Comments

  • Analytic and a priori
    IF there is no origin, and determinism obtains, then all states are necessary, by virtue of being determined by earlier states; in that scenario there never could be any contingent states at all.John

    Even if determinism is true, the state of the world at any time could still have been different if the state of the world as a whole had been different. If it is just an unquestionable premise for you that the state of the world as a whole is necessary, and not merely actual (and hence, conceivably, contingent), then you are simply assuming the truth of necessitarianism without argument. You don't even need to rely on the thesis of determinism. This also has nothing to do with randomness. Contingent occurrences need not be random. Being determined by the past, and being necessary, are two different things.
  • Analytic and a priori
    So determinism, at least in this strong sense that allows for no true randomness, is coterminous with necessitarianism.John

    That's only true if the first state of the world (if there is one) obtains not just actually but necessarily. This additional premise maybe something that you believe to be true, but it isn't part of determinism as ordinarily conceived.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Notice also that the same sort of mistake in modal logic can lead one fallaciously to infer the thesis of the necessity of the past from true premises.

    Let P be a proposition that expresses the state of the world at some past time t.

    The following two premises are true:

    (1) P is actual

    (2) nec(if P is actual, then P)

    But it doesn't follow from those two premises that nec(P).
  • Analytic and a priori
    Nope. It's deterministic.Mongrel

    Determinism doesn't have the implication that whatever is actual is necessary. Determinism rather is the weaker thesis that the state of the world at any given time, in conjunction with the laws of nature, determines uniquely the state of the world at any other time. Hence, if determinism is true, and P and Q are 'maximal' propositions that express the actual states of the world at times t1 and t2, respectively, then it follows that, necessarily, if P then Q. However, if P is actual (and t1 is some time in the past), it doesn't follow from determinism, in conjunction with P and the laws of nature, that Q is necessary. That's an elementary blunder in modal logic that leads some people (mainly in philosophy forums) to slide fallaciously from determinism to necessitarianism.

    From the two premises

    (1) P is actual,

    (2) if P then Q

    doesn't follow

    (3) nec(Q)

    In order to derive the conclusion (3) validly from something like (1) and (2) you would need to modify the first premise to read

    (1b) nec(P).

    But it doesn't follow from the thesis of determinism that the state of the world, at any given time in the past, necessarily obtains. Hence necessitarianism, the thesis that you are endorsing, doesn't follow from determinism. You also need the thesis of the necessity of the past, and this thesis is independent from determinism.
  • Analytic and a priori
    If you notice, my view is deterministic. Any statement about actuality that is true is necessarily true. It's fun to think about how that works out in modal logic... for me, anyway.Mongrel

    That would make you a necessitarian rather than a determinist, although you may be a determinist as well. Necessitarianism is the view that everything that is actual is necessary. Determinists may hold that although only one future is consistent with the actual past, the whole history of the world isn't necessary, and hence they need not be necessitarians as well. This view (necessitarianism) had sometimes been called actualism in the older literature (e.g. by M. R. Ayers in his The Refutation of Determinism, Methuen, 1968) but now, the label actualism rather is used by analytic philosophers to refer to the denial of possibilism (or of 'modal realism', which is a sort of possibilism). Many things you said in this thread seem to stem from your being a necessitarian (or "actualist" in Ayers' sense), but also to be inconsistent with actualism in the new sense.

    This would also explain why some of the things you say may seem to clash with what TGW, or Kripke, or Soames, or I myself, would say, since none of us are necessitarians.
  • Analytic and a priori
    If I'm thinking of the actual France, it has Paris as its capital in all possible worlds where the actual France exists (which is exactly how many?)

    And I learned aposteriori that the actual France has Paris as its capital.

    Problem?
    Mongrel

    There are two problems. First, the "actual France" and some "alternative France" (as you might contemplate it in some possible world) are not distinct objects. If there exists a possible world where France has Toulouse as its capital, this simply means that France (the very same object) could possibly have had Toulouse as its capital. Likewise, in the actual world, me, being 6 feet tall isn't a different person from me, being Canadian. And if I cease to be Canadian, it doesn't follow that "me, being Canadian", some queer object with just one arbitrary determination tacked onto it by fiat, goes out of existence, but merely that, I, the flesh and blood individual, who was contingently Canadian all along, have lost my Canadian citizenship.

