• What does Quine mean by Inscrutability of Reference
    It's not a slur because...Moliere

    No, it's a slur. Get real, Moliere. :roll:
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    - It strikes me as accurate. A handful of 20th century logicians think up a very new (and as it turns out, very bad) way of approaching existence, and they declare that anyone who thinks otherwise is an untouchable. So it is a strange form of imperialism.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    As Bunge himself says:Arcane Sandwich

    Hence the atheist will have to propose serious arguments against it [Anselm's argument] instead of the sophistry of the logical imperialist. (...) In short, Anselm was far less wrong than his modern critics would have it. — Bunge (2012: 175)

    That sort of "logical imperialist sophistry" is pretty common here on TPF, as the thread on Anselm's proof shows.
  • What does Quine mean by Inscrutability of Reference
    But problems happen when folk think they can prove that their sky daddy exists using the ontological argument, and so that anyone who says otherwise is anathema.Banno

    Or does the problem occur when atheist trolls can't manage to refute an argument, so anyone who uses it is anathema? They resort to slurs like "sky daddy" because they are too dumb to mount a coherent argument.

    But Dawkins and his ilk are in their 80's and the irrational fad has passed. Once the hangers-on die out completely it will be back to inter-religious dialogue, particularly with the burgeoning forms of neo-paganism.
  • Laclau's Theory of Populism
    I’m referring to a situation where a system of values becomes the foundation for large-scale political struggle.Number2018

    I don't see why the "digital medium" gives every system of values a populist mode of expression. For example, when the incumbent uses that same digital media to promote the reigning values, what is at stake is not poplism.

    Laclau’s concept of the empty signifier refers to a vague and transient, yet potent and dynamic, sense of solidarity.Number2018

    Okay.

    MAGA is not just about concentrating executive power. But the logic behind its implementation takes on a dynamic of its own, one that eludes pre-existing discursive or ideological frameworks. Take, for example, the latest executive orders on tariffs that the Trump administration is set to impose on Canada and Mexico.Number2018

    Trump has touted tariffs for a long time, so I don't see this as "the logic taking on a dynamic of its own." Tariffs are basically a simplistic approach to the "America first" mentality that is inevitably bound up with MAGA.

    If populism requires a shift from pre-election promises to post-election actions, then it's not so clear that it fits Trump, because he has a surprising tendency to fulfill his promises. Or at least to try. And maybe that's a problem with Laclau: populism can function fine even when the signifier is not empty. Sometimes the people know what they want, and there isn't a great deal of ambiguity in the signifier. Sometimes the desired change has a clear direction.
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    Many have been especially interested in the proof itself and section 2. Such people may be interested in another paper of Klima's where he spends much more time on objections to the argument. That paper may be an alternative version of the book chapter of the OP, and it uses a slightly different formalization of Anselm's proof:

    "Anselm’s Proof for God’s Existence in the Proslogion," by Gyula Klima
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    - I agree that Musk does not have the authority to abolish USAID, but the video from Rubio makes it fairly clear that USAID has not been abolished. And "notice" is a fair bit different than "approval." We can agree that it was in violation of the requirement for "substantive rationale," which my link speaks to in detail. :up:
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    - Well, you're always welcome to produce some arguments or some sources. It would be especially helpful if you produced support for your views that appointing Rubio administrator of the USAID was illegal, or that removing an IG without congressional approval was illegal. Those are pretty big claims, and they formed the backbone of your consternation. I would suggest doing some research before making accusations like that. I think Australians would be surprised at how different the Overton window is in the U.S. as compared with Australia.

    Like many Americans, I believe we need to make cuts to address the national debt. I don't expect such cuts will come easy.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    Biden had more popular votes than Trump and a bigger mandateBC

    There you go, and you've unwittingly admitted that Trump has a mandate. :up:
    The point here is that trimming government agencies is not an undemocratic move by a rogue Musk.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    But Rubio was confirmed as Secretary of State.Wayfarer

    So what? Is there some reason you think Rubio cannot serve as both? Or are you concerned about the rumor that USAID will be merged? Note that USAID is already closely tied to the Secretary of State:

    As an official component of U.S. foreign policy, USAID operates subject to the guidance of the president, secretary of state, and the National Security Council.USAID | Wikipedia

    And you're OK with that?Wayfarer

    I think you've been caught up in the sensationalism. From what I have seen Musk did not do anything without approval from the White House. I mean, what is the objection, here? That USAID has "some of the most sensitive offices in the government"? That doesn't seem true. That Musk had a team of young techies helping him? What's wrong with that? And sure, I wish Musk wouldn't talk that way about the wood-chipper, but that's Musk. He's always been like that. And what if it's as bad as he says? I am seeing a lot of hearsay online intended to whip people up into a frenzy.

    So, your opinion piece says one thingWayfarer

    It's not an opinion piece, it's from an American legal scholar. You merely linked to a Google search. Do you have a concrete source for your view? Namely for your claim that the act of firing an inspector general requires congressional approval?

    Right - cuts are perfectly understandable. Had the debate been had, USAID been informed that it was to be merged with State, staff told that it was happened and had a chance to respond and wind up operations, it wouldn't be a story, and I wouldn't be complaining about it.Wayfarer

    Fair enough, but it would probably still be a story.

