Comments

  • Time is a Byproduct of Consciousness - Consciousness is Universes Fundamental Dimension
    That, without consciousness, we would not be aware of time passing, is a very different thing to time being brought about by consciousness.

    There seems to be an error along these lines going on in this thread. It's a very common, popular misunderstanding.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    Thanks for the clear response, Ludwig

    Forgive my ignorance. That suggests that you have an independent definition of "extensional context". But I thought that intersubstitutability was the definition of an extensional context. ?Ludwig V

    No, that's right, this is the circularity I mentioned. It's an extensional context if substitution works. Being extensional and allowing substitution that preserves truth are the same thing. We are either in an extensional context, or not.

    Are you possibly confusing "All the propositions that we think we know about tigers are false" with "Each of the propositions that we think we know about tigers may be false"?Ludwig V
    I don't believe so. The idea is that we learn what some thing is, name it, and then discover that everything we knew about it was false.

    I couldn't locate the original Thales example - I think it was Kaplan - so I had ChatGPT reconstructed something similar:

    Consider the historical figure Thales of Miletus. Tradition holds that he was the first philosopher, perhaps the first to suggest that water is the fundamental substance of all things. Yet, on closer inspection, our supposed knowledge of Thales collapses into uncertainty. Were these views really his? Were the anecdotes true? Or are they accretions of later doxography and myth-making?

    As historical scrutiny deepens, it becomes clear that we know almost nothing about Thales with certainty. Yet this very realization—that we know nothing about him—is itself a fact about Thales. It is not a fact about someone else or a mythological construct; it concerns the very individual to whom the name "Thales" refers.

    Therefore, paradoxically, our ignorance becomes a form of reference. The name "Thales" successfully picks out an individual in history, even though our beliefs about him may be largely mistaken or minimal. This supports the view that the name refers rigidly and directly, independent of any particular descriptive content we might associate with it. The denotation succeeds not despite our ignorance but is revealed in it.
    — ChatGPT

    What this shows is that we don't manage to pick out Thales in virtue of what we know about Thales, a somewhat counterintuitive result. There's a bunch of such examples, from Kripke, Donnellan, Kaplan and others, that have pretty much undermined the so-called "descriptivist" account. The suggested replacement - the "causal" account - has about twice as many adherents on the PhilPapers survey, despite not being all that well articulated.

    What this doesn't rule out is the sort of view that might be seen in a Wittgensteinian account, in which reference is an aspect of the more general language games in which we participate, or even a sub-game within those games. On such a view a reference may be counted as successful if we get on with what we are doing, regardless of how it managed to denote it's target. I think Malcolm's concerns were misplaced (@Richard B)

    So now I'm wondering how reference is achieved.Ludwig V
    Good question. To my eye, it's clear that we sometimes do work out a reference from a description associated with it; it's just that we can show that this is not what happens in every case. Indeed, it should hardly be a surprise to learn that there is more than one way for a reference to succeed.

    And even less reason to suppose that references are dependent on some sort of essence.

    I've my own ideas about how to explain reference and such, (@J), but we might move on without a general theory of reference, if we agree that somehow it manages to work despite our not understanding quite how.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    I'm not too keen on talk of essences, either. Whatever they are, they are peripheral to the issue of what is real and what isn't.

    We have three or four differing views of the nature of essences here.

    There's the older view in which to understand what something is just is to understand it's essence. That's perhaps what Tim is thinking here. On that account, being real and having an essence are pretty much the same thing.

    There's the more recent analytic natural language view, from the later Wittgenstein through Malcolm and maybe @Richard B, and close to that taken more formally by Quine and friends, that there's not much more to essences than confusion.

    Then there's Kripke's suggestion, that if we must think of essences we can think of them as the properties had by something in every possible world in which that thing exists. This has the benefit of being formalisable and reasonably clear while keeping to a minimum any metaphysical consequences.

    Then you may be suggesting that we can be rid of essences by doing some sort of Bayesian analysis that allows us to conclude that tigers are real. Maybe.

    But you and I might agree that essences have little to do with what is and isn't real.
  • Knowledge is just true information. Isn't it? (Time to let go of the old problematic definition)
    Knowing how to use a faucet is not the same thing as knowing that any particular faucet is working...Count Timothy von Icarus

    Sure.

