We all use them to pick out white and gold and blue and black things. We just differ on which things. — creativesoul
The adjectives "red" and "painful" describe things like pens and stubbing one's toe.
The nouns "red" and "pain" refer to the mental percepts that pens and stubbing one's toe cause to occur. — Michael
Do all of the eyes that are perceiving the very same scenery at the very same time from nearly the same vantage point perceive the same light? Yup. — creativesoul
Why focus on color specifically then? — Hanover
I'm just not buying into Lockean primary and secondary qualities where some qualities are deemed mind created and others inherent in the object. — Hanover
Colour variation is the fact that what colour physical objects look to have depends on viewing conditions and a perceiver’s visual system. Both Colour Relationalists and Colour Eliminativists regard their analyses of colour variation as central to the justification for their respective views. Yet the analyses are decidedly different. Colour Relationalists assert that most instances of colour variation are veridical and infer from this that colours are relational properties of objects that are partly determined by perceivers. By contrast, Colour Eliminativists assert that colour variation is too unsystematic to ground the claim that many or most instances of colour variation are veridical. From this they infer that objects don’t have colours. I argue that the Eliminativist analysis is superior. On my view, the Relationalist account of veridical colour experience reduces to the assertion that objects have colour simply because they cause perceivers to have colour experiences of them. In this context, I argue, the resulting conception of veridicality is vacuous. More directly, the foundational idea of Eliminativism is the opposite claim: the fact that objects cause perceivers to have colour experiences of them is on its own not sufficient to justify or ground the claim that objects have colour. The Relationalist, I argue, has failed to justify anything stronger than this. In this debate we should thus side with the Eliminativist: objects do not possess colour; they merely cause us to undergo colour experiences.
It is fair to say that Eliminativists value adequate explanations of phenomena like colour variation more than, for example, offering a straightforward account of Common Sense Colour. In this regard, theirs is a “perception first” approach to colour (as opposed, e.g., to a “language first” or “no priority” approach). They need not (and generally do not) doubt that there are blueberries, that blueberries often cause perceivers to undergo colour experiences, or that our concept BLUE is often meaningfully applied, and to good effect, to blueberries. What they doubt is that blueberries are blue in a basic sense, believing instead that blueberries merely have the power to cause perceivers to undergo colour experiences. Insofar as we can explain what basic colours are, blueberries only have this causal role. No feature of blueberries is part of the basic nature of colour or of what constitutes basic colour.
Sure. The relevance of that distinction here, however, escapes me. — Banno
Pain and colour are different. I can hand you the pen, but not the pain. — Banno
Why should there be a singular thing to which the noun "colour" refers, and which must therefore be either in your head or in your hand? — Banno
Yet it is more plausible to believe that it is the addition of a substance that causes the variation. There is no good reason to believe that the variation occurs without the added substance. — jkop
For example, you claim that the colour variation in the dress is caused by the brain. — jkop
A summary of what? The article contains many different sections and summaries, and you picked one that partly (debatable) suits one or two of your single-minded assertions. :roll: — jkop
The “common-sense” naive view truly posits that colors are mind independent properties of objects because when I change the color of my room’s wall and get another bucket of paint with a different color, not a different mental percept. — Richard B
It is strange to ask if mental percept are mind-independent — Richard B
Problem with this is you are no longer talking about mind dependent concepts but mind independent (brain neurons etc I would think you would call mind independent). — Richard B
One of the major problems with color has to do with fitting what we seem to know about colors into what science (not only physics but the science of color vision) tells us about physical bodies and their qualities. It is this problem that historically has led the major physicists who have thought about color, to hold the view that physical objects do not actually have the colors we ordinarily and naturally take objects to possess. Oceans and skies are not blue in the way that we naively think, nor are apples red (nor green). Colors of that kind, it is believed, have no place in the physical account of the world that has developed from the sixteenth century to this century.
