You don't need a full history of the evidence I've been exposed to engage in this discussion, and the evidence (in the form of anthropological journals which you've requested) that I have presented should be sufficient (there are probably no academic studies which concisely capture the main thrust of my original post (that western civilization has been the opposite of a disaster)). I've gathered my understanding of human cultures over a long period of time and from many sources (such as history books and documentaries, which I reckon you would merely ridicule as undisciplined); I made a myriad of points in a cumulative argument, each of which I've been happy to provide evidence for, but providing all my original sources would be a herculean feat of memory. — VagabondSpectre
I haven't asked for a full list. I'm merely defending my statement that your opinion was largely uninformed (in the academic sense), and supported
post hoc with evidence you found by searching the internet in a concious attempt to support it. You seemed to take great offence at the suggestion, so I presumed it wasn't true. This would mean that your opinion was, in fact, supported by some academic information and that you searched the internet for new sources to support it for some reason other than your lack of previous sources. If you're now saying that that wasn't the case, then my first assertion, which you labelled ad hominem, was actually perfectly true. I'm not judging. I didn't at any point say "... and therefore your opinion is stupid and rubbish", just that it was reasonable of me to to not treat it's exposition as a learning experience.
I'm never going to be able to prove that there is a 0% chance I am wrong, or that no expert in a vast field of study hold conflicting views. However, the more rational merit I can give to my own positions, the less likely alternative theories seem to be. — VagabondSpectre
That's fine, showing that one theory has more rational merit than another is a reasonable way of comparing them (although I don't see any convincing ethical argument that we should then
adopt the argument which shows most rational merit, but that's another debate entirely), but contrary to your later suggestion that we cannot discuss these ideas in the midst of a bias-laden debate, I really don't see how we can even have a debate (bias-laden or otherwise) unless we resolve what it is we're using as a measure of rational merit. You seem to believe in the (I think very much mistaken) notion that the ability to provide counter-arguments is just such a measure, but the history of ideas demonstrates with glaring empirical accuracy, that the ability to derive counter-arguments is almost infinite, limited only by the imagination. So then we're left with this unsatisfactorily subjective notion of 'compelling' counter-arguments. You don't find my arguments 'compelling', I don't find yours 'compelling' so where do we go from there?
We're more than capable of forming and informing evidence based opinions, even if originally they may have started as anecdotal or evolutionary preconceptions. In the spirit of philosophy and debate I think it always best to try and confront evidence and arguments directly (unless they're obviously absurd). — VagabondSpectre
I agree entirely. The difference I'm trying to get at is that presenting your argument, together with the rational process and evidence by which you support it, is not sufficient on it's own to do anything more than offer someone an alternative (which they may then adopt or reject). If you want to go further, then this you'll need to do some comparative work. My criticism of your argument so far was mostly based on the fact that it is rarely more than a just-so story. It lays out how something
could be the case, not how something
must be the case, nor even how something is
more likely to be the case than any alternative. Giving you the benefit of the doubt, I presumed at first that this was intentional, and you were simply laying out an alternative for me to consider (which I why I said that I wasn't interested in reading an alternative presented by someone who was largely uniformed, when I could read alternatives presented by experts). Now that you've made it clear that you're not simply laying out an alternative, but are attempting to argue it's relative merits, I'm focussing my criticism more on the fact that I don't see any such
comparative arguments there.
My second post attempts to draw out where I expected to see some comparative arguments.
The most important point you're missing, which covers the first three of your responses, is a simple mathematical one. You're treating survival as a binomial factor when it is in fact variable. Hunter-gatherer tribes do not fail to survive (where modern societies achieve survival). Hunter-gatherers survive for
less long than modern people's on average. This treatment of a variable as a binomial causes all sorts of problems for your argument...
If life is worth living, and I'm saying that it usually is to most people, then survival is intrinsically important as necessary to preserve the value life contains. — VagabondSpectre
So here, 'survival', is not a binomial factor (one you either have or do not have), it is a variable (one you have a certain quantity of). The decision we're talking about is trading a certain quantity of this variable for an increase in the variable 'happiness', yet this argument here treats it as if the only choice were to either have 'survival' or not have it. Treat it as a variable and your last assertion "survival is intrinsically important as necessary to preserve the value life contains" ceases to be true. Only when the 'survival' variable is zero does the 'value life contains' variable become impossible to obtain. At all other values for the 'survival' variable, it is still possible to obtain any amount of the 'value life contains' variable depending entirely on how 'valuable' each moment of that life is.