    The point made is that in order to be said to know something, it's not usually enough to have the information; one also should be able to act on that information.

    That seems to have little to do with being able to carry on a ritual without having faith in the accompanying theology.

    So what do we conclude?

    I don’t really care about what it means to know how to do something. At least not in the context of philosophy.T Clark
    A shame. Fine.
  • Knowledge is just true information. Isn't it? (Time to let go of the old problematic definition)
    If you had someone who could set out, to whatever degree of detail you like, what is involved in riding a bike, and yet fell off every time they tried to ride, would you say that they know how to ride a bike?

    They have all the information.

    But they can't do it.

    Hence knowledge is more than information.
  • Knowledge is just true information. Isn't it? (Time to let go of the old problematic definition)
    When I get involved in a discussion such as this one, I usually make it explicitly clear the kind of knowledge I'm talking about - specifically excluding knowing how to do something.T Clark

    Yep. Not an uncommon move. Is it justified? Is there a difference in kind here? You know that there is water in the tap. You can show that you know this by saying "There is water in the tap", or by going and getting a glass of water. Going and getting a glass of of water is something you do. But so is saying "There is water in the tap".

    Indeed, if we came across someone who said "I know that there is water in the tap", but became confused when asked to locate and turn the tap on in order to obtain a glass of water, we might well conclude that they said they knew but really didn't.

    There seems to be a pretty good argument that "knowing that" is a type of "knowing how".

    I'm not convinced that you can neatly slice knowing how from knowing that.

    What do you say?
  • Magma Energy forever!
    Was it @counterpunch, 4 years ago, who had a thing about this? I might have the wrong bloke.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    Yep. Notice that reference remains intact despite the failure of each description. Hence reference is not achieved by using descriptions, nor by essences.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    It's a poor example that Kripke chose, and a somewhat difficult idea to get across, but the point Kripke makes is at least in part quite right, if misunderstood.

    You may be familiar with the theory that a name refers in virtue of an associated description, and the various arguments mounted against it after the advent of Kripke's semantics. It was found to be inadequate in certain regards, and few still adherence to it.

    What Kripke is doing is pointing out that this applies to types as well as to individuals. It's a hypothetical, in line with the familiar Thales example and others. If we did find out that everything we knew about tigers were mistaken or in error, that would nevertheless be a discovery about tigers. It follows that "tiger" does not refer to tigers in virtue of some description that sets out their characteristics.

    In the hypothetical, we had "established" what a tiger was on the basis of an "agree on definition and judgment as it is applied to our natural surroundings" that was, in the hypothetical, wrong. And yet we nevertheless still manage to pick out what is a tiger and what isn't. It follows that we do not pick out what is a tiger and what isn't, on the basis of supposed essential characteristics of tigers.

    The upshot is agreement - we indeed do not identify tigers on the basis of some essence that exists in all possible worlds.

    The argument is on p.120 of N&N, for those reading along.
  • Australian politics
    Secret figures show Liberal party’s ageing membership in freefall in NSW and Victoria

    Average age of 68.

    “One of the biggest expenses we used to have [at our local branch] was on funeral wreaths.”
  • Knowledge is just true information. Isn't it? (Time to let go of the old problematic definition)
    If I've understood, knows things he doesn't believe, while knows things that are not true.

    And neither account can explain what it is to know how to ride a bike.

    :grimace:
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    I didn't actually respond to your post.
    What exactly is Kripke's value in calling them identity statements?Richard B
    It's not just Kripke, and it's about substitution.

    In set theory, the Axiom of Extensionality is



    Given two sets A and B, if they have the same elements then they are the same set. Now one way to treat this is as a definition of "=". It's also the definition of extensionality.

    If we are instead talking about functions,


    and for predicates


    and in arithmetic


    That is, x=y if they denote the same number.

    Or generally,

    In an extensional context, a=b iff for any string, substituting a for b does not change the value of that string.

