Comments

  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    Right, and to restate my point, J's objection holds against any theory of knowledge which takes truth to be a necessary condition of knowledge, and this is not just JTB, it is pretty much every theory of knowledge.Leontiskos

    I am not sure about that implication of what J has been arguing, but I think truth is a necessary condition of knowledge,Janus

    @J's central move is to say that if someone thinks truth is a necessary condition of knowledge, then they must explain how truth can be known apart from all the other conditions of knowledge (such as justification or belief), and since no one can do that, therefore truth is not a necessary condition of knowledge. This is endlessly confused.

    and I also think knowing the truth and knowing how you know it is also a necessary condition of knowledge. That said, I am not claiming that we cannot think we have knowledge and yet be wrong.Janus

    Okay.

    I will just link to , particularly the second half. If someone thinks this:

    The problem, as I pointed out earlier, is that if we don't know whether the justifications for our beliefs are themselves [sound] then [...] How do we know they are adequate as justifications?Janus

    ...Then they are making justification into something other than justification. Justification is per se persuasive. Persuasiveness isn't something that gets tacked onto justification. A false justification is something that purports to be persuasive but is not. The question of how we know whether a justification is adequate has to do with logic, inference, validity, etc., and goes back to what about "the Aristotelian way to develop such an idea."

    (Still, even once we understand how soundness pertains to justification, there remains a difference between the concept of soundness and the concept of truth. They do not collapse into each other even in those cases where they are biconditional.)

    Edit: Part of the problem here is the semantic range of the word "justification." Properly speaking, what is needed for the internalism that is being presupposed is for one to have the explanation (aitia) for why something in reality is the way it is. One must be able to (correctly) explain why it is true. "Justification" can mean that, but it can also mean providing an ad hoc or unsound account, and the critiques of a justification condition are presupposing this latter meaning (of faux justification).
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    Thermometers never commit epistemic errors; they can only mislead those who uncritically rely upon them. Likewise, the same can be said of a 'believer's' utterances.

    The dilemma is either

    A. a belief merely refers to the coexistence of a believer's mental state and an external truth-maker, where the external truth-maker is decided by the linguistic community rather than the believer. In which case the intentionality associated with the believer's mental state is irrelevant with respect to the belief that the community ascribes to the believer as a matter of linguistic convention rather than of neurological fact.

    or

    B. Beliefs refer to the actual physical causes of the believer's mental-state - in which case the believer's intentionality is relevant - so much so, that it is epistemically impossible for the believer to have false beliefs. (Trivialism).
    sime

    The situation isn't different with humans as measuring devices. And hence as with the example of a thermometer, either humans have intentional belief states, in which case their beliefs cannot be false due to the object of their beliefs being whatever caused their beliefs, else their beliefs are permitted to be false, in which case the truthmaker of their belief is decided externally by their community.sime

    So we have two distinct notions of truth in play: Intersubjective mathematical truth... versus what we might call "John's subjective truth"...sime

    Consider this post a bookmark, as I have been wanting to respond to these posts but haven't had the time and am now occupied again.

    I think there are false dilemmas occurring here, owing to a presupposition that can hopefully be explored later on, but which is close to the presupposition that "the situation isn't different with humans as measuring devices."

    The key will be to see that one's truthmaker is not stipulated merely by oneself, and that the truthmaker is not merely a consensus reached by an external community. For the realist there is an object that exists in reality which one is trying to understand, and correctly understanding the object will not be a matter of aligning oneself with any particular linguistic community. In a more preliminary way we would want to ask why the dichotomy you present would be plausible. Why think that the two options you present are exhaustive?
  • Strong Natural Theism: An Alternative to Mainstream Religion
    This is an interesting video that touches on many of the themes of the OP: Bishop Robert Barron and Rabbi Meir Soloveichik.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    I was thinking rather the opposite. The reason people fiddle with T is to make it so that we can possess "knowledge" and access "truth" while still maintaining a view of J (and B) that makes it impossible to possess knowledge and have access to truth in their traditional sense.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right, I am saying the same thing.

    The problem I see is that this just seems like equivocation. The problems of global fallibilism appear to go away because "knowledge" and "truth" have been redefined, but they aren't actually being dealt with.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yes, and my point is that if one rejects the traditional sense of truth then JTB in its traditional sense naturally falls. Perhaps I should have not spoken about 'T' in the way that I did, since what I said could be read as claiming that someone who replaces traditional T with some other T will thereby reject JTB in the non-traditional sense. That's not quite what I was meaning to say, but I think it is also true.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    That's why I say the J, T, and B are more loaded than they might first appear.

    ...

    A "justification," of claims to be in contact with reality (in possession of knowledge) on the basis of appearances needs some metaphysics of how appearances relate to reality. If this linkage doesn't exist, I am not sure how J ever falls into place or how T would ever show up in our experience. But if J is about the private and communal imputation of status in the first place, and not about a relationship between the knower and known, how could it ever bridge the gap?
    Count Timothy von Icarus

    Good post. :up:

    This is what I was pointing up earlier with the pool analogy. If J and T are conceived of along the lines of that analogy, then the "task" that @J has set before him is impossible by definition. None of it is as mysterious as it is being made out to be. If one's anthropology precludes the mind from knowing things, then truth will be inaccessible and any theory with a T—including JTB—will fail. For example, if T is not traditional-T but rather pragmatic-T or communal-T, then of course JTB is undermined.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    @Janus

    I think the central argument is as follows, and you have been wrestling with it throughout your posts:

    1. If something could be false, then we do not know it
    2. Everything could be false
    3. Therefore, we do not know anything

    Most rejoinders in this thread have attacked (2) by trying to point to certain beliefs that could not be false.

    As for your other argument:

    JTB declares that we possess knowledge when our justified beliefs are true. The problem, as I pointed out earlier, is that if we don't know whether the justifications for our beliefs are themselves true then where does that leave us? How do we know they are adequate as justifications?Janus

    First I would say that justification and truth are not altogether separate notions. The telos of justification is truth. If there is no truth then no justification is doing what it attempts to do. Thus it is a mistake to conceive of justification as this animal which has no intrinsic relation to truth.

    Second, the Aristotelian way to develop such an idea is to identify different kinds of justifications or arguments or explanations. Once we can see that justifications come in different shapes and sizes, we can see why some are better at obtaining the aim of truth than others, and what makes for that difference. Once this is established we are no longer faced with the problem of all justifications being equal (equally sound or unsound).
  • Thoughts on Epistemology


    To elaborate:

    Right, and to restate my point, J's objection holds against any theory of knowledge which takes truth to be a necessary condition of knowledge, and this is not just JTB, it is pretty much every theory of knowledge. "Truth can't be a necessary condition of knowledge," is not merely an objection against JTB; it is an objection against the traditional understanding of knowledge in toto.Leontiskos

    @J is basically saying, "We must reject JTB because it makes truth a condition for knowledge."