    The second problem is that the question of the epistemological status (i.e. its being known a priori or a posteriori) of some proposition "X is F" that it is true, and of the de re modal claim "X necessarily is F" that it is true, are two distinct questions. So, that you learned the first sort of claim (factual) a posteriori doesn't get you off the charge that your procedure for establishing the second sort of fact (modal necessity) is not a posteriori. It is still by fiat that you are establishing the second sort of claim.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Yes, and I do appreciate that Paris is not the capital of France, in a 'fully' analytic sense, that is strictly by definition, inasmuch as the word 'Paris' does not definitively mean 'capital of France'.John

    I think the smoking gun is that Paris preexists the time when Clovis made it the capital of his Kingdom. But what has mainly been at issue in my discussion with Mongrel isn't the de re modal status of Paris's being France's capital, but rather the de re modal status of France's having Paris as its capital city. It is the a posteriori necessary status of this latter de re claim that is a issue. The claims are independent. Likewise, you arguably have the natural parents that you have essentially (i.e. it is a de re necessity, on some reasonable accounts of personal identity) but it is a contingent fact about your natural parents (de re contingency) that they have had you as a child.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Of coarse not. The speaker I mentioned doesn't know apriori what the capital of France is.Mongrel

    The fiat at issue concerns the claim about France* (or whatever the speaker means to be referring to as "France") having Paris as it capital necessarily. If this sort of relativized necessity is merely a matter of interpreting the speaker's intention, then it is not a posteriori.

    And the question being evaluated wouldn't be about what the capital of France is. It would be about something else. like the possibility of Paris, France hosting the Olympics.

    When you inquire about the possibility that Paris, France, hosting the Olympics, the country, France, that is at issue, still has Paris as its capital contingently. It just so happens that you are not interested in what would happen if Paris would lose its status as France's capital. Just because this possibility is irrelevant to your inquiry hardly makes is necessary (let alone a posteriori necessary) that the object, France, being considered in those counterfactual scenarios, has Paris as its capital.

    You seem to be conflating the following two claims:

    (1) Necessarily, if I am thinking of France in circumstances where it has Paris as its capital, then in all those circumstances, France has Paris as its capital.

    (2) If I am thinking of France in circumstances where it has Paris as its capital, then, France, as I am thinking about it, necessarily has Paris as its capital.

    The first claim is a truism that fails to entail the second. The second claim is false since disregarding a possibility doesn't make it an impossibility, let alone an a posteriori impossibility.
  • Analytic and a priori
    I wouldn't ask Scott Soames to read this thread.

    I'll write it out and give it to you for approval. OK?

    And if you have any philosophers you want on the list, just let me know where they work.
    Mongrel

    I wouldn't want you to ask him to read the thread -- just provide the link for reference. I wouldn't want to bother any of them, myself. But sure, if you want to submit a paraphrase of our conflicting positions, and submit it to me first, go ahead. You can post it here.
  • Analytic and a priori
    It's only in the light of aposteriori necessity that we limit our assessment.

    Traditionally, there was no limitation. There is no possible world where a bachelor is not an unmarried man.... you don't need the existence of bachelors in a world for that statement to be true.
    Mongrel

    So, you are again pointing to a limitation agreed upon by everyone. This is the limitation to worlds in which the relevant objects (that are targets of de re a posteriori necessities) exist. In the case of France having Paris as its capital, that would be a limitation to worlds in which France exists. In the case of water being essentially composed of H2O, that would be worlds in which water exists. In the case of Samuel Clemens being Mark Twain, that would be worlds in which Samuel Clemens exists. In all of those cases, the relevant modal truths are a posteriori (and thus a matter of empirical investigation) precisely because it is not simply up to us to stipulate some arbitrarily range of possible worlds such that the modal claim would come out true. If we do so, in the way you are proposing, then it isn't France, water or Samuel Clemens that we are talking about, unrestrictedly, but rather what is true of them, tautologically, in those circumstances only where it is assumed to be true of them.

    Again, you are missing that a posteriori necessary statements are empirically falsifiable. They aren't true by fiat, as they would be according to your analysis in terms of speaker intended limitation.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Deal?Mongrel

    Sure, if you wish. But give them a pointer to this thread so that your paraphrase of our disagreement doesn't misrepresent its nature. You still seem to be taking me to be denying truisms when I am rather questioning the implications that you are deriving from them.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Point to where I denied that.Mongrel

    I just did, immediately after the ":"

    It's relevant, and I would say critical to grasping the concept of aposteriori necessary truths that we're talking about statements that are true over a limited number of possible worlds as opposed to true over all possible worlds.
    (My bold)

    "... over a limited number ... as opposed to all possible worlds" would appear to contradict "...in all possible worlds."
  • Analytic and a priori
    Is there some reason a speaker could not say "France" and mean a country that has Paris as its capital?Mongrel