    Now in physics, extensional equivalence might best be thought of as when two sides of an equation are measured in different ways but always yield the same values in every case where the law holds, and the equation is not a definition, but an empirical or theoretical identification.

    and are definitions, so the extensionality is built in. But in Ohm’s Law, , the two sides of the "=" are measured in quite different ways, and yet their value is the same. Much the same for . What's suggested is that can be substituted for , for , and for .

    There's a catch here, since the circumstances in which the substitution occurs must be carefully controlled. And indeed there is a benign circularity in that extensionality is defined in terms of substitution, and yet substitution is not permitted in cases that are extensional opaque.

    If your "⇔" is understood as, in the appropriate circumstances, permitting the stuff on the left to be substituted for the stuff on the right, then it is extensional and does much the same job as "=".

    The identity here isn't metaphysical; it's just substitution.

    And that's pretty much Kripke's point. If a=b, then you can substitute a for b and get the very same result, provided that you are working in areas where extensionality works.

    So if we discover that this lectern is made of wood, then in every possible world in which this lectern exists, it is made of wood. And if in some possible world the lectern before us is made of plastic, then it is a different lectern.

    And if we discover that water is H₂O, then ☐(water=H₂O). And so on through the many different examples. Notice how each of these is a hypothetical – an "if... then...", in which the antecedent is found a posteriori - by looking around. But all that is being done here is ensuring that we keep our language consistent. Once we fix reference by accepting the antecedent, we are obligated to respect the modal consequences of that act of naming as expressed by the consequent.

    Going back to the "heat is average energy of the molecules" example, Kripke fell over because heat is a sensation, and fails the test of being extensional. But temperature is extensional. That's why changing from heat to temperature works. And that also why his examples of pain and c-fibres are problematic - pain is not extensional.

    So much of Malcom's - and your - criticism is valid. But Kripke wasn't entirely wrong, either.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    If the whole ambit of philosophy is human experience and judgement then is it not always a matter of "what can (coherently and consistently) be said?Janus
    What can be said is a start. What can be shown might be more important. That's part of what is problematic about mysticism. If it is showing stuff rather than saying stuff, it's not actually false. But when it says stuff, it is almost invariably false.

    So, the Op question reframed would be not "how do we know what is real?" but "how do we decide what counts as real?"Janus
    I still prefer "How do we use the word real?"
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    I am sir.Moliere
    Good to know.

    I am sure our paths shall cross again about this topic.Richard B
    Sure. I still haven't responded to the points you made in your previous. Will do so later.


    Perhaps. But at the very least philosophical theories ought be internally consistent, so there is a point to the process of working out what that looks like. If it doesn't matter what can be said then anything goes.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    Interesting and stimulating, it has put my mind in such a state of agitation.Richard B
    I'm sorry for the agitation. I hope I can show you that there is no need for such disquiet, and at the same time take us back to the theme of this thread. I want to assure you that I agree with you that Malcolm has the better handle on language as a whole, and that Kripke has taken steps too far in applying his logic. I think we can be fairly precise as to where and how, and bring this back to the discussion of what is real and what is not real.

    We started to talk about essences because some folk here suppose that in some way it is the essence of a thing that decides if it is real or not; or perhaps the other way around. It has been difficult to obtain a clear explanation of how we are to fill this all out.

    Now the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus may well have had a view along these lines, since we can read amongst the changes between that work and the Investigations a change in Wittgenstein's approach to both logic and to essence. For the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus - and here I must ride rough-shod over the detail - the essence of a thing is implicit in the logical form that sets out the nature of that thing. This reflects a kind of logical essentialism: the structure of reality (and language) is essential and necessary, and it defines the limits of meaningful discourse.

    But by the Investigations, much of this had become unacceptable. The assumptions that had held this view firm were rejected. Where in the Tractatus each meaningful term had a strict definition, in the Investigations we were admonished to look instead at what we are doing with words and see that this vast variety of uses can and must not be understood in such a simple and fixed fashion. Doing so greatly misunderstands and misrepresents the variety of language. The notion of a family resemblance is important here, but is not alone.