    "We must stop drinking milk because it contains water."

    I would respond, "There my be good arguments for rejecting milk, but this is not one of them. This is an argument against water more than an argument against milk. Or rather, it is an argument against water dressed up as an argument against milk."

    What is at stake here is an argument against truth dressed up as an argument against JTB.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    JTB declares that we possess knowledge when our justified beliefs are true.Janus

    Right, and to restate my point, @J's objection holds against any theory of knowledge which takes truth to be a necessary condition of knowledge, and this is not just JTB, it is pretty much every theory of knowledge. "Truth can't be a necessary condition of knowledge," is not merely an objection against JTB; it is an objection against the traditional understanding of knowledge in toto.

    JTB declares that we possess knowledge when our justified beliefs are true. The problem, as I pointed out earlier, is that if we don't know whether the justifications for our beliefs are themselves true then where does that leave us? How do we know they are adequate as justifications?

    Or looking ta it the other way around, take the Theory of Evolution, for example. It seems we are amply justified in thinking it is true, but we don't really know whether it is true. Can the justifications for thinking it true be themselves true even if the theory is false?
    Janus

    As I have said in the past, I would want to use the words valid/invalid and sound/unsound for justifications, and true/false for propositions. That itself clears up part of your conundrum, albeit not all of it.

    Going back to my earlier point, if we read JTB as referring to "justification" materially, then in my opinion it fails. If we read JTB as referring to "justification" formally, then in my opinion it does not fail. But the first option seems uncharitable and strawman-ish.

    Regarding Evolution, I think it is clear that the theory of Evolution is not knowledge in the strictest sense (scientia), and therefore it is not demonstrable. The theory of Evolution involves precisely the sort of probabilistic guesses that some take all knowledge to be bound up with.

    Again, part of the problem here is that some want JTB to offer a recipe for knowledge, as if we could know that we know with perfect certainty via JTB. Whether this is possible is an interesting question, but even if some kinds of knowledge could fit into that category, Evolution cannot. Note though that if we can know that we know some things with perfect certainty, then the J and the T will be inextricably bound up with respect to those things. Contrary to @J's claims, this does not mean that the J and the T are indifferentiable, but it does mean that a biconditional holds between them in the case of demonstration.

    Hume was skeptical of what cannot be observed as "matter of fact". If I know you well, and I see you fall off your bicycle, there can be no doubt in that moment that I see you fall off your bicycle, so I can say that I know you fell off your bicycle because I saw it happen. How long does the "no doubt" situation last, though?Janus

    If we take Hume's theory to its logical conclusion, then it is not permissible to trust your eyes because there is no valid argument to the effect that your eyes are trustworthy, or that your eyes are providing accurate information in that moment when you see me fall.

    The way that this would manifest in @J's thinking would be to say, "My belief that you fell off your bicycle could be false, therefore it is not knowledge." He would just offer the possibility of, say, unreliable faculties, hallucination, etc.

    That would be down to the accuracy of my memory. I might say my memory is very good and has been well-tested over the years and hardly ever fails me, and even when it does only in small matters, not significant ones like you falling off your bike, but that doesn't logically entail that my memory remains reliable, or even that my memory of the results of my memory being tested is accurate.Janus

    Right, but Hume would say that even if you've pocketed the 9-ball in this identical situation 1,000 times in the past, it doesn't follow that you will pocket it this time. Even if we grant that your memory has been accurate in the past, it doesn't follow that it is now accurate.

    ---

    No, you are quite right. Justification and investigation are how we determine the truth.Ludwig V

    Right.

    The issue here turns on justifications that provide evidence, but not conclusive evidence. In the context of JTB, such justifications can work, because the T clause denies claims to knowledge based on partial justification when their conclusions are false.Ludwig V

    I think there is a problem with this account, and I think the problem is precisely what Gettier points up. Gettier shows that someone can have belief, truth, and inconclusive evidence, and still fail to have knowledge. (But I am going to come back to your earlier posts in this vein. I am still catching up.)

    ---

    Well, I was going to respond to you before about "infallibalists," but I figured it might be beside the point of the thread.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Right.

    What then in infallible?Count Timothy von Icarus

    As I said earlier, I think it is a tangent. The crux is certainty, not infallibility. You can get to certainty via infallibility, but the claim that the only way to get to a certain judgment is through an infallible faculty is at best contentious.

    I think the difficulties for truth and knowledge crop up when the metaphysics of reality versus appearances is ignored, and so we default into this thin idea of "p is true if p." There is no explanation of how the being of p relates intrinsically to the thought of p. Appeals to cognitive science or the physics of perception don't end up being able to bridge this gap if they themselves are viewed as largely a matter of pattern recognition within appearances. Fallibalism will be unavoidable, except perhaps within the realm of our own experiences (a sort of solipsistic tendency).Count Timothy von Icarus

    Sure, but going back to Aristotle, if the identity of mind and object is true, then you do not have global uncertainty. If, on the other hand, like turtles it is "probabilities all the way down," then uncertain guesses are all we are afforded. The question here is whether the intellect is capable of certain knowledge, given its relation to the objects of knowledge. If there is a Humean severance between mind and its object then Aristotle is wrong and we are playing a game of pool where everything is an extra-mental collision that cannot be grasped by the mind with certainty.

    Although I will add that the fact that people are incapable of living like they believe nihilism is true is precisely what you would expect if their intellects were being informed by the world around them; they would be unable to shake off their understanding. No matter how hard they reasoned about the groundlessness of their own knowledge, they would still run from rabid dogs like Pyrrho or climb a tree to get away from raging bull elephants like Sanjaya.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yes indeed. So one ends up professing to believe something that they simply do not believe, given their actions. And whether what one cannot-but-believe is also known will depend on one's epistemology (and metaphysical anthropology).
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    I see. I think JTB is flawed but figuring out just how is tricky. JTB seems very thin and portable, but I think an investigation of the metaphysical context in which it was developed is helpful for diagnosing it.Count Timothy von Icarus

    I'm sort of wondering what context people take JTB to be coming from. That some are referencing Plato and others are referencing Ayer is a pretty significant difference!

    The problem with J's objection, as has been pointed out...