    And the whole point of Inspectors General is that they're not political appointeesWayfarer

    I'm not sure what that's supposed to mean. The President can remove IGs. Their "point" is not to be above the head executive.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    - That's good to hear, jgill. :up:
    My father has a similar story with cancer and Medicare.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    Two of my grandchildren are American. Their father is a dual citizen.Wayfarer

    Okay, fair enough.

    An illegal appointment.Wayfarer

    Except that's not true at all. The President appoints the administrator of USAID (and other executive agencies). The Senate approves the appointment. And of course it has not been dissolved.

    Or does it? Trump summarily fired a dozen Inspectors general 10 days ago. That also was illegal as each act requires approval by Congress and 30 days notice.Wayfarer

    Are you just making things up? USAID is a government agency of the executive branch, and like other executive agencies was originally created by Congress. It is in no way illegal for the President to fire and replace officials in executive agencies (link).

    So, question: do you support the right of Trump to act illegally in such cases, and the right of the Executive to ignore Congress and established law?Wayfarer

    It sounds like you don't understand the U.S. government very well. The Democrats have pushed for a strong executive branch over time, in order to circumvent the gridlock that our system is designed to produce (especially in the legislative and judicial branches). Trump has inherited that strong executive branch, and is using it.

    Put yourself in the position of a USAID stafferWayfarer

    Cuts are cuts. If the American people didn't want cuts they shouldn't have asked for them. It's not like you make cuts without cutting jobs, and in many cases it seems that benefit packages have been provided, or offered for those who wish to leave. The goal is to move a significant percentage of the government workforce into the private sector.
  • The Musk Plutocracy


    I'm sort of surprised to see Australians with a bookmark in the New York Times expressing such strong opinions on U.S. politics. If I read a single news outlet from Australia and opined strongly on Australian policies, how would I be viewed?

    The Trump-Musk team is inevitably a brake-gas team, and even your NYT article says that Trump has pumped the brakes at times (Trump himself has said that Musk requires authorization from the White House for any moves he makes in this capacity). But given that the mainstream media hates Musk for helping Trump get re-elected, and that anyone who makes cuts is going to be demonized, these sorts of stories are very much to be expected. No agency is going to take a cut laying down, and that's why Musk may be just the right man for the job, aggressive as he is. The Pew Research Center reports fairly often on the debt, and recently had a piece on the federal workforce.

    There is a basic tendency among citizens to say they want the deficit addressed, but then to object whenever anything gets cut. Or to say they want illegal immigrants deported, but then to object whenever illegal immigrants are deported.

    Regarding USAID, here is Senator Rubio, who is now the acting head of USAID and is an elected official:



    As Rubio says, "There are a lot of functions of the USAID that are going to continue, that are going to be part of American foreign policy." So the idea that everything within USAID is being cut seems like scare-mongering. Here is the White House Press Secretary on the strange USAID expenditures. As I understand it, the argument from the right is that USAID was created to provide aid and promote U.S. interests abroad, and it is now largely failing in that charter due to ideological capture. It is not being shut down but it is being reorganized to accomplish its purpose.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    In what sense, derives from a mandate?Wayfarer

    One of Trump's campaign promises was to address the federal debt. Musk and others are the ones he put on that job. There is no such thing as an elected debt-reducer. Musk represents Trump, and the President has more control over the federal bureaucracy than any other individual.

    And sure, Congress is the ideal party to address federal debt, but they have shown themselves unable to do so for a long time now. It's really not that strange to see a president who was elected in part because of his promise to reduce the debt appoint an official to reduce the debt.

    I don't think the average citizen is concerned that Musk is trying to address the debt. I think they are grateful that someone is finally doing what should have been done decades ago. The problem of the federal debt is one of the least partisan issues. And those who are making cuts are basically guaranteed to make certain groups angry, namely the groups who are benefitting from the money that needs to be cut.

    The real wonder here is that Trump is giving Musk so much authority. That's surprising, but also hopeful. Musk has even expressed a willingness to make cuts to defense spending (which is where it would really count), but it is less likely that he will be allowed to touch that. Even Bernie Sanders was pretty happy about that idea.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    But, remember, this guy has never been elected to any public office.Wayfarer

    "Unelected bureaucrat is appointed by President to cut costs associated with bureaucratic bloat."

    As has been pointed out, Musk is the democratic bureaucrat, given that his job derives from a mandate. So if we are using principles of democracy to calculate whether the bureaucracy that Musk represents or the bureaucracy that Musk opposes should win out, obviously the bureaucracy that Musk represents wins out. Musk's job is to address the budget problem, and this is something the citizens of the U.S. have been desiring for decades. The U.S. debt is $36.4 trillion and counting.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    Does it matter if Jesus claimed that he was God? My contention is that he could be God even if he never claimed such a thing.Arcane Sandwich

    It is logically possible, but it doesn't surprise me that no one goes around arguing that Jesus was God even though he never claimed to be God. Basically, if Jesus and the documentary evidence we now possess are not self-consciously presenting evidence for Jesus' divinity, then the whole point is moot. If that is not in place then one could as easily claim that Benjamin Franklin was the Son of God as Jesus.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    - When you say "arguments" you presumably mean formal arguments, and on that reading the answer is that historical arguments are more difficult to formalize. I don't find arguments for Jesus' divinity to be at all lacking. In fact I see them more often, probably because it is usually admitted that Jesus is a historical figure, and because the question of whether Jesus claimed to be God usually precedes the question of whether God exists. This is because, if Jesus claimed to be God, then the atheist has a new case to consider, whereas if he did not claim to be God, then everyone is off the hook. And given the Christological theology that has become popular especially since Barth, leading with Jesus has become very common. This is particularly true in a secular age which is more opposed to traditional notions of God.