    At around the same time, Quine was proffering another influential critique of essences, one more within the constraints of formal logic. Quine's argument shows that when someone uses a name - "gavagai" there may be no fact of the matter as to what that might be referring to. There are two aspects of this, the first that it need not be necessary to fix the referent perfectly in order to get your rabbit stew. The second, that no statement is true or false only as it stands, but that they are true or false as a part of the whole web of belief. Extensionally, to supose "gavagai" refers to the same thing as "rabbit" is to suppose that each element of the set "rabbit" is an element of the set "gavagai" - that's setting out what it would be for "gavaga" to mean "rabbit" in a way that does not rely on the intentionality of speaker meaning or web of belief. But that some individual is a member of the set "gavagai" or "rabbit" is of course open to referential opacity. If reference wasn't fixed, so much the worse for essence.

    Historically, these and other considerations led to a pretty widespread consensus in around the 1950's that essences were a bit useless, an anachronistic hangover form Medieval logic with which we could safely do without.

    The spurning of modality had much to do with the great success of predicate calculus and other advances in formal logic after Russell that seemed to have left the formalisation of modality behind. This changed dramatically when a kid from Nebraska showed how to construct a semantics and demonstrate completeness for S5.

    At the centre of this formalisation is a simple idea, restored from Leibniz. Modal language is pretty every-day. It comes about when we consider how things might have ben different - what if that table had been in the other room, or had been red instead of blue. In using such language we are asking about how the world would be if things had been a bit different - perhaps if the table were in the other room, the young people could play their board game on the table in there while we old folk dance in here... or whatever - we have interesting parties. The suggested way to understand such utterances is wondering what would be different in a world in which the table were in the other room. That's all a possible world is - a way of giving a firmness to such utterances by stipulating a difference and inferring the consequences.

    The formal version gets a bit complex, of course, but that's the basic idea. The formal stuff is what gave the idea respectability - here we had a way of using modal talk that we could be assured was coherent and complete, and that for many was intuitively familiar.

    And along with this comes a way of thinking about essences that shares in this coherence and completeness. Essence could be considered as being those properties that belong to a thing in every possible world in which that thing exists. Or, if you prefer, the properties without which we'd be talking about something else.

    It's worth paying some attention to how this works. A typical example is that Nixon was necessarily Human, and so that in every possible world in which Nixon exists, Nixon is human. Now it remains that perhaps the Nixon who was impeached might have been an alien. In that case, we are not talking about Nixon, but some alien who has replaced Nixon. Our Nixon is necessarily human.

    The point Id like you to see here is that the specification that Nixon is necessarily human is not a restriction on Nixon so much as a restriction on how we can make use of the word "Nixon". We might use the word "Nixon" to refer to something other than Nixon - to the alien. But doing so does not make Nixon an alien.

    Notice here the shifting of the burden from ontology to language. That's really quite important. Kripke can be understood as sneaking metaphysics in in the guise of logic. And at time he does appear to be guilty of this sin. But there is also a way of treating possible worlds as setting out for us a way to talk coherently about modal problems, without, or at least with minimal, metaphysical implications.

    Following this path, we treat possible worlds not as metaphysical entities but as stipulated language games within which we can evaluate the truth of particular propositions, of how things might otherwise have been. And essential properties are not discovered, nor the attributes of Platonic Forms, but are decided by virtue of keeping our language consistent. They are a thing we do together with words.

    There's a lot more that can be said here, but I have to go do other things, an there is enough here for now. The Law of Diminishing Returns applies, too. Is any one reading this?
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    So we agree that the second response seems inadequate*? Cool.

    Making a deduction is a process, something we do, rather than something sitting passively waiting to be noticed. This goes for rationality in general, as can be seen by the presence of irrationality. If we had no choice but to be rational, there wouldn't be so much fuss about being irrational. Adding six and seven and realising that doing so gives the same value as adding nothing to 13 is not quiescence.

    This leads to another point relating to mathematics. Making a calculation requires effort. Performing a deduction makes explicit what was previously hidden. And physically, doing this require work - energy over time.

    There's also the interesting fact that not all Hamiltonian path problems have an answer. That is, some of them are not equal to any value. It’s not accurate to say that “the input is the same thing as its output” in a Hamiltonian path problem when there is no path. The input does not implicitly contain a path if there isn’t a path. The input is not the same thing as the output.