    Whenever anyone speaks about France, one speaks about a country that indeed has Paris as its capital. It is generally understood that it doesn't have Paris as its capital essentially. That is, there are intelligible counterfactual circumstances in which France has (or would lave had) another city as its capital. It would still have been France. But you are rather meaning to say, it seems, that one could conjure up a new meaning for the word "France" such that the 'country' that answers to it has Paris as its capital essentially (which also requires an arbitrary modification of the ordinary concept of a country). I am unsure what the point of doing so would be. For whatever object X that has property P contingently, I can conjure up some concept X* such that X falls under X* and X* has property P essentially. This is a queer and artificial concept reminiscent of Quine's gavagai or Goodman's grue. It doesn't seem to have any bearing en the topic of a posteriori necessary truths, which are truths that we can investigate about, and are empirically falsifiable, rather than being modal truths that we stipulate by dint of arbitrary concept modification as you seemingly envision them to be. Stipulated truths aren't a posteriori.
  • Analytic and a priori
    And if a statement is necessarily true, it's true in all possible worlds.Mongrel

    Yes. That's what I am claiming. And that's what you seem to have been denying consistently:

    It's relevant, and I would say critical to grasping the concept of aposteriori necessary truths that we're talking about statements that are true over a limited number of possible worlds as opposed to true over all possible worlds.

    You appear, strangely, not to have realized that a posteriori necessary statements are... necessary.
  • Analytic and a priori
    This is a confusing statement. Necessary modifies true. I guess it could modify false... that could be managed. You seem to be thinking of some.... thing? as being contingent or necessary. Some thing that could have been otherwise if it's contingent.Mongrel

    Sorry, this was a shorthand. I means something being said; some proposition, or claim of de re necessity.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Having determined the meaning of a statement, one need not at any point abandon that meaning for some convention for the sake of predicating truth.

    No philosopher I know of would disagree with that. Do you know of one?
    Mongrel

    You thought I was advancing something crazy and I merely clarified what I meant. Now you seem to agree. But in that case, once it is established what de re necessity it is someone is purporting to express, you haven't shown how this claim being a posteriori necessary could depend in any way on the intentions of the speaker (beyond specifying what she means to say), or -- what has been centrally at issue between us -- how it could depend on some arbitrarily restricted range of possible worlds being single out for special consideration by the speaker (e.g. worlds in which France has Paris as its capital city). You've merely muddled the issue with the insistence the the items under consideration must exist in those possible worlds, which is trivially accepted by everyone (see my earlier Kripke and Burgess references) and has nothing to do with the speaker's particular intentions. Worlds in which water or Samuel Clemens don't exist just don't have any relevance to the evaluation of the modal status of the claims of a posteriori necessity that we've been considering.
  • Analytic and a priori
    As it is, your position seems to leave you endorsing a contradiction. Intention matters when discerning meaning, but not when evaluating modal claims. That just seems crazy to me.Mongrel

    That seems rather trivial to me. If someone purports to make some statement of a posteriori necessity, then, in a first step, you may indeed have to pay attention of the circumstances of her utterance, and her communicative intentions, etc., in order to understand what it is that she is claiming to be a posteriori necessary. Then, in a second step, by dint of the fact that her claim can only be known to be true a posteriori, you have to investigate what it is, in the world, that makes it true (e.g. investigate the nature of water, or seek out, by means of investigative journalism, if Clark Kent and Superman really are the same person, as she claims them to be.

    In short, it's one thing to assess what it is someone means to say, and another to evaluate if it is true. In the special case where the claim can be known to be true a priori, then, maybe, those two steps collapse into the first one, but it is precisely a distinctive feature of the a posteriori necessary that they do not so collapse.
  • Analytic and a priori
    It's relevant, and I would say critical to grasping the concept of aposteriori necessary truths that we're talking about statements that are true over a limited number of possible worlds as opposed to true over all possible worlds.Mongrel

    This is a puzzling remark that you would have to explain. That something is necessary rather than contingent just means that it could not have been otherwise in any circumstance, which is exactly how Kripke urges that the claim that there is no "possible world" where it is false be understood. If there were (per impossibile) a possible world where Samuel Clemens isn't Mark Twain, then this would mean that they aren't necessarily identical, and hence, a fortiori, that the claim of identity is not a posteriori necessary. Likewise, if there were a possible world where water isn't composed of H2O, that would mean that water isn't necessarily composed of H2O, and hence, a fortiori, that this claim of essence isn't a posteriori necessary either.
  • Analytic and a priori
    And this just to show that the analytic/ synthetic divide is not as clear cut as it is sometimes made out to be.John

    True, but then, if the division isn't clear cut, this means that many socially instituted facts (e.g. the values of currencies relative to the gold standard, of the legal/political/administrative functions of cities and institutions) also have an empirical character. Also, if some entity has an institutional status (e.g. some city being the capital of a sovereign state) as a result of the collective will of the people (or of the King, etc.), then if the determination of this human will is itself contingent, then so is the inherited status and official function of the entity.
  • Analytic and a priori
    I hold that in the case of any utterance, it will have to be sorted out somehow what it means. You can't just point to what you understand to be linguistic convention.