    My concerns with JTB are all about how the truth of P is supposed to be established.J

    ...is that it is an objection to any theory which says that truth is supposed to be established prior to justification and investigation, and it is also linked to J's belief that truth and understanding are, properly speaking, impossible. The first problem is that there is no theory which says that truth is supposed to be established prior to justification and investigation. That is a strange strawmen that has persisted for page after page. The second problem (which is related), is that if you are opposed to truth and knowledge, then why single out JTB as if it has some specific difficulty?

    I think the core problem here is J's Humean "game of pool" epistemology. If every belief is reducible to a guess and the mind never merges with its object in reality in the way that Aristotle describes, then J's conclusion that truth and knowledge do not exist is foregone. All of this meandering and ignoratio elenchus is just a working out of that Humean presupposition.

    I think JTB is flawed but figuring out just how is tricky.Count Timothy von Icarus

    As noted earlier, I think the problem with the way people are here conceiving of JTB lies precisely in seeing justification as material rather than formal. In seeing an unsound justification and a sound justification as equivalently sufficient conditions for knowledge. In conflating a false explanation with a true explanation, and inferring that someone who possesses the false explanation possesses the requisite justification.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    Regarding "probablistic" - do not mistake this with orthodox Bayesian epistemology, which depends on the absurd assumption that we can attach a consistent set of epistemic probabilities to every statement we claim to believe. Rather, I embrace Mark Kaplan's* "modest Bayesianism", which makes the modest claim that we can attach a relative confidence level to SOME pairs (or small sets) of statements of belief. If there's a reasonable basis for the ranking.Relativist

    Okay good, and therefore let me try to answer one of your questions from a different thread here, in part because I will be out for a few days:

    If there is no pole of knowledge then I don't see how one IBE can be better than another (because no IBE can better approach that pole).

    Similarly, if we know what ice is then we have a pole and a limit for the coldness of water. If we don't know what ice is, then the coldness of water is purely relative, and there is nothing to measure against. I would argue that knowledge is prior to IBE, and that IBE is parasitic upon knowledge. Thus if you make IBEs the only option, then there is nothing on which an IBE can be parasitic upon or subordinate to, and this undermines IBEs themselves.
    Leontiskos

    Does your "tentpole" comment refer to the mere fact that knowledge exists, are you suggesting IBEs that aren't based on knowledge are all equivalent, or something else entirely?Relativist

    Not a tentpole, but a pole such as the North Pole. If some things are more North and some things are less North, then something must be most North.

    So if knowledge is probabilistic, then it would seem to be asymptotic towards "100% probable." If someone doesn't know what it means to be 100% probable, then they cannot know what it means to be probabilistic at all. And if you admit IBEs or probabilistic knowledge without admitting traditional knowledge, then it looks like you have no pole to orient your IBE.

    The phrase itself, "inference to the best explanation," presupposes the idea of an explanation, and an explanation is not merely probabilistic.

    The general idea here—which will apply to a large number of the epistemological theories on offer—is that if we abandon the possibility or notion of certain knowledge, then the replacement form of uncertain knowledge will cease to make sense. If all knowledge is uncertain, then no knowledge is uncertain, so to speak. And if there is to be a spectrum of certainties, then one must account for what makes the more certain knowledge more certain and what makes the less certain knowledge less certain, and this accounting will itself reinstate the traditional view of knowledge that one was trying evade in the first place.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    Here is a different approach to the same conclusion:

    Can it be in any way validly justified that no ontologically occurring truths occur? If one believes that this is the case, what does one intend to express by the proposition of “no ontically occurring truths occur” if this proposition is not meant to conform/correspond to the actual states of affairs of the world and, thereby, of itself be an ontic truth? Thereby contradicting the very proposition made. Therefore, there is no justifiable alternative to the proposition that ontic truths occur.
    javra

    That's also an intelligible argument, but I think it's weaker than the other one. This is because it seems to commit the error of applying the LEM to justification, so to speak. It seems to say, "If you don't think one is justified in affirming the existence of 'ontological truths', then you must have some justification for affirming their non-existence." I don't think this works because I think that someone could reject all particular justifications on offer in either direction, even if they do not affirm the truth that there can be no justification in either direction. One example of this approach would be the ancient skepticism that you mentioned, but in a more general sense I think an agnostic stance that does not affirm either of the two "ontological truths" is coherent.

    As to providing knowledge of some "ontological truths", this, again, is what our ability to honestly and cogently justify offers us the possibility of. It just that our JTB knowledge will not, by a fallibilist account, be infallible. (Fallibiilty does not equate to being wrong.)javra

    But if "fallibility" means that we cannot be certain, then the same problem arises.

    The words "infallible" and "fallible" are often used by "fallibilists" but never by "infallibilists," which makes me think they involve contentious presuppositions. I would say that what is at stake is the certainty of knowledge, not the infallibility of knowledge. Actually the object of in/fallibility is a faculty or power, not a piece of knowledge, which is another reason I don't find those terms helpful. It is understandable that one would use them, but given that no one accounts themselves an "infallibilist" the distinction's usefulness is questionable. More simply, I see no reason why someone who affirms the certainty of some knowledge must be a so-called "infallibilist."

    Remember that the JTB model of knowledge was presented by an Ancient Skeptic. If one presumes knowledge to be infallible, then this quote holds. If one presumes knowledge to be fallible, then it does not.javra

    ...and since no one presumes knowledge to be infallible, and yet pretty much everyone holds that knowledge is certain, @Janus' conditional must apply more generally than you allow.

    By everything I've so far stated, there then can occur ontically true beliefs which we can justify at will. These then will be instances of ontic knowledge, which is certain. Because we can only hold epistemic appraisals of what is ontically true, though, everything we uphold as knowledge will be epistemic knowledge, rather than ontic knowledge - which, as with epistemic truth, is less than "completely assured, fixed, and invariable."javra

    Well you're walking a tightrope with these sentences. For one thing, I would want to ask what it means for "ontic knowledge" to "occur" or be "certain." And why is it "certain" that there are instances of ontic knowledge? Couldn't someone of your persuasion hold that there are no ontically true beliefs, even though every epistemological belief aims at ontic knowledge?

    I would take the more traditional approach and agree with a great deal of what you have said, but add that sometimes "epistemological knowledge" and "ontic knowledge" coincide, and can be known to coincide.

    I'll be back tomorrow.javra

    Okay, and if I don't manage to post tomorrow then I will be out for a few days.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    The truth of the proposition here quoted would of course of itself be an epistemic truth. One which I so far find thoroughly justifiable: To keep things short, I so far find that there can be no epistemic truth in the absence of an ontically occuring truth it aspires to express. Can you, or anyone else, cogently justify the occurence of an epistemic truth that does not claim to be or else intend to conform to an ontic truth?