    *added: Is that your opinion? There is no explicit conclusion in your post.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    , Leon


    Much as I dislike the present infection of Aristotelian thinking, I have to agree with this:
    A very recent book aiming at summarizing the philosophers’s doctrines concludes the chapter on Aristotle’s physics with the words: “We can say that nothing of Aristotle’s vision of the cosmos has remained valid.” From a modern physicist’s perspective, I’d say the opposite is true: “Virtually everything of Aristotle’s theory of motion is still valid”. It is valid in the same sense in which Newton’s theory is still valid: it is correct in its domain of validity, profoundly innovative, immensely influential and has introduced structures of thinking on which we are still building. — Carlo Rovelli, Aristotle’s Physics: a Physicist’s Look

    Does this roughly correspond to your point, Moli?
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    There's a risk, in focusing on second reply, of watering down the response to the other two. But it;s interesting, so...

    I gather, or at least supose, that mathematicians and physicist see a continuity between their use of "=" in 1+1=2 and in . Philosophers are the sort of people who question such things. Let's look at the three examples provided.


    makes the point that E=mc² can be considered as showing how we convert matter into energy, and that's a valid way to understand it. But others will say that it shows an equivalence such that matter and energy are different forms of the same thing. Need we insist that one of these views must be the correct on? I don't see why.

    X = vt + Xi is a pretty direct bit of maths. If you start at 5m and travel at 1m/s for three seconds, you will be at 8m. Is that final position identical to "1m/s x 3s +5m"? That's just 3m + 5m, so yes, it is.

    was derived form first principles rather than from the results of experiment. Interestingly the 3/2 comes from , the energy in each dimension added together. in kinetic theory, temperature is a measure of average kinetic energy. In this model, the concepts are interdefinable—we can understand temperature through motion and vice versa.

    We are indeed doing quite different things with each equation. However there is a pretty strong case for claiming that despite this, the "=" fulfils much the same role in each.

    That word - interdefinable - may well be seen as about a metaphysical stipulation.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    Thank you.

    So what I see is that skepticism, rather than security, is the basis of knowledge.Moliere

    Excellent phrase.
  • What is real? How do we know what is real?
    An excellent reply. "=" is used in different ways in these examples, so one can argue that such equations as these do not use "=" in the way that it is being used by logicians doing modal logic. If this is so then Kripke apparently overreaches in claiming the necessity of such equivalences. Following this line of thought, the relation between mean kinetic energy and temperature is not one of metaphysical identity.

    The implication for Kripke is a weakening of the apparatus he uses to argue for a posteriori necessity and doubt cast on his argument against the identity of mind and brain.



    One possible reply is that there is something in common to equations, since in each case they use the "=" to state that the value on the left will be the same as the value on the right; that it is this value that is rigidly designated, not the items in the equation. So in E=mc2, what is rigidly designated is that the value of E is the very same as the value of mc², and so on for each example. This would be to agree with you that in physics "=" does not always assert an ontological identity, but that if the use of "=" is to make any sense, it must assert the identity of the two values it equates.

    On this account, the identity here is not between ontological entities but between their values within the structure put together by doing science. This would considerably weaken the applicability of Kripke's system.



    A second possibility is that the historical use of "=" back to Russell's attempt to ground arithmetic in logic, does show that the "=" in physics is the same as the "=" in logic. They are both uses of the identity relation set out in Begriffsschrift, and that all arithmetic equations are grounded in that logical interpretation. It's just what "=" means. So the mean kinetic energy just is .

    This is a pretty dogmatic response, stating that the reason we can write such equations at all is that their effectiveness is dependent on or justified by the logic of identity, that accepting your argument would be tantamount to claiming that identity signs in physics are ambiguous and equivocal. Pretty harsh. My response to suffered from something like this, and perhaps Tim might say something similar. Are physical equations really that precise?



    A third approach might be to take on board what has been said, and go back to the basics to reassess how our modal logics work.

    In propositional logic, one can substitute any proposition for any other provided that they have the same truth value. In predicate logic, one can substitute any individual variable for another provided that they designate the same individual. In modal logic, this fails: while two propositions may both be true in a given world, it does not follow that they are true in every possible world. Truth is evaluated not only by what individual is designated, but also by which world the evaluation takes place in.