    You apparently disagree with that as well. Again.. I think you're wrong.
    Mongrel

    I certainly don't disagree with this either. I am questioning the inferences that you are drawing from this. It is one thing to evaluate what is said by a speaker who makes use of a sentence, accounting for pragmatic considerations and contextual features of the utterance, and another to evaluate the modal status of the claim being made. You wish to make the latter rest entirely on the former, but questions of a posteriori necessity obviously outrun mere considerations of the utterer's intentions. If they would rest entirely on intention and/or convention then those modal claims would be a priori, stipulated by mere fiat.
  • Analytic and a priori
    I hold that Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain can only be true at a possible world that contains an object picked out by Samuel Clemens.

    If you disagree, we have an impasse, but all I can say is I think you're wrong.
    Mongrel

    I don't disagree. I quite agree. You misread me. I denied that the evaluation of this sentence at possible worlds where Samuel Clemens doesn't exist is relevant to the determination of the modal status of this sentence. Kripke agrees, since he restricts his attention to possible worlds where the relevant objects exist in his demonstration of the necessity of identity. See the first four pages of his paper Identity and Necessity, or the first few pages of John P. Burgess's paper On a Derivation of the Necessity of Identity.

    Unless you are a modal realist, then you can simply hold, as does Kripke, that X is necessarily identical to Y if and only if there is no possibility that X not to be identical to Y, where X and Y are the objects designated by "X" and by "Y", respectively, in the actual world (*). It's not relevant to the evaluation of this claim that X's or Y's existence be contingent, and hence that there might be possible worlds where they don't exist. Likewise, to repeat myself, the evaluation of the a posteriori necessity of water being composed of H2O is insensitive to the mere possibility that the world might have been devoid of water (and thereby, of course, also devoid of H2O).

    (*) See Kripke's Naming and Necessity p.14: "I will say something briefly about 'possible worlds'. (I hope to elaborate elsewhere.) In the present monograph I argued against those misuses of the concept that regard possible worlds as something like distant planets, like our own surroundings but somehow existing in a different dimension, or that lead to spurious problems of 'transworld identification'. Further, if one wishes to avoid the Weltangst and philosophical confusions that many philosophers have associated with the 'worlds' terminology, I recommended that 'possible state (or history) of the world', or 'counterfactual situation' might be better. One should even remind oneself that the 'worlds' terminology can often be replaced by modal talk—'It is possible that . . .'"
  • Analytic and a priori
    The difference you are still failing to see is that the fact that the sun is shining is directly observable; whereas the fact that Paris is the capital of France is not, The latter is a kind of secondary fact that can be known only by accepting what others have said; it is derivative on the fact that people say that they designate and consider Paris to be the capital. If people ceased to designate and consider Paris to be the capital tomorrow it would cease to be the capital.John

    Yes, of course, social-institutional facts aren't the sorts of facts that physicists and other natural scientists are interested in. Facts of the former kind are, in a sense, human dependent in a way that facts of the latter kind aren't; although I would resist attempts to inflate this common sense distinction into a sharp dichotomy. If human beings were wiped off the surface of the Earth, most objects left behind would lose most of their socially instituted determinations (for instance, monetary tokens would cease to have determinate monetary values, dogs would cease to be pets, etc.), but they would retain their natural-scientific determinations. I am not denying or ignoring this distinction but it seems to have little relevance to the a priori/ a posteriori or the necessary/contingent distinction that are being discussed in this thread. Both of those distinctions cut across the institutional/natural divide that you are appealing to. Many natural facts can be known a priori and/or are necessary, and many social/institutional facts can be known a posteriori and/or are contingent. So I don't see how you can expect to ground the distinctions that are the topic of this thread on the social-institutional/natural divide.
  • Analytic and a priori
    If the statement can't be evaluated at all at those worlds, then it certainly isn't true at them.Mongrel