    (Here is an example of just such an article published today.)
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God


    Let me refine the argument I gave:

    If a logical form need not be isolated, then it "behaves in precisely the same manner" (and therefore does not have a different logical structure...).

    That's the key point, namely:

    Put it this way: when someone gives a modus ponens you don't have to check with them first, to make sure that p!=q. It makes no difference at all. There is no caveat when it comes to modus ponens, no condition where if p=q the rule fails.Leontiskos

    Call this MP1:

    1. p → q
    2. p
    3. ∴ q

    And this MP2:

    1. p → p
    2. p
    3. ∴ p


    If MP2 behaved differently than MP1 (in a relevant logical sense), then MP2 would need to be isolated from MP1. In that case every time someone offered up a modus ponens we would need verify whether we are talking about MP1 or MP2. But we don't. Because nothing is at stake. They behave in the same manner (because modus ponens doesn't care whether the first premise is tautological). It makes no difference. And therefore they have the same structure. We don't say that things which do not need to be differentiated have a different structure. MP2 is merely a particular kind of modus ponens. For the formalist it is no more or less modus ponens than any other modus ponens. It is not anything other than modus ponens (and therefore has no different inferential structure).

    The difference between MP1 and MP2 is metalogical, and one of course needs to move into the meta-language if they want to understand what an argument really is.

    (We actually have a lot of threads on these sorts of topics, so I don't want belabor this for too long.)
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    Not quite, because the difference between p → p and p → q affects their truth values.Arcane Sandwich

    It is merely a subset of the truth table where p!=q. The truth values are no different. Or in other words, at no point would someone become alarmed upon learning that p=q. It makes no difference at all. Nothing that was valid where p!=q will become invalid where p=q. This is why representing them with the same letter or a different letter makes no difference at all.

    That's not what I claim. Formally they have different structures, not poetically.Arcane Sandwich

    If two things behave in precisely the same manner, then they do not have two different logical structures. The two modus ponens "arguments" under scrutiny behave in precisely the same manner; therefore they do not have two different logical structures (on the formalist's understanding).

    Put it this way: when someone gives a modus ponens you don't have to check with them first, to make sure that p!=q. It makes no difference at all. There is no caveat when it comes to modus ponens, no condition where if p=q the rule fails.

    The same goes for the notion of degeneracy. It only makes sense outside of logic, not within it.Arcane Sandwich

    You say that but then you want to make an ad hoc distinction between the "structure" of different modus ponens "arguments," so I still have hope for you. :wink:
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    There's two types of structures in logic: the structure of arguments, and the structure of propositions. Two arguments can have the same structure (i.e., both of them are modus ponens) while having propositions with different structures (i.e., p → q instead of p → p).Arcane Sandwich

    That's an interesting account, but I don't know of any rule of logic which requires that a modus ponens where p=q magically has a different structure. The validity rules are all the same, so it's not clear what it would even mean to claim that it has a different structure. If you're all about formalism, then the structure is exactly the same.

    When I say that some arguments are good and that some of them are bad, I'm speaking poetically. In other words, I'm being rhetorical, not logical. I don't dismiss rhetoric, I simply declare that being persuasive and compelling are within its province, instead of being qualities of the formal science that we call logic.Arcane Sandwich

    Then you have no reason to claim that the modus ponens where p=q has a different structure, apart from poetry. "Poetically they have a different structure, but formally they do not."

    On my view if someone cannot see that this is a degenerate case of modus ponens, then they haven't grasped the raison d'être of logic:

    1. p → p
    2. p
    3. ∴ p

    ...and of course someone who limits themselves to "formalisms" cannot admit the notion of a degenerate case.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    They have different structures. "If p, then p" is not the same structure as "If p, then q".Arcane Sandwich

    Same structure:

    p: God exists
    q: God exists

    1. p → q
    2. p
    3. ∴ q

    (The structure is modus ponens, and you yourself claimed that 1-2-3 is a modus ponens.)

    But I wouldn't endorse that argument myself, because it's easily refutable. To speak poetically for a moment, it's not a good argument, even though it's both valid and sound.Arcane Sandwich

    But just a few minutes ago you said, "An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it." Now you want to say that some sound arguments are good and some sound arguments are bad. So clearly there is something more to it.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    There's nothing "degenerate" about such cases. That notion has no place in a formal science such as logic.Arcane Sandwich

    <Sure it does>. And when Frege first tried to introduce the material conditional he was resisted for decades for this very reason.

    Which is why the arguments in the OP, while being modus ponens, do not have the same structure as the one in your example. Because in your example, the conditional has the form "if p, then p", while the conditionals in the arguments of the OP have this other structure: "if p, then q".Arcane Sandwich

    But you yourself said that it is a "perfectly valid modus ponens." So what's the problem? What's the difference between a modus ponens where p=q and a modus ponens where p!=q? It seems that on your view there can be no significant distinction between the two modus ponens. You said, "An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it. Logic is a science (a formal science, just like mathematics)."