    If not, then it remains cogently justifiable that ontically occuring truths do occur. Conversely, it then becomes unjustifiable that ontically occurring truths do not occur.
    javra

    That's a fair argument. It is similar to a comment asked me about, and which could perhaps be folded into this thread:

    If there is no pole of knowledge then I don't see how one [inference to the best explanation] can be better than another (because no [inference to the best explanation] can better approach that pole).Leontiskos

    You seem to be saying that "epistemic truths" presuppose the existence of "ontological truths"; we all believe ourselves to be uttering "epistemic truths"; therefore we are all presupposing the existence of "ontological truths"; and because of this the belief in "ontological truths" is justified.

    I think that's a good account on the "game of pool" approach, but I would prefer an account that provides for knowledge of at least some "ontological truths," rather than mere justified belief. Or in other words, if we take up your idea of fallibilism via Janus' conditional:

    So, if we know p could be false, then we don't know that it's true, but we may well believe that it's true.Janus

    Then on the premise that we know that every p (epistemological truth) could be false, we cannot know any p.

    has forwarded a theory where all (or almost all - this is contentious) beliefs are inferences to the best explanation, and are thus probabilistic.

    On all of these conceptions certain knowledge is impossible, and yet knowledge is traditionally understood to be certain.


    (It should again be noted that none of this has anything special to do with JTB. The one who thinks JTB does not understand JTB.)
  • Hate speech - a rhetorical pickaxe
    The phrase itself betrays its own bad faith intentions. A technical term that means something quite different from what it says.Roke

    The problem with "hate speech" is that it very often involves hostile translation. It very often amounts to, "You don't think your speech is hateful, but I do think it is hateful and I am going to punish you for it."

    Another way to think about it is to note that if "hate speech" is an honest descriptor then it isn't bad, and if it is bad then it isn't an honest descriptor. For example, if someone were using "hate speech" as an honest descriptor, then Neville Chamberlain's declaration of war against Nazi Germany was hate speech, and yet it was not bad hate speech. And if someone is using "hate speech" the way it is usually used, as "bad speech," then Chamberlain's declaration of war fails to be hate speech for some magical reason that the person cannot articulate.

    So the accusation is incoherent as used. Only pacifists or quasi-pacifists are able to use a concept like "hate speech" meaningfully, and the people trying to justify their hate on the basis of "hate speech" are far from pacifists. :wink:
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    If I combine this:

    In short, when a truth occurs, it occurs ontically—and that which ontically is is not subject to the possibility of being wrong, i.e. fallibility. But we can only appraise what ontically is epistemologically, which will always be to some extent fallible.javra

    And this:

    When differentiating the ontological from the epistemological, ontically occurring truths (which are absolutely certain and not possible to be wrong) do occur all the time. But our epistemic appraisals of what are and are not ontic truths (the latter, again, do occur) will be fallible to some measure.javra

    Is there a contradiction?

    Consider this proposition as if it were itself a truth:

    <Ontological truths (which are absolutely certain and not possible to be wrong) do occur all the time.>

    Is this "truth" an "ontological truth" or an "epistemological truth"? Because if it is an "epistemological truth," then it is not certain, and if it is an "ontological truth," then your appraisal is not fallible. This is why I'm not sure the way you are dividing up this territory is ultimately coherent. You are speaking as if your knowledge-claims about ontological truths are themselves ontological truths and not epistemological truths, and your theory seems to preclude this.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    If—as any fallibilist will maintain—all possible epistemological appraisals can only be fallible, then our appraisal of a belief being either true or not will always be liable to some possibility of being wrong (with the likelihood of this possibility varying by degrees).javra

    Right, and I think this is the more central piece for @J, along with what has said. It goes back to this:

    The counterargument could be phrased this way:

    1. Truth is always known via justification, and ensured by justification
    2. Justification can never overcome the possibility of the one-in-a-million anomaly
    3. Therefore, truth is never certain

    This form of skepticism is a bit like the claim that epistemology is like a game of pool and no matter how good you are, there is always a chance that your shot will not pocket the 9-ball. Accidental contingencies are always involved, and therefore the best one can hope for is a good probability (or an ↪inference to the best explanation). Such a skeptic would say, "The only way to guarantee that the 9-ball is pocketed would be to pick it up with your own hand and place it into the pocket directly, but that would be cheating."
    Leontiskos

    Put more simply, for someone like @J every knowledge-claim involves guessing, and therefore there is no knowledge that is qualitatively different from a guess. Everything he is arguing about JTB is dependent on this form of skepticism that is so foundational for him. Truth is going to be a problem for him in any circumstance, JTB or otherwise. He will make (and has made!) the same objections to anyone who talks about truth as if it is a meaningful category, whether they hold to JTB or not.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    That's true (sorry!)J

    There is an interesting meta-question here. Given that you don't actually believe in truth or knowledge and therefore are forced into an intersubjective notion of truth, here in this thread we have an example where you are at an intersubjective loss. What you are saying in this thread is simply false on an intersubjective approach to truth, given that literally everyone is disagreeing with you. Does that mean that you should accept that what you are saying is false and give up this strange line of argument (given that you yourself think truth is an intersubjective phenomenon)? Or is there something more to truth than intersubjectivity? Are you allowed to hold that although your claims about JTB are intersubjectively false, they are nevertheless not false?
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    I don't follow this at all. Smith is not considering two propositions, but only one, and that proposition is false and so does not entail that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket,...Ludwig V

    If there were only one proposition, then how could there be an entailment? Gettier's argument depends on the entailment, and entailments involve at least two propositions. "The man who will get the job" does not refer to either Smith or Jones. It is a descriptor. What this means is that, contrary to your view, Smith is not uttering a tautology when he says, "Jones is the man who will get the job." Such an utterance is not the same as, "Jones is Jones," even for Smith.

    Your theory amounts to the idea that when Smith says, "The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket," he is saying something false. But when someone else says the exact same sentence, such as the hiring agent who knows that Smith has ten coins in his pocket, he is saying something true. This goes back to what I said here:

    Regarding the "false grounds," the key to the Gettier case is the difference between a material conclusion and a formal conclusion...

    ...Taken further we might say that a valid conclusion is different from a sound conclusion, and therefore John and Ben have reached different conclusions.
    Leontiskos

    So I think a material conclusion can differ from a formal conclusion, for example when both say the same thing and yet the "therefore" of the first is merely valid whereas the "therefore" of the second is sound. This may even go further and apply to propositions themselves rather than mere conclusions, as I surmised in that post. But I don't see that what is at stake is a simple matter of reference, as if there is only one proposition and no entailment occurring.