    However, at the level of possible worlds semantics, modal logic is extensional: formulas are assigned sets of possible worlds as their extensions, and modal operators like necessity (□) are interpreted as quantifying over those sets. That is, □A is true at a world w if A is true in every world accessible from w. Because substitution of formulas with identical extensions preserves truth across all worlds in the model, the possible worlds interpretation is extensional.

    ☐p is true in w iff p is true in every world that is accessible from w.

    We also have that in S5 and elsewhere that it is valid that a=b→□(a=b). It is the consequences of this simple theorem that Kripke is teasing out. The salient bit is that we may find out only a posteriori that a is indeed equal to b. This is what leads to the conclusion that so many find objectionable, that there are necessities that are discovered by looking around at how things are rather than understood a priori.

    In the simplest case, that a=b means that a and b are the very same individual. And becasue of the extensionality involved, with some standard considerations we have it that if some expression is true for a, it will also be true for b. There is no obvious reason that this analysis can't be somewhat extended, including to kinds. So if we find, as seems to be the case, that every animal that has a heart also has kidneys, then extensionally, the set of animals with hearts and the set of animals with kidneys are the very same set, and we can substitute "animals with hearts" for "animals with kidneys" while preserving truth.

    So if, whenever we pick out an animal that has a heart, we also thereby pick out an animal that has a kidney, then necessarily, if an animal has a heart then it has kidneys. If they are extensionally equivalent in every possible world, then necessarily, if an animal has a heart is has kidneys.

    We might do this if, for instance, we were to insist that if we were to come across some animal that appeared to have a kidney but no heart, what appears to be a kidney is not a kidney, but has been misidentified.

    The third response, then is to note that Kripke's move treats identity statements as extensional, and not in the intensional fashion seen in Malcolm. These rigid designators refer to the same entity or set in all possible worlds. Substitution of such identical entities is permitted at a modal semantic level, so when we find that a=b a posteriori, we might stipulate this as a metaphysical necessity, and reject counter instances as errors of identification.




    What we have here is an at least apparent conflict between two quite different approaches. Folk might be tempted to suppose, somewhat simplistically, that either one or the other must be true, and the other must be false. Is it the case that we must either adopt the extensional approach and Kripke, or the intensional approach of Malcolm? Or are they talking past each other.

    It might be interesting to look at Malcolm's approach through the lens of one of the formal intuitionist logics. Perhaps relevance logic would be informative.

    This post has taken a few hours to put together, so thanks for the challenge. I hope you find it as interesting as I do.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    Unless we have the difficult situation where an approved drug is blocked by legislation from being used for it's approved purpose.

    In January, the Queensland Government issued a Health Service Directive that prohibits public hospitals and health services from initiating puberty blockers (Stage 1 treatment) or gender-affirming hormones (Stage 2 treatment) for new patients under 18 diagnosed with gender dysphoria. This directive was done following concerns about prescribing practices at a clinic in Cairns and is pending the outcome of an independent review.

    Causing a bit of a stink. So should governments be permitted to overrule on such issues apparently on religious and ideological grounds, or is it better to leave it to those doing the work.

    See The fight to overturn Queensland’s trans ban
  • Demonstrating Intelligent Design from the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    That'll save on the physics budget then. No need for all that experimental machinery if they can work it out by deduction. Pencil and paper from now on.
  • Demonstrating Intelligent Design from the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    I think the interesting philosophical point is precisely the sense in which the laws of nature seem true a priori, irrespective of experience. I mean, whenever something is suggested that might not obey those laws on this forum, merry hell usually follows :-)Wayfarer
    "seem true a priori"?

    Surely not. Your intuitions can't be that bad.
  • Demonstrating Intelligent Design from the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    the laws don't just describe motion, they enable precise prediction.Wayfarer

    The law doesn't enable anything much. Except text book, perhaps. They do describe motion precisely, enabling prediction. Best avoid giving then the ontological status of involved in causation. Reification and all that. So better not to talk of enabling.