    It's not a sound argument, at least not to my atheist eyes. It is valid, however. Just not sound.Arcane Sandwich

    Yes: you think 4-5-6 is the sound argument, right?
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    I can't see how we could know who the name refers to if we didn't know at least one of the following that Socrates is purported to be; that is 'the teacher of Plato', 'the agora gadfly' 'the man charged with corrupting the youth of Athens and condemned to drink hemlock' and so on.

    Of course if someone is familiar with those descriptions the proper name 'Socrates' "functions correctly", but for someone who doesn't I can't see how it functions at all.
    Janus

    Yes, I agree. I had a conversation with Banno on this topic awhile back, such as <here>. One example exchange from that thread:

    A novice who asks "Who is Thales?" does not have at hand a description of Thales, and yet they are asking about Thales.Banno

    But the novice does have a description of 'Thales'. If they had no description they would not be able to ask the question. Specifically, if they did not believe that 'Thales' described an ancient philosopher, they would not be able to ask the question. "Thales was an ancient philosopher" is a description, as is (1).

    Suppose, ex hypothesi, that the novice has no description of 'Thales'. If this were so, then what in the world do you propose they would be asking about when they ask about 'Thales'? In that case they could not be asking about a man, because if they were asking about a man then 'Thales' would have a description. They could not be asking about a previously existing thing, because if they were asking about a previously existing thing then they would have a description. They could not be asking about a name from their textbook, because if they were asking about a name from their textbook then they would have a description, etc.

    So again, you are contradicting yourself in simultaneously holding that the novice has no description of 'Thales' and nevertheless uses the name in a meaningful sense.
    Leontiskos

    What's interesting is that if you start with Russell's (bad) theory, it is very hard to extricate yourself. You end up compulsively concerned with the question concerning a verifiable "definite description."
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    Both premises can be true, but they can't both be false. Only one of them can be false.Arcane Sandwich

    Sure, if you rely on the degenerate cases of the material conditional, where a false antecedent or a true consequent guarantees a true conditional. But I think I spoke to that.

    What can I say? I don't share your notion of a "substantial" argument. An argument is either sound or unsound. There's nothing more to it. Logic is a science (a formal science, just like mathematics). It has nothing to do with persuasiveness, just as algebra or geometry have nothing to do with persuasiveness.Arcane Sandwich

    Let me show why I disagree.

    Suppose I say that God exists, and you tell me that I've made an assertion rather than an argument. So I give what you view as an "argument":

    1. If God exists, then God exists
    2. God exists
    3. Therefore, God exists

    Now apparently this is an argument, which is entirely different from an assertion. Since I have given an argument, you have the burden of proof in addressing the argument. You might say, "God does not exist," and I might say, "That's an assertion, not an argument." So you comply:

    4. If God does not exist, then God does not exist
    5. God does not exist
    6. Therefore, God does not exist

    We could do that for eternity, and on my view we are neither arguing nor giving arguments, whereas on your view we are (and I have encountered people who literally did this).

    Aristotle tells us that arguments move from premises that are better-known to conclusions that are lesser-known. If it doesn't do that, it isn't an argument. Note too that "better-known" and "lesser-known" can easily be indexed to persons, but that they are also indexed to communities, which is why not all sound arguments for the same conclusion are equal. In fact 1-2-3 is a sound "argument," but I would contend that it is not a real argument at all.

    An since an argument is the same thing as a proof, it follows that I already gave two proofs in the OP.Arcane Sandwich

    Well if you "spoke" the proofs then you have the basic burden of proof, no? Your Wikipedia article says that the one who speaks has the burden.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    Due to how the burden of proof works, I don't need to prove a negativeArcane Sandwich

    According to your Wikipedia article you have the burden of proof, for you are the one who spoke.

    Or rather, you have simulated a scenario in which someone gives a very opaque argument (FTI), and then you "denied" part of FTI (to quote Wikipedia), so for Wikipedia whoever spoke FTI has the initial burden of proof. So who spoke FTI? No one at all, it seems. It is part of an OP that offers no real argument, and which does not accept the burden of proof for what it claims.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    You lost me here. Can you please clarify what you mean by that?Arcane Sandwich

    For example, you said, "if FTI1 is true, then FTI2 must necessarily be false." Why? Why can't both premises be true?

    I'm not sure I follow. The formal structure of that argument is the following one:

    1) If p, then q.
    2) p.
    3) so, q.

    If (1) is false, then (2) is true, and if (1) is true, then (2) is false.
    Arcane Sandwich

    Okay sure, if you are appealing to the "degenerate cases" of the material conditional then I agree that the former Muslim cannot deny that God exists without affirming that, "If God exists, then God is identical to Jesus," at least if he is consistent. But I'm not sure how useful arguments that depend on such degenerate cases are.

    Here you might be right, but only in the sense that both arguments might be valid and yet unsound.Arcane Sandwich

    But isn't that precisely what you meant when you spoke about the possibility of "rejecting both arguments at the same time"?