    Yes, perhaps I was a bit hasty there. Though if someone tells me that the earth goes round the sun, I can demand their proof and they can, no doubt, provide it - the data exist and the interpretation can be explained to me. But I would have to trust the data, or, perhaps collect a fresh set of data.Ludwig V

    Yes, and I would go farther and say that you can see that their argument is correct. It's not so much a matter of trusting them.
  • A -> not-A
    A. ((¬3 → ¬2) ^ 2) → 3
    B. ((¬3 → ¬2) ^ 2)
    C. ∴ 3

    Premise B and conclusion C complete the modus tollens.
    NotAristotle

    Again, I see no modus tollens there. The inference needed to achieve C is modus ponens, not modus tollens.

    Second, let's do the substitutions that I suggested you do. We start with your construal:

    A. ((¬3 → ¬2) ^ 2) → 3
    B. ((¬3 → ¬2) ^ 2)
    C. ∴ 3
    NotAristotle

    And we substitute the premises into their places:

    A. ((¬[MP is not false] → ¬[RAA is not false]) ^ [RAA is not false]) → [MP is not false]
    B. ((¬[MP is not false] → ¬[RAA is not false]) ^ [RAA is not false])
    C. ∴ [MP is not false]

    That doesn't make any sense to me. It doesn't even include (1) at all, and it doesn't look anything like my own construal:

    (1 ^ 2) → 3
    (1 ^ 2)
    ∴ 3
    Leontiskos


    ...which would be:

    ([If MP could be false, then RAA could be false] ^ [RAA is not false]) → [MP is not false]
    [If MP could be false, then RAA could be false] ^ [RAA is not false]
    ∴ [MP is not false]

    That's valid and intelligible, at least if we don't fret too much about the "could be" modal idea that I have not been fretting about.
  • The End of the Western Metadiscourse?
    Yes, that's exactly what I was talking about. It is stated on paper: you are free from everything, just do not violate the rights of others. Freedom lies in the fact that no one is responsible for you. In essence, at all times in liberal regimes there have always been other institutions of unfreedom: the church, morality, institutions of civil society. I wrote about this above: try to declare in a liberal society that you love Putin or Kim - you will immediately be attacked, but not by the state, but by civil society. Much has been said here about the prohibition of dissent in authoritarian regimes. And yes, the consequences of dissent in such regimes will be harsher. However, I see how many forum participants seem to have the firmware "Liberalism is good" pre-installed, and even if they themselves doubt it, they are not very willing to speak out about it. Isn't this another form of prohibition of dissent? More sophisticated?Astorre

    Yes, that's well said. You my be interested in Count Timothy's thread, "The Myopia of Liberalism."

    As to the question of whether it is the liberal state or the liberal civil society which defends liberalism from illiberalism, I want to say that it is both. This is part of the paradox wherein liberalism professes to be value-neutral and yet is inevitably founded upon the value system of liberalism. When someone promotes an idea that is at odds with liberalism, the liberal culture will oppose them, and this opposition will come from both the state and the civil society. For example, the end-limit of promoting a figure like Putin will end up conflicting with the laws of the liberal state. Put differently, if enough people within a liberal society embrace an illiberal approach, then the liberalism of that society will itself fail and the laws will need to be changed to reflect the societal change.

    the content of hidden pillars was revealed to meAstorre

    Can you say more about the "hidden pillars" of liberalism? Presumably you are thinking of the pushback that comes from civil society, but I am curious about the nature of those hidden pillars.

    My goal is to find “something else” that would be capable of self-organizing structures, and which previous ideologies do not allow to appear, constantly putting spokes in the wheels with their interventions.Astorre

    I think philosophical anthropology is tightly knit with any political program. For example, Hobbes' "State of nature" is tightly bound up with liberalism, and the truth or falsity of Hobbes' doctrine will correlate to the success or failure of liberalism. Of course there are alternatives that deviate in smaller or larger ways from Hobbes' anthropology, but I think Hobbes is the most central, coherent, and enduring philosophical basis of liberalism. I would say that Aristotle offers a better philosophical anthropology and a better political program as well.
  • A -> not-A
    I would not say I misrepresented my own argument, I would say I miswrote your representation of my argument.NotAristotle

    Here is your argument:

    1. If MP could be false, then RAA could be false.
    2. But RAA is not false.
    3. Therefore neither is MP.
    NotAristotle

    Here is my construal:

    (1 ^ 2) → 3
    (1 ^ 2)
    ∴ 3
    Leontiskos

    Here is your construal:

    [If] 1 and 2 then not 1.
    1 and 2.
    Therefore not 1.
    NotAristotle

    Isn't it clear that your construal is mistaken? Try substituting 1, 2, and 3 into each of our construals and see what happens. 1, 2, and 3 are defined in your original argument.

    -

    Would you agree that your representation of my argument:

    ...

    could also be written as follows...

    A. not-3 then not-2. And 2. Then 3.
    B. not-3 then not-2. And 2.
    C. Therefore 3.
    NotAristotle

    No, I don't follow this. And you'll need parenthesis and clearer operators if you are trying to transform my propositions. For example, "X then Y" is not a standard usage. You are either omitting 'ifs' or confusing 'then' with the implication sign (→).

    So maybe you are right that any argument can be written metalogically as a modus ponens, but I think it cannot be so written without the logical inferences that the argument require, in this case a modus tollens is necessary to the argument and cannot be written off as being a hidden modus ponens.NotAristotle

    But I don't see how your construals are retaining the modus tollens. None of them seem to use modus tollens at all...?

    The point about the ubiquity of modus ponens is related to the "therefore" of all arguments. "Therefore" means something like "Hence it follows from the preceding," and that "follows from" move is arguably identical with modus ponens.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    Smith wrongly, but not without justification, believes that Jones is the man who will get the job, but the truth is that Smith will get the job. So Smith is using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones, but we (and Gettier) are using it to refer to Smith.Ludwig V

    Okay, that is an interesting way to approach the problem. The reason I don't think it works is because if Smith were using "the man who will get the job" to refer to Jones, then there would not be an entailment involved. In that case rather than there being an entailment, Smith's two propositions would just be saying the same thing with different words. But Gettier is explicit that an entailment is involved ("Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment from (d) to (e), and accepts (e) on the grounds of (d)"), therefore what is at stake is not a mere matter of reference.

