1. ¬(PvQ) ∴ (¬P∧¬Q) 2. assume: ¬(¬P∧¬Q) 3. | assume: P 4. | | PvQ (3, add.) 5. | ∴ ¬P (3; 1 contradicts 4) 6. | assume: Q 7. | | QvP 8. | ∴ ¬Q (6; 1 contradicts 7) 9. | ¬P∧¬Q (5,8, conj.) 10. ∴ ¬P∧¬Q (2; 2 contradicts 9)
1) ¬(P∧Q) ∴ ¬P∨¬Q 2) assume: ¬(¬P∨¬Q) 3) | assume: ¬P 4) | | ¬P∨¬Q (add.) 5) | ∴ P (de 3; 2 contradicts 4) 6) | assume: ¬Q 7) | | ¬Q∨¬P 8) | ∴ Q (de 6; 2 contradicts 7) 9) | ∴ P∧Q (5,8, conj.) 10) ∴ ¬P∨¬Q (3; 1 contradicts 9)
Correct--we can derive "It is not the case that some A is not B" from "All A is B." However, we still cannot derive "Some A is B" from either of these without the additional premise, "Some A is A." — aletheist
It's a negative existential one, but any universal proposition can be transformed into an existential one."No Greek is man" is just to say that it is not the case that some Greek exists and is a man. That's an existential quantifier, not a universal one. — MindForged
Based on this one either can't claim to know almost anything or else you have to change our understanding of biology and what creatures exist on Earth in order to credibly say we don't know them to not exist. — MindForged
"All Greeks are man" is a universal statement, while "No Greek are men" is a particular. One is about an abstract domain not involving existence while the other is explicitly about existence. — MindForged
Honestly, how do you know that winged horses are non-existent? I'm noy saying that they exists or that I believe that they exist, but you can't affirm that categorically only based on "no winged horse has ever been seen".It's false because we know it's true that winged horses are non-existent — MindForged
Yeah, I read it and i was kinda doubtful too. For me it doesn't make any sense.It might help to also consider that Russell would also interpet "All winged horses are wingless" to be true. Since nothing is in the set "winged horses". — Ben92
The problem is that it is invalid to cross predicates in this way. A is B is to predicate B of the subject A. A is C is to predicate C of the subject A. B and C are predicates of the subject A. Until we convert either B or C into a subject, and predicate something of that subject, we have nothing to allow us to draw any conclusions about either B or C, because B and C have not been presented as subjects. — Metaphysician Undercover
No, that is invalid. It becomes more obvious if we reformulate the two propositions as follows.
For all x, if x is B, then x is C.
There exists an x, such that x is B and x is C.
The first proposition clearly does not entail the second. — aletheist
And I don't see how Russell would consider "All winged horses are wingless" to be trivially true. His description theory of names doesn't say sentence with empty terms are by default true, especially contradictory ones. They are deemed false in his theory because they must posit the existence of some thing (winged horses) but we know the thing to not exist. Nothing satisfies the condition "winged horse" so the translation of the previous argument into classical logic would have a suppressed premise, namely:
There exists at least one winged horse.
Which gets the value false, leading to a false conclusion. Have I misunderstood you or perhaps Russell's theory? — MindForged
"If it happened that there were no Greeks, both the proposition that "All Greeks are man" and the proposition that "No Greeks are men" would be true. The proposition "No Greeks are man" is, of course, the proposition "All Greeks are not-man". Both propositions will be true simultaneously if it happens that there are no Greeks. All statements about all the members of a class that has no members are true, because the contradictory of any general statement does assert existence and is therefore false in this case. This notion, of course, of general propositions not involving existence is one which is not in the tradictional doctrine of the syllogism." — Russell
Because empty terms show this argument form to fail — MindForged
All winged horses are horses,
All winged horses have wings,
Therefore some horses have wings.
Clearly the first two premises are true but the conclusion is clearly false, we know there are no horses with wings. — MindForged
Why? Of course, you would need to know if an atom in a far away galaxy would impact on your actions, but you don't need everything that is happening with this and other atoms, you only need to know whether they'll change your actions.Basically we need to be omniscient
In this exemple, both P and ¬P implies in Q, which mean that anything implies in Q. This is equivalent to (P^¬P) ⊃ Q, which is always true. But this is not the case, because if A if true, it's conclusion isn't the same as it would be if A was false. If you choose values for a variable, you will only know what would be the result of that if this were to be really the truth value, but you don't know what it is.P ⊃ Q
¬P ⊃ Q
∴ Q