    None of which makes the descriptions arbitrary.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    There's a difference between outlawing and not approving. That's what I'm drawing your attention to.
  • Demonstrating Intelligent Design from the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    What is determined is how they orbit their stars and planets.Wayfarer
    Not determined so much as described. The motion precedes the "law," and supersedes it, too. The law was decided as a result of looking at the motion, and is changed in the light of further observation.

    So which is doing the "determining"?
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    That will not be happening in the future because it will be against the law.frank
    Not too keen on that.
    You've got a fairly profound misapprehension about how medine works.frank
    I'm involved in health consumer advocacy hereabouts, so I hope not - and doubt it, since I get to hear more than my share of horror stories. I do hope for the best, though. Evidence based practice is in the consumer's interest. Legislation tends to be either misguided or too slow.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    Puberty blockers were outlawed in Britain for people under 18 because there's no evidence that they accomplish what they're supposed to. Other countries including the US are following their lead.frank

    Thanks for being candid. I have a bit of an issue with legislating such "protections". Probably a hang over from studying Popperian ad hoc social engineering. I prefer to see the decisions made "locally" than "globally", except in the case of evidence-based demonstrated harm. The first finding in CASS is - lack of such an evidence base. Then noting "conflicting views among clinicians regarding appropriate treatment."

    The recommendations lean in the right direction. (edit)


    Keep going, if you like. encourage me to admire your views even less.Banno
    it's working.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    Someone a while ago made a joke about me doing quantum mechanics of gender here, and I guess I’ve moved on to quantum field theory of gender now.Pfhorrest
    Neat analysis. Cool. Makes a mess of the conservative desire to force everyone into one of two fixed boxes because complexity and ambiguity make them uncomfortable.

    I can see why you might prefer to maintain some distance from this discussion.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    I asked you over and over again for either evidence or sophisticated argument.Jeremy Murray

    And ignored the reasons given for not doing so. I didn't come here for a mud wrestle, a he-said-she-said yawn fest. Your accusations of trolling are feeble, your ad homs hackneyed.

    Basically you are being a bit of a dick. Perhaps your aim was to change my mind, but the result has been to reinforce my view of an unreasoning, wilfully ill-informed and ideologically driven opposition to trans discussions.

    Keep going, if you like. encourage me to admire your views even less.
  • Demonstrating Intelligent Design from the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    Compounding your own confusion.

    The law of diminishing returns applies. Have fun.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    You, sir, are contributing to the "Spiral of Silence".Jeremy Murray
    I'm here. I'm making noise.

    While your passion is apparent, I've not been persuaded to reconsider my view. Your tone is confrontational rather than enquiring, your evidence one-sided and your logic dubious.

    Cheers.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    That's how a lot of philosophy is done.RogueAI
    Calling this thread "philosophy" is a stretch. More like mud wrestling.

    And pretending that there is no evidence in support of the efficacy of puberty blockers is an act of bad faith.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    You came here to prove your point, not to discuss the topic. That's fine, if tedious.

    What about prudence and restraint? Nuance? Context? Perhaps the wisest course is epistemic modesty: recognising complexity, acknowledging uncertainty, and striving for a response that does justice to both care and caution.

    And in the mean time allowing some flexibility in order to accomodate the diversity of individual difficulties folk face.

    Not blanket responses.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    common sensefrank
    ...is a prevaricating term.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    And if it turn out to be so, your were right - but if it turns out to be wrong, then you will point to some machinations on the part of those of ill will, or do-gooders, to explain why.

    You win either way. Well done.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    It's a fact. That's where we're headed.frank
    And you know this... from examining a crystal ball?

    This thread is shite.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    What good is philosophy if it does not help evaluate evidence?Jeremy Murray
    Would you have a philosopher evaluate your cancer biopsy?

    It took me ten minutes to come up with this evidence, and I can go on.Jeremy Murray
    Why so long? Slow internet connection? If you would be an instant expert you might need to upgrade your network.

    I can do it too.

    A good argument for better health care. Not for rejecting gender affirmation outright.
  • Disambiguating the concept of gender
    every male who takes puberty blockers will be permanently infertile and will never have an orgasm.frank
    That's misinformation. Not wrong, but not quite right, either.

    Puberty blockers will eventually be illegal everywhere.frank
    Or improved so as to avoid these complications.

    But again, Instant expert syndrome is at play here.