    JTB requires me to accept a claim to knowledge only if I know it is justified and true (and believed). But that means that I have to know p as well as the person claiming knowledge.Ludwig V

    I don't think this is right. Someone can "justify" a claim to you and thereby show you that it is true. Thus one can learn from another on JTB precisely through the other's justification.
  • Self-Help and the Deflation of Philosophy
    "Optimize" how? This is a value-laden term, just like your earlier invocation of "Darwinian success." Now if there is no end being sought, and whatever is "adaptive" is just whatever just so happens to end up happening, all these value terms are simply equivocations. Indeed, "pragmatism" is itself an equivocation if there is no real end involved.Count Timothy von Icarus

    Yeah, I think this is right, despite the fact that we seem to be beating a dead horse.

    Or as the Catholic Encyclopedia of Social Theory puts it surprisingly polemically:Count Timothy von Icarus

    Interesting quote. :up:
    Is the source, "Encyclopedia of Catholic Social Thought, Social Science, and Social Policy"?
  • The End of the Western Metadiscourse?


    There are lots of interesting ideas there, but let me focus on just one:

    Perhaps herein lies the main metaphysical kernel of liberalism:
    it is power without the master.
    Not because the master no longer exists, but because he has become invisible, elusive, inaccessible to reproach.
    He no longer commands — he regulates. He does not care — he provides platforms. He does not answer — he disconnects.

    Are you free?
    Then be responsible for everything.

    But freedom that does not include structures of responsibility — this is not emancipation, but a form of finely crafted abandonment.
    And if the slave, despite all his unfreedom, was once held by the master’s sleeve, today the free person — falls alone.

    ...

    What is more important: to be free and nobody's, or unfree, but in a system where someone needs you?
    Astorre

    I think this is on point, and it is at least clear that our current stage of liberalism has resulted in a dearth of subsidiarity. The individual has become isolated, responsible only for themselves and therefore not responsible at all. And where individuals are to be responsible only for themselves and their state of being, we end up confused in the face of realities which contradict this doctrine. For example, the "crack baby" confuses a society which holds to the doctrine of liberal individualism.

    In the Hobbesian mindset the only foundational agent other than the individual is the state, and the only rights bestowed upon the individual by any other agent are bestowed by the state. Thus in the modern liberal mindset the only one which truly owes us obligations—the only "master"—is the liberal state. Thus one must either reason from what one receives from the state to what one is owed (i.e. "The state gave me bread therefore I was/am owed bread by the state"), or one must reason from what one is owed to what one is owed by the state (i.e. "I have a right to X, therefore it is the state and only the state which must fulfill this right").

    This unnatural situation where there is only the agent of the individual and the agent of the state results in a lack of natural intermediate and subsidiary institutions and associations by which rights and duties are generated among social animals. Instead of assuming that every right must be fulfilled by the state, a non-liberal society is much more apt to assume that some rights are fulfilled by subsidiary institutions, such as the spouse, or the family, or the community, or the polis. Or in the case you give, one would look to the "master."
  • The End of the Western Metadiscourse?
    This discussion can go nowhere I believe because of a basic difference in our metaphysical logic.apokrisis

    The strawmen abound. I've already explained why this is a misconstrual in places like this:

    Throughout there seems to be a kind of equivocation, where you eschew the terms "good" and "bad" by claiming that an optimal mixture of both is what is needed, but then you don't seem to notice that what is actually good on that account is the optimal mixture. Don't you agree that the optimal mixture or balance is good, and that the ordering is bad to the extent that it deviates from this optimal balance? This is why I think Count Timothy von Icarus' objection cuts deeper than you realize, for it applies also at this new level of good-as-balance. If I am right and you have your own conception of what is good and what is bad, then acknowledging this would help put us on the same page and would help us appreciate a common criterion.Leontiskos

    Or that "balance" approaches are fine, but not unique:

    I also find that "balance" approaches tend to be almost indistinguishable from other robust approaches in practice. For example, I think you will end up appealing to the cardinal virtues of prudence, temperance, justice, and fortitude, just in a roundabout way. The question is then whether the simplification is helpful: whether pragmatism prefers that humans conceive of an ur-cause or not.Leontiskos

    If you are aiming at balance, then for you balance is good. You can't just keep avoiding that fact and claiming that good/bad divisions must be avoided. Once it is recognized that balance is good, then one will want to ask why it is good, or what it means for it to be good.

    My central objection is that survival-based poles lack explanatory power. It's as if you think that shades of grey are all that is needed to explain the world, and I think we need colors. I think that the explanadum of human social reality is more complex and robust than survival-based poles are able to account for, and that a unified survival-theory is therefore an oversimplification. Your account literally reads to me like the very Protestant Occasionalism that you so often project onto your interlocutors, with a tidy Ur-cause that accounts for everything. ...With that objection and one or two others aside, I see nothing overly wrong with a "balance" approach to ethics or metaphysics. Such is soundly Aristotelian.

    Yet you are also saying that I do not properly understand how great your semiotic-evolutionary theory really is. And that may be. Maybe you really are able to explain all of the diversity of human social realities with one unified theory, and I just don't understand that theory well enough to see it. That's possible, but I have no reason to believe it, and the reason this discussion can go nowhere is because your esoteric theory is opaque to those who have not spent a large amount of time with it.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    You are right that there is at least one sense in which justification and truth rise or fall together. But Gettier's argument assumes that they do not, that is, that it is possible to be justified in believing that p and for p to be false.Ludwig V

    Well, I think Gettier creates a strange division between justification and truth, but the Gettier cases I am familiar with involve a proposition that is true, not false.

    But if I'm evaluating whether someone knows that p, I must make my own evaluation of the truth or falsity of p,Ludwig V

    Yes, quite right.

    This has the awkward consequence that I can never learn anything from anyone else.Ludwig V

    Why think that?

    ---

    Q1. Do I have knowledge of X (a proposition)?J

    Again, that's not what JTB is for. It doesn't give you a recipe for knowledge, and it is not primarily meant to allow you to see if your own beliefs constitute knowledge. If one thought that JTB was meant to allow you to see if your own beliefs constitute knowledge, then the T and the B would be otiose, as you keep saying.

    what use is JTB if it can't show us how to tell whether we know something or not?J

    Right, because if something can't show us how to answer your pet question then it must be of no use at all. :roll:
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    I agree with Leon, but then, because of the possibility of error, what is happening when we think we know something but we do not? Wouldn’t we have to be able to separate J, T or B from the others to think we know something when in fact what we know is missing J, T or B? Or are all three destroyed, along with K, when we are in error?Fire Ologist

    I think the first thing is this:

    JFB fails the test for knowledge, and we know P is F rather than T due to a "justification," namely a justification separate from the particular J in JFB. If someone offers a claim and we have no reason to believe it is false, then we cannot claim that it is false (i.e. not true).Leontiskos

    So on JTB we will only know we have failed when we know that one of the three conditions is absent. And we cannot know that T is absent unless we know that the knowledge-claim is not true. And we cannot know that the knowledge-claim is not true if we are not justified in so knowing, which means that we must have reasons or grounds (whether or not we can articulate them). More simply, it means that knowledge-claims are never invalidated except in light of some other, opposed knowledge-claim. So contrary to @J's thinking, one would never know or even claim that T is absent without reasoning/justification.