...(the point is to get repeated doses, which requires you to go on living). I'm not saying that mortality rates are the one true and ultimate measure of societal success, but they are a necessary and major part of any broad and comprehensive assessment of societal success. — VagabondSpectre
Again, same error. It does require you to "go on living" to get repeated doses of happiness, and lack of mortality is definitely necessary for a society to be successful. But both modern societies and hunter-gatherer societies have that. Hunter-gatherers do not instantly drop dead the moment they're born, so both possess this necessary quality 'being alive for some time'. The variable is the
amount of time. The point I'm making with the sky-divers is that statistically they will be (as a population) reducing the amount of time they spend alive (sky-divers have a shorter lifespan on average than non-sky-divers). They trade this shortened average lifespan for the adrenaline rush their sport gives them. This is also true of absolutely any of the risks we take in life. We trade the shortened average lifespan of a group taking that risk for the benefits that risk gives us. This is no different to the argument I'm making about hunter-gatherers who choose to remain so. They're trading a shortened average lifespan for the benefits their lifestyle gives them.
If a given society is rife with such boons, then being alive longer within them would indeed be valuable/sucecssful — VagabondSpectre
Here, bizarrely, you've basically undermined your own argument and replaced it entirely with the one I'm trying to lay out. "
If a given society is rife with such boons,
then being alive longer within them would indeed be valuable/successful". Do you see... The variable 'being alive longer' is only of value
if a given society is 'rife with such boons'. If a given society is not 'rife with such boons' then the variable 'being alive longer' is not worth anything. So why are you suggesting we judge the worth of a society in any way on the variable 'being alive longer' when we've just established that such a variable is only worth anything
if such a society is 'rife with such boons'? The first job is to establish whether a society is rife with boons, before we've done that the variable 'being alive longer' is of no use to us as a metric, as you just stated.
It doesn't exactly matter that some societies offer better odds of leading successful lives: statistically, if you have a higher chance of dying, you have a lower chance of leading a successful life, whatever that may entail. — VagabondSpectre
No, you've completely ignored the maths. You do not automatically have a lower chance of leading a successful life if you have a higher chance of dying. That's not the way probability works. With two variables the one is multiplied by the other. If you live in a society with an extremely low chance of achieving happiness, it doesn't matter how long you live for (presuming infinity is not an option), because your chances of happiness are so low that getting to roll those dice more often is not sufficient compensation. Imagine I have a ten-sided-die and a hundred-sided die, and my aim is to roll a one as often as I can (the size of the die represents how easy it is to achieve happiness in a given society, rolling a one represents happiness being achieved, the number of times you can roll a die represents your lifespan). I need to roll the hundred-sided die ten times more to have an equal chance of obtaining a one, than if I roll the ten sided die. So if someone said to me, would you be prepared to trade a loss in the number of times you get to roll the die for an opportunity to swap dice, you would be best taking that option.
This is what I'm suggesting makes hunter-gatherer societies compare favourably to Western ones despite their lower life expectancies. This is why sky-divers accept a lower life expectancy on average than non-sky-divers. This is why anyone does anything remotely risky.
People are, and always have been, prepared to trade a loss in expected lifespan for an increase in the happiness of that lifespan.
By necessarily and exhaustively you seem to be supposing that an individual metric ought to occupy a universal and immovable place in a hierarchy of values that all humans agree with. I cannot tell you the exact point at which security becomes a greater concern than freedom, or precisely chart the many factors which influence individual human happiness. — VagabondSpectre
And yet that's exactly what you're doing because you're presenting the fact that Western societies have a higher life expectancy as a metric which is sufficient to outweigh any advantages hunter-gather societies may have in diet, child-rearing, equality, community, exercise, purpose, freedom etc. You have decided the place life expectancy has in the hierarchy of values.
