I don't agree with them, but that is just a personal preference of mine. — Lionino
All this, I take as evidence that we do not know what "life" is. We seem to believe that there is something called "life", (and it's sort of odd that we name it as a thing, harkening back to "the soul"), but we really do not understand what it means to be alive.
Kant agreed that all our knowledge begins with experience, but he disagreed with Hume's conclusion that it therefore arises solely from experience. Kant introduced a critical distinction between the forms of intuition (space and time) and the categories of understanding (including but not limited to causation), which are necessary for us to interpret sensory information.
According to Kant, these categories are not derived from experience but rather are the preconditions that make experience intelligible in the first place. They are the innate structures of the mind that organize sensory data into coherent perceptions ('percepts'). For example, when we perceive one event following another, our understanding interprets this as causation, allowing us to see one event as causing the other, rather than just as two events occurring sequentially. Thus, Kant argued that Hume's reduction of knowledge to mere sensations and perceptions overlooks the active role of the mind's inherent structures, which underpin experience. — Wayfarer
I would think that since having these categories is actually having a form of knowledge, then we cannot truthfully say "Kant agreed that all our knowledge begins with experience". There is a bit of inconsistency here, whereby it is necessary to either break knowledge into two types, a priori and a posteriori (such as innate and learned), or else we need to provide different principles for understanding the a priori as something other than knowledge.
The latter, which appears to be the direction you've taken, is a very strenuous task. This course of explanation drives toward the resolution of Plato's "knowledge is recollection" problem. Without a proper separation between the potential for a specific form of knowledge, and actually holding that knowledge, the two become one and the same, with something separating them. So as Plato demonstrates, learning is nothing other than recollection. That produces the problem of infinite regress, and the conclusion that all knowledge has eternal existence.
Aristotle offered a resolution by portraying this as two distinct layers of potentiality. Kant's a priori can be understood as the capacity, or potential for learning. This potentiality underlies all a posteriori, or empirical knowledge, which is describe by Aristotle as the capacity, or potential to act. Notice the two distinct levels of potentialities. Knowledge proper, is the potential to act in a specific way. But in order to act in a specific way, we must first learn how to act in that way. Below this though, supporting it as a foundation, is the capacity, or potential to learn, which is a necessary requirement to learning. This, the lower level capacity to learn, appears to have all the characteristics of being a form of knowledge itself. Learning is a type of acting, so the capacity to learn is itself a capacity to act.
What separates these two forms of potential (two types of knowledge) is a form of activity. That type of activity is described by Aquinas as the creation of habits. This is how the one type of potential, the capacity to learn, becomes the other type of potential, as the capacity to act in a specific learned way. The former "capacity to learn" is the more general, and the latter is to focus the general potential in a more specific way. The importance of habits in the shaping and forming of living beings through evolution is what Lamarck focused on in his evolutionary speculations.
The first point is that what is significant to you, what is important to you, conditions your desires. We all have first order desires for pleasure, satisfaction, gratification, stimulation and so on. But in case those desires lead to habits that are unhealthy, they may be countermanded by stronger concerns like personal health, social harmony, or even simply by introjected moral prescriptions and proscriptions. — Janus
This seems to support my claim rather than yours. Since you name a multitude of types of desires, and the human being must prioritize one over the other in many situations, this seems to support what I said, that we can choose what we want. Please note, that having a general inclination in some way, is not the same as having a want. The want is for something specific an "object". So for example, I may have an emptiness in my stomach producing a general uneasy anxious feeling called "hunger", but this is completely different from the "want" of "I want a hamburger".
The second point is that what you desire in the first order sense; food, warmth, shelter, sex, and so on simply is what it is. — Janus
Notice, that all these so-called "desires" manifest simply as general uncomfortable, or even painful feelings. You only call them "desires" because you assume that there is an object involved. A desire is for something specific, this is the end, or object. The objects of all your mentioned desires, "food, warmth, shelter, sex," are very general. These generalities do not serve as objects at all, in reality. You just mention them as if they do, because it makes your argument. In reality, the desire is for a specific object, and since the person has the choice between many different objects, you can use the general terms, ""food, warmth, shelter, sex,".
Suppose for example, that you have the general feeling which we know as "hunger". This you seem to describe as "the desire for food". Hunger is clearly not the desire for food. It is a feeling within your body having an effect on your mind. The effect is not the general "desire for food", it is the desire to eat something. Then that desire to eat something is turned more specific by the conscious mind, toward the desire to eat a specific thing. The saying, "the desire for food" is simply a feature of the mode of description. Since we observe that the desire to eat something may be satisfied by many different food substances, we can simply call it "the desire for food". However, when hunger, the desire to eat something, actually manifests in the particular circumstances that it does, there is the opportunity for the hungry person to choose from many different food items, so that the feeling of hunger transforms to the want for a specific item, without ever actually being "the desire for food". That generalization is just the way that we describe the reality that the hungry person, the person with that feeling, has the freedom of choice to choose whatever object that one wants, to eat.
The third point is that each person's capacities just are that person's capacities—some are more capable than others at overcoming their compulsions or addictions. Some people simply don't and cannot, feel empathy, for example—they cannot force themselves to care for others, although is they are smart, they may at least be able to bring themselves to act as though they do. — Janus
This is simply a copout, the position of a determinist, fatalist, defeatist. As described in my reply to wayfarer above, a person's capacities are multilayered. And, through habit forming we are very able to shape and direct our capacities. This is because they are based in the most general, yet are actualized in the most particular, as in my description of hunger above. Because there are layers, and the opportunity of choice at each layer, and what is formed at the higher level is a further capacity, we very clearly have the ability to shape and form our own capacities. This for example is what we do when we grow up from childhood to being an adult, we shape our capacities in the directions that we choose, and eventually take on a career. And this ability to shape our capacities continues through our lives.