    Not necessarily. If you analyse all singular terms as definite descriptions (as Russell does in the case of all singular referring expression except for private demonstrative reference to one's own sense data and one's use of the first personal pronoun) then all statements of the form "The X is F" would be evaluated false at possible worlds where nothing answers to the description "X". But proper names (or ordinary demonstratives) aren't like that. If a proper name NN is empty, then the statement "NN is red", say, is not false. It is meaningless. It purports but fails to express a singular thought. Nobody would say that NN isn't red (which would logically follow from "it is not true that NN is red") who knows NN not to exist.
  • Analytic and a priori
    In any case, I didn't want to get into modal philosophy at all. I was originally making a point about the differences between the kinds of knowledge exemplified by "Paris is the capital of France" and "the Sun is shining at such and such a location at such and such a time", and TGW and Jamalrob denied that there is any valid distinction in kind between those two propositions. That there is such a valid distinction is all I have been arguing for.John

    So far as I can see, that the Sun is shining at some place X at some time T is an empirical and contingent fact of geography/meteorology/astronomy, whereas that France has Paris as its capital city at some time T is an empirical and contingent fact of human history. The Sun would still be the Sun while hidden behind a thick cloud cover and France would still be France with its capital city established away from Paris. I don't see any categorical difference between those two cases in point of topic-neutral metaphysics.
  • Analytic and a priori
    To interject...there is a paper by Michael Weisberg called Water is not H20. I liked it. Distilled water, maybe, although I gather chemists would prefer greater precision even then. But this topic gets me into hot, erm water. Someone turned me down for a Master's course over a paper i wrote about it. Water just is H20, she exclaimed. How then can heavy water be a form of water? How can the polluted water in my local canal be water?mcdoodle

    Yes indeed. The crude identity statement is quite a simplification. Hilary Putnam himself was sensitive to some of those pragmatic consideration, even as early as his original The Meaning of "Meaning" paper, if I remember.

    Which is why I rather like the loose phrasing "Water is essentially materially constituted by H2O", since "essentially" has the ordinary language connotation "almost but not quite exactly". It's got to have some fair amount of H2O in it, and heavy water is almost but not quite H2O, isn't it? (For deuterium and tritium also are hydrogen isotopes). Putnam was also, of course, sensitive to the fact that some stuff-names, such as jade, aren't "natural kind" terms at all. And some acceptions of "water" may also be like that.
  • Analytic and a priori
    So you're agreeing that we don't look at all possible worlds. We look at all relevant possible worlds... specifically where our rigid designators pick out an object that exists in that world.Mongrel

    Well, if we are evaluating the de re modal status of a true statement (i.e. inquiring about its being necessary of merely contingently true predication of some object) then we are looking for a possible world at which this statement might be evaluated false. If the object mentioned in the statement does't exist in some possible worlds, then the statement can't be evaluated at all, so those worlds aren't relevant. But when the statements at issue are purported a posteriori necessary statements, then it is not up to us (or up to "speaker's intentions") whether or not such a possible world W exists, or doesn't exists, such that the statement would be evaluated false.

    Hence, I may know who Mark Twain is, and also have heard about some writer called Samuel Clemens, and not know that they are the same person. When I make this discovery (in the actual world, through historical investigation) then I can rule out that there is any possible world at which Mark Twain isn't Samuel Clemens. Possible worlds where Mark Twain never was born (whoever else might have been given the same name) aren't relevant to my discovery.

    By the way, it seems to me that the reason why we speak of evaluating statements at possible worlds, rather than in possibles worlds, in the technical literature, might be in order preempt the confusion that the statements are to be evaluated in accordance with the alternative linguistic conventions that hold among our Doppelgangers "in" those worlds. This is a mistake that you (and John, if I remember) have a tendency to make. Evaluating a statements at a world means assessing its truth value in the hypothesized circumstances of this world while interpreting the statement in accordance with our own language. Hence, who Mark Twain refers to in some possible world W, at which we are evaluating the statement "Mark Twain is a featherless biped" is insensitive to whatever name Mark Twain goes by in that world. When those conventions are lost track of, endless confusion ensues.
  • Analytic and a priori
    But what about worlds where this man does not exist?Mongrel

    Possible worlds in which Mark Twain never was born aren't relevant to the evaluations of the necessity of the identity between the people that we call "Mark Twain" and "Samuel Clemens" in the actual world. I am unsure why you think there being such possible worlds is relevant. The positive claims of necessary identity between them is equivalent the claim that there isn't any possible world at which the men that we designate with those two different names both exist and aren't numerically identical, or at which one of them only would exist.