    If so, then that's a powerful reason for rejecting both arguments.Arcane Sandwich

    Why think that?

    However, it's still the case that if one of the conclusions is true, then the other one is false, and vice-versa.Arcane Sandwich

    Correct.

    The concept of soundness (and unsoundness) applies only to arguments, not to propositions (premises and conclusions), just as the concept of validity (or lack of thereof) only applies to arguments, not to propositions. A proposition (being a premise or a conclusion) can only be true or false. That is at least the modern understanding of such notions.Arcane Sandwich

    On the contrary, a sound conclusion is the conclusion of a sound argument. And as I said, "if either conclusion is sound then both first-premises must be true" (given material conditionals).

    This is indeed an argumentArcane Sandwich

    It is not an argument in any substantial sense, and the "arguments" of the OP are similarly insubstantial. Namely, there is nothing persuasive or compelling about them. For example, I could write an OP:

    1. If the moon is made of cheese, then pelicans are vegans
    2. The moon is made of cheese
    3. Therefore, pelicans are vegans

    I might follow this with, "Options for resisting the argument." But there is no argument to resist, not in any substantial sense. The person making the argument has the burden of proof in showing the argument to be persuasive or compelling, and mere validity does not succeed in doing this. (Formalizations such as this are only valid consequences, not cases of true inference.)

    So rather than give a substantial argument, you've asked TPF users to give substantial arguments against at least one of four propositions (namely, the premises). It's a bit like saying, "I think X. Prove me wrong."

    (I would grant that ATI is closer to a substantial argument than FTI, since FTI1 is entirely opaque.)
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    - That gets into the questions similar to <this thread>. My point wasn't to claim that both first premises are false. That cannot be done if we are using material conditionals. Note, though, that if we are talking about material conditionals, then if either conclusion is sound then both first-premises must be true.
  • Arguments for and against the identification of Jesus with God
    Due to the rules that govern the truth table for conditional statements, it's not possible to deny both premises (of either argument) at the same time. For example, if FTI1 is true, then FTI2 must necessarily be false, and vice-versa. Likewise, if ATI1 is true, then ATI2 must be necessarily false, and vice-versa.Arcane Sandwich

    I think was correct the first time (in challenging some of these claims). Let me just poke a few holes:

    ...it's not possible to deny both premises (of either argument) at the same time. For example, if FTI1 is true, then FTI2 must necessarily be false, and vice-versa.Arcane Sandwich

    First, if it is not possible to deny both premises, then it would follow that if one is false, then the other must necessarily be true. Your opposite claim simply does not follow.

    (FTI1) If God exists, then God is identical to Jesus.
    (FTI2) God exists.
    (FTI3) So, God is identical to Jesus.
    Arcane Sandwich

    To give a counterexample, consider a Muslim who became an atheist. They deny (1) and (2). So it is very clearly possible to deny both premises.

    Conversely, it's not possible to reject both arguments at the same time. If you reject one of them, then that means that you accept the other oneArcane Sandwich

    This too looks to be false. The conclusions are contradictories, but that does not entail that the arguments are "contradictories" (so to speak). The believing Muslim is someone who rejects both arguments.

    (Beyond that, I wouldn't count the formalizations of the OP as arguments, given that their premises are neither intuitive nor defended.)
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    - Because I am covering multiple posts of yours. Count Timothy already pressed your early, question-begging posts into the arguments that appeared in the later posts (although those arguments are still fairly thin).
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    Having read through Roark's paper and Klima's response to Roark, I think Klima successfully defends his positions. Let's look at the facet that was brought up:

    Arguably, the argument simply proves that the atheist cannot deny God (i.e. the being greater than which no being can be thought) without affirming a contradiction.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Here is Roark's explicit claim:

    The upshot of all of this is the following: in order simultaneously to render the sufficiency claim in the third premise plausible and to accommodate (γ), the predicate ‘Ix’ must also be interpreted as including a modal-pistic component: ‘x can be thought to exist only in the intellect’. One obvious consequence of this reinterpretation is the fact that the conclusion of the argument is not that God exists in reality, but rather that one cannot think God to exist only in the intellect.Tony Roark, Conceptual Closure in Anselm's Proof, 8

    Note that Roark wants to reinterpret Ix for two reasons: both because he thinks validity requires that Ix be pistic, and because Ix introduces conceptual closure.

    Klima's first point is that Ix is already pistic:

    The original interpretation of the predicate ‘I( )’ in the reconstruction was ‘( ) is only in the intellect’, which I expounded further by saying that an x is only in the intellect in this sense if and only if x is thought of, but does not exist in reality. So, this predicate does contain a certain ‘pistic component’, namely, the component that x is thought of, which of course entails the ‘modal-pistic component’ that x can be thought of. Now, if g is only in the intellect in this sense, then it seems clear that something greater than g can be thought of in the sense of Roark’s interpretation (γ) by a thinking subject S who assumes premise (2). For S, by virtue of assuming premise (2), is thinking that g is in the intellect and does not exist in reality. Therefore, S can obviously think of something with ‘a greater cardinality’, whether g itself or anything else, by simply thinking, or counterfactually assuming, that that thing does exist in reality.Klima, Conceptual closure in Anselm’s proof: reply to Tony Roark, 132

    But this does not foreclose Roark's claim that the conclusion of Klima's formulation of Anselm's argument ought to itself be pistic. Klima responds to this idea as follows:

    Accordingly, the argument does have to prove its conclusion for any thinking subject S, provided S assumes all the premises in the required senses, interpreting the phrase ‘x can be thought to be greater than y’ as expounded by Roark. The important point here is that what S has to conclude on the basis of the premises thus interpreted is not that he simply cannot think that g exists only in the intellect, but that it is not true that g exists only in the intellect, from which he further has to conclude that, since g is in the intellect and not only in the intellect, g also has to exist in reality.