    This means that if John claims that Ben's knowledge-claim is false, there is the presupposition that John's claim involves JTB. John believes Ben's knowledge-claim is false; it is true that Ben's knowledge-claim is false; and Ben has the proper justification for knowing that Ben's knowledge-claim is false. Nowhere arises the idea that John must know whether Ben's knowledge-claim is true or false apart from justification (or belief, for that matter).

    Or are all three destroyed, along with K, when we are in error?Fire Ologist

    I don't see how belief would be destroyed, but there is at least one sense in which justification and truth rise or fall together. But that gets us back to @Sam26's questions about Gettier's objection.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    how are we supposed to use JTB as a test for knowledge?J

    Is that what JTB is for?Srap Tasmaner

    What is JTB for?

    It is not a "test" in the sense that we have a machine that allows us to practically run any knowledge-claim through it and know in fact whether it is or is not knowledge.

    But it is at the very least supposed to provide a set of three necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge.

    @J's objection could be that the T in JTB is otiose, but this is obviously false. The objection could also be premised on the idea that JTB is a kind of automatic knowledge-testing machine and that J, T, and B are three separate and reliably verifiable properties of every knowledge-claim. This is also false, as is the sub-idea that the three properties are supposed to be separable: as if we could have knowledge of each of them separate from the others.

    JTB is a tripartite schema, which means that the three components are not separable vis-a-vis knowledge. Beyond that, every epistemological approach will fail to provide a knowledge-guarantee-machine. If one is looking for a knowledge-guarantee-machine, then it is not only JTB that will let them down.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    "The T in JTB is dependent on P's being true" -- yes, but if we don't ask "How can I know this?" then I don't understand how we'd ever be able to use T in JTB.J

    Again, if you think the T in JTB can be known apart from the J and the B then you have rejected the JTB account. You have claimed that there is knowledge apart from J and B.

    JTB proposes that only true propositions can be known, AND that there is a way to determine truth apart from justifications.J

    If JTB thought there were a way to know truth apart from justification, then there would be no J in JTB. You are effectively objecting to a 'T' account of knowledge, not a 'JTB' account of knowledge.

    You are still doing your "JTB as a recipe for knowledge-cakes," noted from my very first post.

    So if we can't determine T in some way independent of J, how are we supposed to use JTB as a test for knowledge?J

    JFB fails the test for knowledge, and we know P is F rather than T due to a "justification," namely a justification separate from the particular J in JFB. If someone offers a claim and we have no reason to believe it is false, then we cannot claim that it is false (i.e. not true).

    You are always searching for a magic bullet that will allow us to get behind the scenes and infallibly distinguish JTB from JFB according to some "God's-eye view." There isn't one, but that doesn't mean JTB is incoherent.

    (The trouble is that you hijack every epistemological discussion and make it about this pet question of yours, in much the same way that an atheist will hijack every theological discussion and make it about the existence of God.)
  • A -> not-A
    My point in these last few comments is just that MT is not an instance of MP metalogically.NotAristotle

    I continue to think that modus ponens is always operating metalogically:

    Yes, but I think that all arguments are, structurally, modus ponens. This goes back to the earlier point about whether all arguments are modus ponens, or whether all arguments utilize a material conditional. Tones is claiming that the metalogical inference uses a material conditional, and is not merely a modus ponens, and that this is why he thinks inconsistent premises automatically* make an argument valid [whereas I think a mere modus ponens is at play].Leontiskos

    The initial argument I forwarded...NotAristotle

    Which was this:

    1. If MP could be false, then RAA could be false.
    2. But RAA is not false.
    3. Therefore neither is MP.
    NotAristotle

    The initial argument I forwarded would, I think, be more like:
    [If] 1 and 2 then not 1.
    1 and 2.
    Therefore not 1.
    NotAristotle

    The most obvious problem is that you seem to be misrepresenting your own argument. Your argument is a modus tollens that metalogically comes to this modus ponens:

    • If 1 and 2, then not [antecedent of 1]
    • 1 and 2
    • Therefore, not [antecedent of 1]

    You are mixing up the antecedent of 1 with 1 itself. But I think my phrasing is preferable since there really is a 3 in the object-level argument, namely the conclusion. The conclusion is not reducible to the premises, and neither is it "not 1." Once we recognize that the conclusion, namely 3, is the same as "not [antecedent of 1]," we see that the two construals are identical, and that both utilize modus ponens.

    I still agree with what I said about the metalogical question .


    * Note that we could generalize the form of this modus ponens representation of modus tollens:

    • If [conditional] and [negation of conditional's consequent], then [negation of conditional's antecedent]
    • [Conditional] and [negation of conditional's consequent]
    • Therefore, [negation of conditional's antecedent]

    (Edit: for the root issue, see my post <here>. If someone like Tones thinks RAA equally entails two completely different conclusions and makes no recourse to explosion, then I think it is obvious that what I have said about RAA is correct. Namely: The RAA inference is not as metalogically secure as the modus ponens inference, and the introduction of something which can be construed as semantically equivalent to Falsum helps show this.)
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    So, if we know p could be false, then we don't know that it's trueJanus

    This is correct, and it is the crux. Someone like @J thinks that for every proposition or claim, we know that it could be false (and therefore we cannot know that any proposition is true). Put differently, @J thinks that every belief should include the caveat, "This could be false."

    "Could have been" is a different question. You are asking the more central question, which is, "Could be false."

    When Aristotle talks about this he basically talks about the possible alternatives, where the case where we know there are no possible alternatives is a case of proper knowledge. Thus if we know that something could be false then we do not have proper knowledge that it is true (scientia).
  • How Does One Live in the 'Here and Now'? Is it Conceptual or a Practical Philosophy Question?
    Being trapped within the ‘dead’ past and imagined future are of a piece with being stuck within the punctual ‘now’.Joshs

    Yeah, that's well said. :up:

    the late psychologist Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi (trying to pronounce that name might produce a flow state.)Wayfarer

    :lol:
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    A question remains though― what use is something's being true if we don't know it.Janus

    Well we could ask whether the 'T' in JTB is "accessible" truth or "inaccessible" truth. Isn't it pretty obvious that it is "accessible" truth? Or is there some JTB proponent I am unaware of who thinks "inaccessible" truths are per se important and also central to the JTB approach?