    Likewise, the claims that water essentially is H2O is equivalent to the claim that there is no possible world at which both water and H2O-stuff would exist and they would not be the same stuff, or at which only one of those two stuffs would exist. It is irrelevant to this claim of metaphysical identity (or claim of metaphysically necessary material constitution, if you prefer) that there are possible worlds at which water doesn't exist at all. Also, that there are possible worlds where France never came about, historically, isn't relevant to nationhood being an essential property of France (if it is one).
  • Analytic and a priori
    Explain to me again how "Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain" is necessarily true.Mongrel

    Simply put, because, firstly, although "Samuel Clemens" and "Mark Twain" have different Fregean senses, they have the same references in all possible worlds (being rigid designators), and the truth of statements of identity between two items depend only on the references of the words used to refer to them. And, secondly, because Kripke and Ruth Barcan Marcus have argued convincingly that identity is a necessary relation.

    By contrast, the de dicto necessity statement: 'necessarily, the man named "Samuel Clemens" is Mark Twain' is false because 'the man named "Samuel Clemens"' -- the first term of the identity relation -- isn't a rigid designator. It picks different items in different possible worlds, and in some of those, this man isn't Mark Twain (and neither is it Samuel Clemens! -- it's just someone else who was named "Samuel Clemens")

    It is still truly said of the man named Samuel Clemens in the actual world (de re) that is Mark Twain (albeit not necessarily named Mark Twain!) in all possible worlds, and vice versa.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Pierre.

    Samuel Clemens didn't have to pick the pen-name Mark Twain. He could have picked something else.
    Mongrel

    Yes, and he could also have been baptized some name other than Samuel? So what? You might just as well claim that "water is H2O" doesn't express an metaphysical necessity just because "water" has been used to name "iron" in some alternative history of the English language. When we are assessing the truth of a claim of de dicto necessity, we are interpreting the worlds in which the claim is made according to actual and present linguistic conventions, not the alternate conventions that hold at the different times or counterfactual situations that we are talking about.

    When we say that "Mark Twain is Samuel Clemens" expresses a metaphysical necessity, we are not implying that "Mark Twain" always has been uses (if at all) with the reference that we are assigning to it now. What distinguishes a de dicto from a de re necessity is not the fact that linguistic expressions have arbitrary meanings. It is rather a matter of the scope of the modal operator relative to the scope of the existential statement (when the claim of necessity of made explicit in modal logic). The issue of the conventionality of linguistic meaning is entirely separate; it is unrelated to the de dicto/de re distinction.
  • Analytic and a priori
    I think what you're doing is imagining some criteria for reference that holds in spite of a speaker's intentions.Mongrel

    My claim is rather more narrow than that. I am merely denying your claim that when people think of France in some counterfactual scenario, they are thinking of "France" as referring to an object that has its envisioned determinations necessarily. That's just not part of the speaker's intention, and even if it were, it would have no bearing on the issue of a posteriori necessity being discussed in the literature. If you were right about the relationship between necessity and speaker's intentions, then there would be no a posteriori necessity, for there would be no way to inquire empirically about such metaphysical necessities. Whatever one would envision to be necessary for X to exist as we intend to represent it to be determined would be metaphysically necessary by fiat. Each and every speaker would have his own vacuous and tautological conception about how it is necessary that an object be determined in some merely stipulated situation. Hence, what would make it 'necessary' for France to have Paris as its capital is that someone is imagining it in some situation where it has Paris as its capital. That seems to be your account of a posteriori necessity in a nutshell.
  • Analytic and a priori
    When were they co-referential terms?

    Consider the truth of the sentence when Clemens was a child. In case you don't know who we're talking about.... no, he was not Mark Twain at that time.
    Mongrel

    People don't come into existence when they are named. "Mark Twain was born in 1835" is a true statement in spite of the fact that he was actually baptized Samuel Langhorne Clemens. He was indeed Mark Twain when he was born, he was just not going by that name. In fact he wasn't going by the name Samuel Clemens either, in all probability. "He was not Mark Twain at that time" isn't the true denial of an identity claim, it's just shorthand for the true claim that he wasn't going by that name at the time.
  • Analytic and a priori
    OK, so I think you're refusing to acknowledge something that should be very clear.

    "Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain."

    This is not a necessarily true statement. You should know why that is and you should know what you have to add to it to make it necessarily true.
    Mongrel

    Actually it is a necessary statement since the context is extensional and co-referential terms can be intersubstituted in it salva veritate. The sentence thus expresses the de re necessity, about Mark Twain, that he is identical with himself. It might not be necessary if it were embedded in some intensional context. Someone who ignores that Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain would thus not realize that this sentence expresses a de re necessity, just as someone who would ignore that water essentially is H2O would not grasp that the demonstrative sentence "this water sample is composed of H2O" (in context) expresses a metaphysical necessity.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Likewise,

    If the France that I'm thinking of exists, it's capital is Paris.