It's more misleading as ametric for societal happiness because as I understand it suicide often is the result of clinical depression, an affliction not necessarily caused by society itself. I've put forward and supported many good metrics, but I don't exactly feel the need to show why all other possible metrics, including suicide, are more misleading. Hell, maybe suicide is actually the closest proxy for societal happiness that we have, as you say it is, but until I get ahold of some reasons as to why this is the case (as opposed to not the case), I have no reason to assume its merit. — VagabondSpectre
This seems to go back to the 'laying out an alternative' approach rather than any comparative work. I'm not asking you to assume the merit of suicide as a metric. As far as I'm concerned you can take it or leave it, but it was my understanding that you wanted to engage in arguing the
relative merits of your theory, which would make it necessary for you to show how your metric compared
relative to mine, how it improves on mine. So if we're talking about the property of a metric's clarity (it's failure to mislead), then a
comparative argument would show how your metrics had less tendency to mislead than mine. Without that you're just back to saying that you have a reasonable theory and I already don't deny that.
I have to keep pointing out that inductive arguments which establish conclusions as likely rather than deductively necessary can be just as philosophical (better in fact). — VagabondSpectre
No you don't because I have at no point denied that is the case. I haven't at any point claimed that you do not have a valid philosophical theory. We're not arguing about validity, we're arguing about relative merit. Why are your conclusions
more likely than mine?
Are you essentially suggesting that we would be equally happy if we were all forced to do the same job? — VagabondSpectre
Yes. So long as the 'force' you mention is simply the force of naturally occurring circumstances and not some dictatorial government, then that is exactly what I'm saying. Your job does not determine who you are, two bakers could be more diverse in personality and approach to life than a bank clerk and a soldier who might approach their respective jobs with exactly the same world-view. What matters is your personal identity, not what you do for a living.
Being alive is definitely required to be mentally and spiritually healthy, therefore low mortality rates improves your odds of being mentally and spiritually healthy. It's not a presumption... — VagabondSpectre
Back to this again...I refer you to the discussion on how probability works above. 'Being alive' is not a binomial value in this. Hunter-gathers achieve 'being alive', western societies achieve 'being alive'. The binomial value 'being alive' does not vary across the societies we're comparing as both have it. What varies is the variable value 'length of being alive', and 'length of being alive' is not directly correlated with mental and spiritual well-being as our population of sky-divers, soldiers and all other risk takers proves.
Again, I'm not going to take your comments on evolution individually. Suffice to say they conform to the same approach. You've given me a perfectly cogent argument as to why genetic factors determining what makes us happy might have evolved more quickly than, say, dietary requirements. Once again proving that you have a perfectly logical and reasonable argument. But you have not done any comparative work. Is it
more likely that our genetic predisposition to causes of happiness has evolved quickly to take account of modern life? Because if not, then we simply have two equally valid alternatives.
From an evolutionary perspective, those who suffered too much due to their physiology/psychology will have tended to reproduce less, but it would also be true that evolving to be completely satisfied would also cause you to reproduce less successfully. Having insatiable desires keeps us motivated. — VagabondSpectre
Absolutely, but this is no less true of a modern society. If we satisfy all our desires easily, we will have nothing to strive for and will ultimately feel less satisfied in the long run.
---
To sum up. You're arguing that mortality rates are a good metric because you need to be alive to enjoy anything else life has to offer, but this mistakes a variable for a binomial value. Both hunter-gatherer tribes and modern societies achieve the binomial value 'being alive'. Mortality rates are a measure of the variable value 'length of being alive', and again, both societies have a positive value in this measure. It is clearly, and I think fairly irrefutably, not the case, that a particular value of this variable is a contingent necessity for enjoying life, (one could potentially really enjoy a single year, or fail to enjoy a hundred years) so your arguments about necessity are irrelevant.
What is relevant is the trade and this requires us to measure
how valuable each year of additional life in modern society is, and
at what cost those additional years are purchased. My use of the shockingly high suicide rates in modern societies means to show that the value of each additional year is really not that high. Dozens of additional years are routinely thrown away to avoid misery. My example of sky-divers and other risk takers further reinforces this. Again, many potential additional years are thrown away for what seems like the most trivial of benefits. We really do not value additional years that highly.
What we do seem to value highly is happiness, the tiniest potential increases are pursued doggedly; advertising companies, peers and our own desires get us to do all sorts of risky behaviours for the most trivial, ephemeral and often completely illusionary gains in happiness.