passing in his mind. Not only can he view and scrutinize a flower through his sense of sight and listen to and discriminate the notes of a bell through his sense of hearing; he can also reflectively or introspectively watch, without any bodily organ of sense, the current episodes of his inner life. This self-observation is also commonly supposed to be immune from illusion, confusion or doubt. A mind’s reports of its own affairs have a certainty superior to the best that is possessed by its reports of matters in the physical world. Sense-perceptions can, but consciousness and introspection cannot, be mistaken or confused.

    On the other side, one person has no direct access of any sort to the events of the inner life of another. He cannot do better than make problematic inferences from the observed behaviour of the other person’s body to the states of mind which, by analogy from his own conduct, he supposes to be signalised by that behaviour. Direct access to the workings of a mind is the privilege of that mind itself; in default of such privileged access, the workings of one mind are inevitably occult to everyone else.

    For the supposed arguments from bodily movements similar to their own to mental workings similar to their own would lack any possibility of observational corroboration. Not unnaturally, therefore, an adherent of the official theory finds it difficult to resist this consequence of his premisses, that he has no good reason to believe that there do exist minds other than his own. Even if he prefers to believe that to other human bodies there are harnessed minds not unlike his own, he cannot claim to be able to discover their individual characteristics, or the particular things that they undergo and do. Absolute solitude is on this showing the ineluctable destiny of the soul. Only our bodies can meet.

    As a necessary corollary of this general scheme there is implicitly prescribed a special way of construing our ordinary concepts of mental powers and operations. The verbs, nouns and adjectives, with which in ordinary life we describe the wits, characters and higher-grade performances of the people with whom we have do, are required to be construed as signifying special episodes in their secret histories, or else as signifying tendencies for such episodes to occur. When someone is described as knowing, believing or guessing something, as hoping, dreading, intending or shirking something, as designing this or being amused at that, these verbs are supposed to denote the occurrence of specific modifications in his (to us) occult stream of consciousness. Only his own privileged access to this stream in direct awareness and introspection could provide authentic testimony that these mental-conduct verbs were correctly or incorrectly applied. The onlooker, be he teacher, critic, biographer or friend, can never assure himself that his comments have any vestige of truth. Yet it was just because we do in fact all know how to make such comments, make them with general correctness and correct them when they turn out to be confused or mistaken, that philosophers found it necessary to construct their theories of the nature and place of minds. Finding mental-conduct concepts being regularly and effectively used, they properly sought to fix their logical geography. But the logical geography officially recommended would entail that there could be no regular or effective use of these mental-conduct concepts in our descriptions of, and prescriptions for, other people's minds.
    ...
    It is an historical curiosity that it was not noticed that the entire argument was broken-backed. Theorists correctly assumed that any sane man could already recognise the differences between, say, rational and nonrational utterances or between purposive and automatic behaviour. Else there would have been nothing requiring to be salved from mechanism. Yet the explanation given presupposed that one person could in principle never recognise the difference between the rational and the irrational utterances issuing from other human bodies, since he could never get access to the postulated immaterial causes of some of their utterances. Save for the doubtful exception of himself, he could never tell the difference between a man and a Robot. It would have to be conceded, for example, that, for all that we can tell, the inner lives of persons who are classed as idiots or lunatics are as rational as those of anyone else. Perhaps only their overt behaviour is disappointing; that is to say, perhaps ‘idiots’ are not really idiotic, or ‘lunatics’ lunatic. Perhaps, too, some of those who are classed as sane are really idiots. According to the theory, external observers could never know how the overt behaviour of others is correlated with their mental powers and processes and so they could never know or even plausibly conjecture whether their applications of mental-conduct concepts to these other people were correct or incorrect. It would then be hazardous or impossible for a man to claim sanity or logical consistency even for himself, since he would be debarred from comparing his own performances with those of others.
    — Ryle