    That is a necessarily true statement if the France I'm thinking of must have Paris as its capital.
    Mongrel

    You are making an invalid inference from one de re necessity statement to another unrelated de re necessity statement. Just because you are thinking about France in circumstances where it has Paris as its capital doesn't entail that the object you are thinking about, France, necessarily has Paris as its capital. It could possibly have some other capital. The first de re necessity is about you and your specific thought about France. That you are thinking about France having some specific determinations (either actual or counterfactual) may generate de re necessities about this very thought that you have, but it doesn't generate de re necessities about France. It would still be possible for you (counterfactually) to think intelligibly about France not having Paris as its capital. You would not thereby be thinking about a different country.

    Also, the nominal phrase "France as it exists with Paris as its capital" is not the name of a Fregean object. It's just a device used to call attention to a possible determination of an object. Just because you can call attention to a possible determination of an object hardly make that determination metaphysically necessary.
  • Analytic and a priori
    No it isn't. We covered this already. This sentence is necessarily true:

    If Samuel Clemens exists, he is Mark Twain.
    Mongrel

    Of course they are identical in any world where they exist. In possible worlds where Mark Twain never was born, the issue doesn't arise. My point it that they aren't identical just because you are arbitrarily restricting your attention only to some set of possible worlds where they are identical, as you are attempting to do with the case of France having Paris as its capital. In the latter case, you remain free to widen the scope of your consideration to possible worlds where France's capital moved, whereas in the former case there just aren't any possible worlds for you to consider where Samuel Clemens isn't Mark Twain. A posteriori metaphysical necessity isn't a mere matter of stipulation or the arbitrary restriction of the range of possible worlds being considered in some scenario.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Since the the object I'm talking about must have Paris as its capital, perhaps it's a moot point whether we call it essential or not. It's necessary. And it's aposteriori knowledge.

    Agree?
    Mongrel

    No it is not essential, neither is it necessary, logically or metaphysically. It just so happens that you are restricting you attention to counterfactual situations where France nevertheless still has Paris as its capital. That hardly makes it necessary that France has Paris as its capital. Likewise, I could restrict my attention to possible worlds where all water is liquid. This would not make it necessary that water is liquid in the same sense that water necessarily is composed of H2O. However, I am not free to posit possible worlds where water is composed of XYZ. This would be to misconstrue what water essentially is (if Kripke and Putnam are right).

    Likewise, if Samuel Clemens is (numerically identical to) Mark Twain then they are the same person in all possible worlds where they exist; and that's not just because I've chosen to arbitrarily restrict my attention merely to possible worlds where this identity holds. The identity expressed (by us, in the actual world) by the sentence "Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain" is necessary (i.e. it holds at *all* possible worlds) assuming only that it holds in the actual world and that both "Samuel Clemens" and "Mark Twain" are proper names (and not conventionally abbreviated definite descriptions, say). Here also, the necessity of identity doesn't depend on the speaker's intention in the way that you suggest. Is is not relative to the specific counterfactual situation that the speaker countenances.
  • Analytic and a priori
    3. I may tell you that: "France might have escaped invasion that year." From the context of the conversation, you know (beyond any shadow of a doubt) that I mean the France that actually existed in 1940. Since that particular France had Paris as its capital, considering a possible world in which France did not have Paris as its capital would be a mistake. The object I am considering must have Paris as its capital.Mongrel

    Yes, for sure, you are talking about a counterfactual situation where France still has Paris as its capital. This hardly establishes that the country, France, that you are talking about, has Paris as its capital essentially. You seem to be assuming without argument that "the France that actually existed in 1940" is an object that has all its actual properties essentially. But this is a confusion of categories. The object talked about just is France, while also talked about are all the essential and contingent determinations that this object is countenanced to have in the counterfactual situation. If we were to countenance France having a different capital, instead, then we would not be countenancing a different object, but rather a different (counterfactual) determination of this very same object.
  • Analytic and a priori
    I baptize a turnip "France."

    Pierre: "That's not France."
    Me: "Well, it's not the country whose capital is Paris. That's true. But I'm calling it France."
    Pierre: "But it's not France."
    Me: "What do you mean by France? What picks it out of any world (including this one?"

