More information and explanation [aka 'increasing the word count']
I specified exactly what a sentential logic interpretation is. To add to that, here is what is meant by "true (or false) per an interpretation" or "true (or false) in an interpretation":
First we define 'is a sentence' by induction:
Every sentence letter is a sentence (drop parentheses when not needed):
If P is a sentence, then ~P is a sentence.
If P and Q are sentences, then (P & Q) is a sentence.
If P and Q are sentences, then (P v Q) is a sentence.
If P and Q are sentences, then (P -> Q) is a sentence.
If P and Q are sentences, then (P <-> Q) is a sentence.
It is in "stages" ('P' and 'Q' here range over sentences):
Then, an interpretation assigns a truth value to each sentence letter. So a sentence letter alone has, per that interpretation, the truth value assigned by that interpretation ('P' and 'Q' here range over sentences):
If P is just a sentence letter, then P is true per the interpretation if the interpretation assigns true to P; otherwise P is false per the interpretation.
~P is true per the interpretation if P is false per the interpretation; ~P is false per the interpretation otherwise.
P & Q is true per the interpretation if both P and Q are true per the interpretation; P & Q is false per the interpretation otherwise.
P v Q is true per the interpretation if at least one of P or Q is true per the interpretation; P v Q is false per the interpretation otherwise.
P -> Q is true per the interpretation if either P is false per the interpretation or Q is true per the interpretation; P -> Q is false per the interpretation otherwise.
P -> Q is true per the interpretation if either both P and Q are true per the interpretation or both P and Q are false per the interpretation; P <-> Q is false per the interpretation otherwise.
An example:
(P -> Q) v (R & Q)
Suppose the interpretation is:
P ... true
Q ... true
R ... false.
Then:
P -> Q is true per the interpretation
R & Q is false per the interpretation
so, abracadabra, voila, and drumroll please ...
(P -> Q) v (R & Q) is true per the interpretation
Similarly, in stages like that, for arbitrarily complicated sentences.
That's what is meant by 'true (or false) per an interpretation' or 'true (or false) in an interpretation'.
/
Various definitions we've seen mention things like 'cases', 'circumstances'.
Those can be taken to mean 'interpretations'.
And sometimes 'possible' and 'impossible' are used.
Those can be taken to mean 'true in at least one interpretation' and 'true in no interpretation', respectively.
/
This is what I say is the common interpretation of your sources on validity:
1. Assume all the premises are true
2. See if it is inferentially possible to make the conclusion false, given the true premises
3. If it is not possible, then the argument is valid — Leontiskos
Whatever is meant by "See if it is inferentially possible to make the conclusion false, given the true premises", here instead is one* common method for checking for the validity of a sentence in sentential logic. *There are some more efficient ways, but they are harder to specify in a post.
Df. An argument is valid if and only if there is no interpretation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion is false:
To check for the validity of an argument (with finitely many premises):
1. Write the conjunction of the premises. Follow that with '->'. Follow that with the conclusion.
2. Write the truth table for the above formed sentence.
2. If there is a row in which the antecedent is true and the conclusion is false, then the argument is invalid, and it is valid otherwise.
Indeed, this highlights a connection between arguments and conditionals.
No "assuming". No seeing "if it is inferentially possible to make the conclusion false, given the true premises" whatever that means. No messing with the modality of possibility. Indeed, just a simple, utterly clear, step by step mechanical method.
Note: There is no mechanical procedure to check for the validity of arbitrary formulas of predicate logic.
/
I mentioned that I don't mention 'inconsistency' when defining 'valid argument'. There is good reason for that, which is:
The notion of consistency requires the notion of deducibility and deducibility is a whole subject in itself.
Df. A set of sentences is consistent if and only if there is no deduction of a contradiction from the set.
But that requires having a deduction system from which to define 'is a deduction'.
But we may wish to consider validity without having first done all stuff we have to do to set up a deduction system, which we can do later.
Indeed, often textbooks in logic devote early chapters to semantics (truth/falsehood, interpretation, entailment, validity, etc.) and then separate chapters to deduction. And then, chapters in which we prove meta-theorems about the connection between semantics and deduction. Such, as I recently mentioned, the central theorems of soundness and completeness. That is a conceptually elegant approach. Indeed, this engenders two branches of study in logic: model theory (interpretations) and proof theory (deductions).
/
Another definition of 'valid argument' to add to the list:
"it is impossible that all the premises should be true and the conclusion false" (Intermediate Logic - Bostock)