Not only does the scientific mainstream tradition conflict with the common-sense understanding of color in this way, but as well, the scientific tradition contains a very counter-intuitive conception of color. There is, to illustrate, the celebrated remark by David Hume:
"Sounds, colors, heat and cold, according to modern philosophy are not qualities in objects, but perceptions in the mind. (Hume 1738: Bk III, part I, Sect. 1, [1911: 177]; Bk I, IV, IV, [1911: 216])"
Physicists who have subscribed to this doctrine include the luminaries: Galileo, Boyle, Descartes, Newton, Thomas Young, Maxwell and Hermann von Helmholtz. Maxwell, for example, wrote:
"It seems almost a truism to say that color is a sensation; and yet Young, by honestly recognizing this elementary truth, established the first consistent theory of color. (Maxwell 1871: 13 [1970: 75])"
This combination of eliminativism—the view that physical objects do not have colors, at least in a crucial sense—and subjectivism—the view that color is a subjective quality—is not merely of historical interest. It is held by many contemporary experts and authorities on color, e.g., Zeki 1983, Land 1983, and Kuehni 1997. Palmer, a leading psychologist and cognitive scientist, writes:
"People universally believe that objects look colored because they are colored, just as we experience them. The sky looks blue because it is blue, grass looks green because it is green, and blood looks red because it is red. As surprising as it may seem, these beliefs are fundamentally mistaken. Neither objects nor lights are actually “colored” in anything like the way we experience them. Rather, color is a psychological property of our visual experiences when we look at objects and lights, not a physical property of those objects or lights. The colors we see are based on physical properties of objects and lights that cause us to see them as colored, to be sure, but these physical properties are different in important ways from the colors we perceive. (Palmer 1999: 95)"
This quote, however, needs unpacking. Palmer is obviously challenging our ordinary common-sense beliefs about colors. Specifically, he is denying that objects and lights have colors in the sense of colors-as-we-experience-them (or colors as we see them), As far as this goes, it is compatible with objects and lights having colors in some other sense, e.g., colors, as defined for scientific purposes. Secondly, he is saying that color (i.e., color-as-we-experience it) is a psychological property, which in turn, might be interpreted in different ways.
What's your view of that? — frank
You're saying that when I experience black, I'm experiencing an example of black. Everybody who has ever experienced seeing black has had their turn with this same thing: black percept. Right? It's something that transcends the individual? — frank
But I have been at pains to point out that colour is not mind-independent; nor is it all in the mind. — Banno
I've mentioned the implication that when you and I talk about something's being red, we would be talking about quite different things - you of your percept, and me of mine. — Banno
But moreover, if "red" refers to something purely mental, how could you be sure that you are using the word correctly? How could you ensure that your use of "red" now matched your use of "red" previously? How could you be sure that your memory is not deceiving you, and what you are now calling "red" is what you previously called "green"? — Banno
You are seeing it wrong. — Lionino
Fair enough, but that sound less like philosophy and more just basic neuroscience and physics. — Hanover
We think of colour as being a fundamental property of objects in life: green trees, blue sky, red apples. But that’s not how it works.
“What colour is not is part of our world,” says neuroscientist Beau Lotto. “Every colour that people see is actually inside their head … and the stimulus of colour, of course, is light.”
As light pours down on us from the sun, or from a lightbulb in our home, objects and surfaces absorb some wavelengths of light and reflect others. “The ones that are reflected then land onto our retina,” says Lotto. There, those reflected wavelengths are transformed into electrical signals to be interpreted by our brain.
So we don’t really “see” colour, but reflected light, as interpreted in our brain. “It’s a useful perception of our world, but it’s not an accurate perception of our world,” says Lotto.
Ugh... the "some see white, others see black" is philosophical spaghetti. — frank
If you're going open the door to questioning inherent beliefs, then why arbitrarily limit it? — Hanover
If it's 1, then color language can refer to both subjective and objective accounts. — frank
He or she is saying that since this uncertainty exists, we have to conclude that color experiences are unique to each individual. — frank
There is a group of views about color, which come under one or all of the labels, Color Irrealism, Color Eliminativism, Color Fictionalism. These titles are a little misleading, since some theorists also talk of there being colors in the sense of being dispositions to cause experiences of a characteristic type, and/or being (attributes in/of) sensations. Following our earlier discussion, in section 1.2, we may take it that what the color-Eliminativist is denying is that material objects and lights have colors of a certain kind: colors that we ordinarily and unreflectingly take the bodies to have.
...
Color Primitivist Realism is the view that there are in nature colors, as ordinarily understood, i.e., colors are simple intrinsic, non-relational, non-reducible, qualitative properties. They are qualitative features of the sort that stand in the characteristic relations of similarity and difference that mark the colors; they are not micro-structural properties or reflectances, or anything of the sort.
'Red' refers to an object's disposition to cause certain colour experiences. — jkop
The words "white and gold" and "blue and black" are referring to both, the light being emitted by the dress and perceived by the viewer. — creativesoul
"Visual percepts" is again hollow. It means the patient discerned shapes. "Visual percepts" is hypostatisation. — Banno
That sometimes one person sees blue where the other sees gold does not change this. — Banno
What he doesn't understand: you can't have a first premise (reality exists) and then from this premise prove that the premise is wrong. That's not a valid argument. — Gregory