    Previously you responded with "It's stipulated."
    Mongrel

    This is an example where two different things of two different sorts (and hence that possess two distinct sets of essential properties), might both be named "France". If you are thus talking about counterfactual de re possibilities regarding some object that you are designating with the word "France", the context of your utterance may resolve whether it is France, the European country, or rather your favorite turnip that is at issue. When this ambiguity has been resolved then it is indeed your stipulation and nothing else that makes it the case that the objects that you mean to be talking about, in the counterfactual situation, is your turnip rather than France the country.

    We are making use of established (or ah hoc) naming practices, and the associated conceptual apparatus, in order to secure reference both to objects as they are in the actual world and also to those objects (the very same objects) as we fancy them to possibly be (counterfactually). When I judge my turnip to be white, or countenance that it could possibly have ripened pink (counterfactually), it is the very same turnip (numerical identity) that I either perceive (and designate demonstratively, say) or predicate counterfactual determinations of. Talk about "possible worlds" may obscure this very trivial fact if one has inchoate modal realist intuitions, maybe. Then one may feel like one has first to posit a possible world, and then, in a second step, specify what specific counterpart (or Doppelganger) the "actual object" ought to be identified with in the possible world. But this is nonsense. The merely "possible world" wasn't dreamed up appart from the act of positing the "actual object" having, counterfactually, some different determinations.

    Honestly, I think it would help if you read the SEP article I pointed you toward. The issue you're imagining as resolved is not. One solution (that you seem to lean toward every now and then) is that we link a proper name to an object in a possible world via a proposition.

    It would also help if you would be rather more specific than that. You yourself have raised very many different issues under the same label "the issue". This SEP article on Rigid Designators also raises very many issues that apply specifically to different theories or conceptions about singular reference. Some of the issues only are issues if you are a modal realist, others only are issues if you hold on to a purely descriptive theory of Fregean senses (and hence have trouble countenancing genuine singular reference), or, in the same vein, if you are holding on to some so called causal theory of reference (similar to what Franck Jackson seems to be targeting). If you aren't beholden to any one of those theories, then most of the issues drop. Kripke isn't beholden to any one of them, but he doesn't claim to have a positive theory of his own. His talk about the unbroken "causal" chain that a naming practice must retain to an initial naming event may invite (and has invited) non-conceptual "causal theories".

    Gareth Evans and John McDowell have developed an alternative conceptions to such non-conceptual "causal" anchoring theories. (See Evan's chapter 11 (Proper Names) in The Varieties of Reference, or McDowell's paper Putnam on Mind and Meaning for primers.
  • Analytic and a priori
    If what you wrote there is true, there should be no issue with a speaker stipulating an object, France, which must have Paris as its capital.Mongrel

    Sure, and one might just as well stipulate that "France" is the name of a turnip and therefore is essentially a vegetable. So what? If you make up essential properties and tag them on France arbitrarily, it's not France anymore that you are talking about.
  • Analytic and a priori
    Kripke side-stepped the issue. So, apparently, have you.Mongrel

    The reason why your name picks you up rather than your body is because it has been introduced in the language (when you were baptized, say) as the name of a living human being, and not the name of your body, or the name of the set of molecules that make you up at a time, or whatever else might be copresent with you. Kripke's so called "causal theory of reference" (which he disown) creates that sort of problems for the initial anchoring of a proper name. Co-presence doesn't entail numerical identity, and sortal-concepts (such as the concept of a person) enable us to distinguish merely copresent items that have different individuation and persistance criteria. (See David Wiggins: Sameness and Substance Renewed)
  • Analytic and a priori
    I asked "so again what is it that makes an imagined purported alternative France numerically identical to the actual France? [/i] but you haven't answered the question. If I had an alternative history, given that I am a more or less self-contained biological organism; I would still be recognizable as myself. But in what sense could this be the case with a so-called France that had an alternative history. It simply wouldn't be France at all, because it wouldn't have had any of the same people, or the same configuration of villages, towns and cites, or occupy exactly the same territory or speak the same language. So on the basis of what could we think that it really is an alternative France?John

    It is not a "purported alternative France" that I was talking about; it is France. France would still be France if, counterfactually, at some point in time, its history had diverged from its actual history in some inessential respects. Likewise, if you actually went to work today, you would still be the same person if you had chosen to skip work instead. Your talk about "actual France" and "alternative France" -- as if those were distinct entities -- confuses you. There is just one France being considered in respect of its actual state (or history), or possible counterfactual states (or histories).

    Maybe you are an actualist. Many of your comments point in that direction. Actualists believe that whatever P is actually true is necessarily true, and whatever Q is actually false is necessarily false. Hence, anything that is possible is necessary, on that view; there is no non-actualized possibilities. But that is a rather contentious metaphysical doctrine.

Pierre-Normand

Start FollowingSend a Message