    To be sure, an external observer E, listening to the reasoning of S, can describe what she observes by saying that S had to conclude that g exists because S cannot consistently think that g does not exist. And E may further claim that she is not thus committed to accepting S’s conclusion, for S can plausibly argue only for himself, since he is the one who makes the comparisons of his own thought objects regarding their assumed cardinalities within his own ‘modal-pistic’ context.

    But then, this result seems to make perfect sense in the larger context of the paper. After all, my main argument in the paper is that Anselm’s argument can genuinely work only for those who are willing to make constitutive reference to God. But for them it is indeed an inevitable conclusion that they cannot consistently think of God and think that he does not exist. So they have to conclude without any pistic-modal component in their conclusion that God exists.
    Klima, Conceptual closure in Anselm’s proof: reply to Tony Roark, 132-3

    To be clear, Roark is claiming that Ix should be reinterpreted as I2x:

    • I(): "() is only in the intellect"
    • I2(): "() can be thought to exist only in the intellect"

    ...and from I2x Roark thinks the conclusion should be changed to, "One cannot think God to exist only in the intellect."

    Klima's point, quoted above, is that Ix always meant, "x is thought of, but does not exist." Thus the conclusion of the reductio for the one thus thinking of x is that x must exist, not that one cannot think x to exist only in the intellect.

    But Klima admits that Ix brings with it "conceptual closure" on account of the non-existence claim that it includes. To Roark's conceptual closure objection, Klima simply notes that global solutions to semantic or conceptual closure, such as Tarski's or Roark's, are overkill. He provides an alternative local solution where one can reject the paradoxes of conceptual closure (such as Modest) without rejecting the non-paradoxes of conceptual closure (such as Anselm's argument).

    (Of course, strictly speaking Klima addresses the Modest paradox without arguing whether or not it is truly analogous to the Liar.)

    ---

    If we think about the importance of parasitic reference for dialogue, and then we think about the tendency of modern philosophy and logic towards a self-referential, closed system which is quasi-solipsistic, then I think it becomes plausible that the notion of parasitic reference could breathe life into the modern paradigm, opening it up to encounters with other forms of thought. This is because parasitic reference provides a principled way to speak about that which is not yet understood, and in this way erects bridges between interlocutors. On the Quinian conception there is a fairly dire absence of such bridges (even the point that, for example, Quinians are unable to make sense of questions regarding quantifier variance as representing substantive disagreements).
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    I should have written the last words of the sentnece differently and added something like the underlined: "Looking at the actual conditions in, and nature of, our world and viewed through the lens of the human notion of goodness and justice an omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent creator seems to be untenable".

    I don't agree that the notions of omniscience, omnipotence and omnibenevolence are logically incompatible per se.
    Janus

    Okay, I see what you are saying. Thanks for clarifying.

    ---

    An immediate consequence for Anselm's is that what is in his understanding is an idea, and thereby cannot exist in reality - is not any kind of thing at all.tim wood

    See the section of my post from the first page beginning, "We actually saw this play out two days ago in the midst of a discussion on Mario Bunge..."

    ---

    However, these are also distinctions made throughout philosophy, and all the time in everyday language.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yes, and this is one of the reasons Klima gives for refusing a global ban on causal closure, for it would ban existence predications.

    Ok, so why do you think [...] ...implies anything to the contrary?Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yep. :up:
    @Banno keeps asserting things without argument.

    ---

    The first says that Kripke does not think a description is needed in order to fix a referent. The second, that Kripke thinks the speaker has at hand a description in order to fix the referent.Banno

    I think you are getting hung up on the word "description," and trying to make it a technical term. Here is Klima's quote in context:

    [The intentional theory of reference] agrees with the recent “historical explanation”19—as opposed to the Russellian—theory of reference on the fundamental insight that speakers may successfully refer to objects by descriptions that do not apply to these objects. For Saul Kripke this indicates that speaker’s reference may diverge from semantic reference. In the Kripkean framework, however, it is also assumed that the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies his description.20 On the intentional theory not even this is always required.

    20 “So, we may tentatively define the speaker’s referent of a designator to be that object which the speaker wishes to talk about, on a given occasion, and believes fulfils the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator.” Kripke, S. 1991, p.173.
    Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 4

    Klima is explicit that Kripke's theory differs from Russell's descriptive theory. Now Kripke says that the speaker "believes [the referent] fulfills the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator," and Klima interprets this as saying, "that the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies his description."

    • "[The speaker] believes [the referent] fulfills the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator" (Kripke)
    • "the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies his description" (Klima's interpretation)

    You are hung up on that word "description," and you want to say that Kripke differs from Russell on descriptions. Sure, but Klima already noted that. "Description" is a common word. Klima is quite reasonably reading "designator" as a description, given the belief about the semantic referent condition.

