My question then is whether we ever utilize (B∧¬B) without conceiving of it as a kind of P. — Leontiskos
So do we have a proof for ((a→(b∧¬b)) → ¬a)? — Leontiskos
Leo seems to think that choosing between ρ→~μ and μ→~ρ somehow involves an act of will that is outside formal logic. He concludes that somehow reductio is invalid. His is a mistaken view. Either inference, ρ→~μ or μ→~ρ, is valid.
Indeed, the "problem" is not with reduction, but with and-elimination. And-elimination has this form
ρ^μ ⊢ρ, or ρ^μ ⊢μ. We can choose which inference to use, but both are quite valid.
We can write RAA as inferring an and-sentence, a conjunct:
ρ,μ ⊢φ^~φ⊢ (ρ→~μ) ^ (μ→~ρ)
and see that the choice is not in the reductio but in choosing between the conjuncts.
Leo is quite wrong to assert that Reductio Ad Absurdum is invalid. — Banno
I think the only way we can utilize logical inference is by using the modus tollens — Leontiskos
Does classical logic not presuppose that such substitution is truth-preserving? — Leontiskos
(B∧¬B) is ambiguous, and can be interpreted as p or as FALSE (i.e. always-false). — Leontiskos
Why did you reject (1) and not (2) or (3)? The reductio is not formally valid in that tight sense. — Leontiskos
What's wrong with Biden? — L'éléphant
Why is he being criticized so much? — L'éléphant
Aging is an issue for one of the most important jobs in the world and in Biden's case we're talking about dementia. He's a vegetable half of the time. — Benkei
some rules of classical logic to come into conflict — Leontiskos
-Any consequent which is false proves the antecedent
-(B∧¬B) is a consequent which is false
∴ (B∧¬B) proves the antecedent — Leontiskos
I don't think that is logically rigorous. As you say, it is not a term in classical logic, and for good reason.A→FALSE — Leontiskos
Another way to read the first argument, and the one I prefer*, is as follows:
A→ABSURD
∴ "A cannot be affirmed" — Leontiskos
I'd like to explore this idea next:
I think that "A does not imply B" can't even be put in terms of logic, because "A does not imply B" conveys no information.
— Lionino — Lionino
The antecedent of a negated material conditional is always true, and this goes back to my point in the edit you may have missed above. — Leontiskos
I think that "A does not imply B" can't even be put in terms of logic, because "A does not imply B" conveys no information. — Lionino
And in each of the invalid cases if "B" could be made necessarily false they would presumably hold. — Leontiskos
Does this support my claim that what is at stake is something other than a material conditional? The negation does not distribute to a material conditional in the way you are now distributing it. — Leontiskos
So I guess that, in order to say "A does not imply a contradiction", we would have to say instead (A→¬(B∧¬B)). From there things start to make more sense.
Since ¬(A→(B∧¬B)) does not translate to "A does not imply B and not-B". I have to fix my post above. — Lionino
From ~(A -> (B & ~B)) we infer that A implies no contradictions.
From (~A -> (B & ~B)) we infer that A implies no contradictions. — TonesInDeepFreeze
From there things start to make more sense. — Lionino
Kazantzakis once said that if he were awarded the Nobel Prize in Literature, he would only accept it if he could share it with Sikelianos. — javi2541997
embraced aspects of the Dark Enlightenment, a movement — frank
And yet now Catholics take the blood at Mass every week. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Ontological assumptions are what foundations are made of — Metaphysician Undercover
and Platonism provides the assumptions required for formalism, the idea of pure form. — Metaphysician Undercover
"If A implies B & ~B, then A implies a contradiction" is true, but it is a statement about the sentences, not a translation of them. — TonesInDeepFreeze
I'm not sure exactly what is "orthodox" here. — Count Timothy von Icarus
.In any case, the doctrine was formally condemned in the first of the famous anathemas pronounced at the Council of Constantinople in 543: Ei tis ten teratode apokatastasis presbeuei anathema esto [See, also, Justinian, Liber adversus Originem, anathemas 7 and 9.] The doctrine was thenceforth looked on as heterodox by the Church. — Catholic Encyclopaedia
Because the goal is deification and once deification has occured the will is not corruptible. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Catholic theologians dance around this issue quite often — Count Timothy von Icarus
SO I supose one question is, can such an argument be constructed? — Banno
So you don't accept that 7=7? — Wayfarer
My view is that numbers are real, but not physically existent. — Wayfarer
If you point to a number, '7', what you're indicating is a symbol, whereas the number itself is an intellectual act. — Wayfarer
And furthermore, it is an intellectual act which is the same for all who can count. — Wayfarer
Elvis is not a man – ¬A
Elvis is a man does not imply that Elvis is both mortal and immortal – ¬(A → (B and ¬B))
Therefore Elvis is a man – A
¬A, ¬(A → (B∧ ¬B)) entails A. That doesn't make sense — Lionino
So ¬(A → (B∧ ¬B)) is the same as (¬A) → (B∧ ¬B), which may be read as "Not-A implies a contradiction", it can't read as "A does not imply a contradiction". — Lionino
Elvis is not a man – ¬A
Elvis is not a man implies that Elvis is both mortal and immortal – ¬(A → (B and ¬B))
Therefore Elvis is a man – A
¬A, ¬(A → (B∧ ¬B)) entails A, from contradiction everything follows. — Lionino
Elvis is not a man – ¬A
Elvis is a man does not imply that Elvis is both mortal and immortal – (A → ¬(B and ¬B))
These two do not entail that Elvis is a man. — Lionino
¬◇(a → (b∧¬b)) entails □a — Lionino
I gather you worked through this? Nice. — Banno
For a religious conservative? Yes. — RogueAI
When I discovered the conditions under which infinite compositions of parabolic transformations converge to their fixed points that was a discovery based upon a creation. — jgill