    So using Kripke's own example that Klima picks up, consider the referent, "Her husband," in the sentence, "Her husband is kind to her." For Kripke the speaker must believe that the man fulfills the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator, "Her husband." For Kripke, even though he is mistaken, his reference succeeds in virtue of his belief. Klima riffs on that very same example and shows how one can use parasitic reference even without the belief that Kripke requires. If Klima can say, "'Her husband' happens to be her kind boss," (or Roark can say, "The most significant British composer in history is a hack"), without involving the belief that Kripke claims is required, then obviously the theory of reference is different from Kripke's. And that's the point here: the intentional theory of reference differs from Kripke's theory of reference.
  • What does Quine mean by Inscrutability of Reference
    Must we pretend? Do dogs do not exist outside human linguistic frameworks?Count Timothy von Icarus

    If your philosophy of language forces you to ho and hum and deflect away from questions like "did cockroaches not exist until humans decided to 'count' them as such?" then yes, that seems like a rather major defect.Count Timothy von Icarus

    If you have to affirm nonsense like "fish don't exist," it's a knock against your philosophy. Fish would have existed in Melville's day as both a commonly recognized type of animal and a scientific designation.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Good stuff. :up:
    The absurdity of nominalism can hardly be overestimated. It's high time we stop letting people pass off absurd theories as normal.
  • The Musk Plutocracy
    Is the problem not enough democracy, or too much?Count Timothy von Icarus

    :up:
  • Question for Aristotelians
    Thanks. This is an idea I've been researching, and I would appreciate your
    view of it.
    Wayfarer

    This relates to your recent post as well (), but I am going to place it in this thread. (And I realize Arcane Sandwich will disagree with this.)

    I was listening to an interview with Rachel Coleman on her recent paper, “How is it with the nothing?, Her emphasis is a Thomistic critique of Heidegger. It reminded me of the way that you oppose Scientism or J opposes Frege, and it helped crystallize some of my thoughts on the subject.

    As I see it, the modern period is characteristically domineering rather than receptive. It is a kind of grasping at being God, which is the antithesis of Philippians 2:6. Everything is in our hands; everything is up to us; knowledge is primarily something we do; we are the occupants of the view from nowhere; and making-knowledge is the highest form of knowledge. Now Scientism is a kind of grotesque epitome of this attitude, and one which is widely recognized to be aberrant. But it is only an epitome. That is, the basic mindset is much more widespread than Scientism. For example, if there were a harsh drought then Scientism would be the place where the fire starts. But the drought is a problem even apart from the fire, and it is precisely what gives rise to the fire.

    Now when I see your response to Scientism (or J’s response to Frege), it reminds me of antinatalism as an analogy. On this analogy everyone recognizes that suffering is a problem, and also that antinatalism would technically solve the problem of suffering, but also that antinatalism is a kind of overreaction or over-correction to the problem of suffering. In just the same way I would say that Idealism (a denial of mind-independent reality) is an overreaction or over-correction to Scientism and the surrounding “drought.”

    Now perhaps the most effective response to Scientism has been Heidegger. Heidegger sees that what is ultimately at stake is not a doctrine or theory, but rather a posture, and in particular a posture towards being. But for Catholics Heidegger’s response is flat-footed in its own way, and here I am thinking of Catholics who critically engage Heidegger, such as Cyril O’Regan, John Deely, Ferdinand Ulrich, and to a lesser extent, John Caputo. Essentially the idea is that Heidegger is right to emphasize a receptivity to being and a shedding of that domineering attitude (which comes to a breaking point in Scientism), but that Heidegger’s thought ultimately leads nowhere. It over-corrects into, and over-relies on, nothingness. This is similar to what Coleman’s paper on Ulrich seems to argue (note: I do not have access to the paper itself).

    In any case, what is required is an attitude toward reality that is receptive and not merely domineering and activistic; an attitude that does not pretend that one can exhaust reality but nevertheless recognizes that reality can be truly known. That our interaction with the real is not just running quantifiable scientific experiments on inert matter, but that being nevertheless does possess its own character and subsistence that meets us as a true, mind-independent “interlocutor.”

    The difficulty with over-correction is that it fails to give the devil his due. It fails to see what is right and true in Scientism, or in Frege, and instead wants to fully negate the thought. Instead of looking at the problems that Scientism or Frege address, it is only willing to look at the problem that itself wants to address, and when only one problem is considered the answer will inevitably be one-dimensional, like antinatalism.

    Anyway, those are my thoughts on Scientism.
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    - Well no one seems to want to give an argument for their claims. No one wants to be transparent. So I did the work for you. . But still, no one seems to want to interact with that construal to say whether it is a correct or incorrect construal.

    So if folks want to make assertions against omnipotence, but they won't provide an argument for their assertion, and they won't interact with the argument that I offer them, then there is little more for me to do to help.
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    You and Klima both appear to have read "the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator" as implying the presence of a description. But the phrase is chosen so as to be neutral. The "conditions" can of course as well be those causal conditions that are the basis of Kripke's theory of reference.Banno

    You are falling into yet another ignoratio elenchus, for Klima tells us explicitly that the intentional theory and the causal or historical* theory agree on this (my bolding):

    This theory agrees with the recent “historical explanation”[19]—as opposed to the Russellian—theory of reference on the fundamental insight that speakers may successfully refer to objects by descriptions that do not apply to these objects.Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 4

    -

    But what you are doing is trying to change the subject. In and you were claiming that Klima is mistaken when he attributes to Kripke the doctrine that, "the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies his description." In I showed why Klima is not mistaken at all. That you did not reply to the substance of that post implies that you admit that Klima correctly captures what Kripke has said. To fall back on the appeal that Kripke's theory is "tentative" is nothing but a quibble, and a quibble that is preempted by Klima's footnote where he quotes Kripke. Klima is proposing something authentically different from Kripke's (tentative) theory. That is the point of the comparison with Kripke.

    * 'In the ensuing discussion, I consider how the conception of reference presented in the first section handles these problems, and how it is related to contemporary discussions of the “causal”, or “historical explanation theory” of reference' (Klima, introduction).

    ---

    You have still not said what you think parasitic reference is.Banno

    Did you read the paper? Klima gives his account of parasitic reference in section 4. Roark gives additional explication of the concept in section 4 of his own paper (beginning on page 8).
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    The following appears mistakenBanno

    The sources are available, and it does not appear to be mistaken at all. Klima quotes Kripke in footnote 20, which attaches directly to your quote:

    20 “So, we may tentatively define the speaker’s referent of a designator to be that object which the speaker wishes to talk about, on a given occasion, and believes fulfils the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator.” Kripke, S. 1991, p.173.Gyula Klima, St. Anselm's Proof - Section 4

    That he is characterizing him correctly can be verified by consulting the text in question: Meaning and Truth: Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, page 173. There Kripke says precisely what Klima claims, namely that "the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies his description."

    The speaker's reference, given by pointing to Kaplan, is Kaplan. The intended reference, given by the name "Kripke", is Kripke. Hence it is not always the case that the speaker's reference is the one that satisfies the speaker's intent.Banno

    As @Count Timothy von Icarus correctly pointed out, there is nothing here contrary to what Klima has said.

    Kripke showed that speaker's reference may differ from semantic reference. However, he also showed that a name may refer to it's referent regardless of any description, and indeed in the absence of any description.Banno

    To again quote the footnote, "...and believes fulfils the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator." Klima is pointing out that on the intentional theory of reference such a belief is not necessary.

    Her semantic reference is to Kripke. Hence it is not true the speaker’s reference is to that which the speaker at least believes satisfies her description.Banno

    This is a non sequitur, for it is in no way clear that Sarah does not, "believe ["Kripke"] fulfils the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator." That Kripke disagrees with your construal is clear if we read the text that Klima cites (my bolding):

    Suppose a speaker takes it that a certain object a fulfills the conditions for being the semantic reference of a designator, "d." Then, wishing to say something about a, he uses "d" to speak about a; say, he says "Φ(d)." Then, he said, of a, on that occasion, that it Φ'd; in the appropriate Gricean sense (explicated above), he meant that a Φ'd. This is true even if a is not really the semantic referent of "d." If it is not, then that a Φ's is included in what he meant (on that occasion), but not in the meaning of his words (on that occasion).

    So, we may tentatively define the speaker's referent of a designator to be that object which the speaker wishes to talk about, on a given occasion, and believes fulfills the conditions for being the semantic referent of the designator.
    Kripke, Meaning and Truth: Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, 173

    -

    The speaker's reference may succeed when description is not satisfied by the referent, or if the belief of the speaker is in error.Banno

    This is yet another ignoratio elenchus, for this is not in question.
  • St. Anselm's Proof: A Problem of Reference, Intentional Identity and Mutual Understanding (G. Klima)
    To the quote from Roark, I do wonder if "parasitic reference" is the right solution here. It seems possible to also frame it as a sort of mental bracketing. So, one can consider the idea of God and affirm that it implies its own affirmation, but then, outside the bracketing, deny that any concept should be able to imply its own affirmation.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Coming back to this, I think it's basically right, except that I think Klima sees that bracketing as bound up with parasitic reference. That is, for Klima when one refers to another's thought object—a thought object which is outside of one's own universe of thought objects—one is engaged in parasitic reference. But as I said just above, I don't really like the way he uses the words "property" and "description" to convey this bracketing in section 4. Regarding the quote from Roark:

    [The atheist] does not himself think of God as the thing than which nothing greater can be thought.Tony Roark, Conceptual Closure in Anselm's Proof, 9

    In Klima's terms, there is a parasitic understanding of what the theist is referring to, but there is no possible candidate in the atheist's universe of thought objects to which this thought object would correspond. On Klima's view, for the atheist to even have such a thought object in his own universe of thought objects would require the process of concept acquisition.

    Else, if we want to isolate and scrutinize the idea of parasitic reference, then perhaps we should ask whether one can achieve what Roark (and Klima) are trying to achieve without recourse to the notion of parasitic reference. I mostly think that one cannot do so. Nevertheless, it may be that parasitic reference is necessary but insufficient to account for the intricacies of disagreements over Anselm's proof, which gets at the difference between questions 1 and 2 <here>.