    Again, the JTB approach does not claim that truths are known independently of justification and belief. The whole point of JTB is that nothing is known independently of justification and belief.

    (This is why 's concern that one must be able to explain why X is true without giving any justification is a kind of ignoratio elenchus.)
  • Arguments From Underdetermination and the Realist Response
    No. I said IBEs are usually the best we can do.Relativist

    Right, but over and over I have been inquiring into whether there is anything other than IBEs, and over and over you keep shying away from that point.

    For example:

    Here are some questions about which rational answers can be given (IBEs), but the answers do not constitute knowledge:

    ...

    Is my name actually "Fred"?
    Relativist

    Earlier you gave this as an example of knowledge that is not an IBE, and now it is an IBE and not knowledge.

    So it looks like you hold that there is no knowledge; only IBEs. That's what I've been pointing up from the beginning.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    But JTB is not about what makes something true, but how I can say I know it to be true.J

    No, that's not right. JTB is not meant to provide you with a recipe for knowledge-cakes. JTB is a descriptive theory, not a normative theory. It is something like an attempt at a definition of knowledge, not an attempt at a recipe for knowledge. It is a set of conditions that is supposed to track when knowledge is present, not a strategy for gaining knowledge.

    Like, someone cannot sit down and say, "Ah, I have ten minutes to spare. I'm going to get me some knowledge. I'm going to know that Jupiter is the largest planet in the solar system. So for 'true' I will ask ChatGPT. Check. It is true that Jupiter is the largest planet. Now I need to check the justification box, so I'll look up some arguments for the idea. Check. Now I need to believe it. I think I do believe it, but to make sure I'm going to sit here and repeat to myself the mantra, 'I believe Jupiter is the largest planet, I believe Jupiter is the largest planet...' Okay, well it looks like I now know that Jupiter is the largest planet, given that I have checked all three boxes. Four minutes to spare... what else should I learn today?"

    JTB creates so much confusion that I think it may be more trouble than it's worth.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    I have to be able to be justified yet wrong.J

    The problem is that you want to make sound justification and unsound justification identical, as if they were the same thing, as if they were interchangeable. You are assuming that the 'J' signifies justification regardless of whether that justification is sound or unsound. You want to say that the person who is justified yet wrong is justified with the same justification of the person who is justified and therefore right.

    The crux is that, following Sam26's thought, there needs to be some space between justification and truth in order for JTB to really be a three-legged tripod.J

    ...And you think that if we distinguish between sound justification and unsound justification then there is no difference between 'J' and 'T', which is incorrect. This goes back to the "three separate ingredients" strawman.

    Aristotle is rather precise on this point in the second chapter of the Posterior Analytics, where he says that scientia proper requires that one knows the explanation for the thing in question. One must know what explains it; why it came to be. One must not merely have an explanation that incidentally lines up with some particular aspect of its existence. One must have more than an unsound argument with a true conclusion in order to have demonstrative knowledge. If one's understanding of 'J' does not take these distinctions into account then they will not be able to make JTB workable.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    This is why I see the Gettier literature as a long detour. It multiplies refinements to patch a problem that dissolves once we keep the standard for justification strong. By “strong” I mean publicly checkable, defeater-sensitive, and free of false grounds. If a justification fails those checks, it does not count as justification. Once that is clear, Gettier’s cases lose their force: they are examples not of knowledge, but of its counterfeit—instances where someone takes themselves to know but does not in fact know.Sam26

    I think Gettier would just provide you with a case where the erroneous clock is publicly checkable and defeater-sensitive. For example: a case where multiple public clocks are all simultaneously erroneous.

    Regarding the "false grounds," the key to the Gettier case is the difference between a material conclusion and a formal conclusion. So suppose we have two different cases:

    Case 1:

    J1. John looks at his clock which reads "2:00."
    J2. John assumes that his clock is working but in fact it is not.
    J3. John infers that it is in fact 2:00.
    4. It is, objectively, 2:00.

    Case 2:

    B1. Ben looks at his clock which reads "2:00."
    B2. Ben assumes that his clock is working.
    B3. Ben infers that it is in fact 2:00.
    4. It is, objectively, 2:00.

    Case 1 and case 2 are identical except for the second proposition, and the Gettier case turns on the premise that knowledge should not be able to be had by accident or by sheer luck.

    When I say "material" vs. "formal" conclusion I mean that both arguments "reach" (4) in a material sense, but only Ben reaches it in a formal sense. If we conceive of (4) as a kind of goalpost that someone must reach, and it doesn't matter how he reached it, then John has reached it. But if we conceive of (4) as a goalpost that someone must reach, and the reaching of which depends upon the means by which they arrived, then John has not reached it given the means in question. John has reached (4) materially but not formally, whereas Ben has reached it both materially and formally. ...Taken further we might say that a valid conclusion is different from a sound conclusion, and therefore John and Ben have reached different conclusions.

    The same thing applies to propositions more generally, including J3 and B3.

    I think what the Gettier case shows is that there are at least some conclusions which are material rather than formal, and knowledge of these conclusions is never certain. But his point isn't applicable to justification tout court. It is only applicable to those situations in which luck or accident plays a role. ...Of course the skeptic will argue that luck and accident play a role in every situation (i.e. that every conclusion is material), and that seems to be the crux.

    The so-called “Gettier problem” rests on a sleight of hand. It trades on the difference between thinking one is justified and actually being justified.Sam26

    We could construe it as saying that every valid justification can be unsound, and that we can only know that a justification is valid, not sound. Such a perspective might simply argue that not all unsound reasoning has defeaters.
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    That's what the J is meant to capture, and it leaves room for epistemic bad luck, where your belief turns out false but anyone would have formed the same belief, and it was a one in a million chance that in this case the evidence misled you.Srap Tasmaner

    The counterargument could be phrased this way:

    1. Truth is always known via justification, and ensured by justification
    2. Justification can never overcome the possibility of the one-in-a-million anomaly
    3. Therefore, truth is never certain

    This form of skepticism is a bit like the claim that epistemology is like a game of pool and no matter how good you are, there is always a chance that your shot will not pocket the 9-ball. Accidental contingencies are always involved, and therefore the best one can hope for is a good probability (or an ). Such a skeptic would say, "The only way to guarantee that the 9-ball is pocketed would be to pick it up with your own hand and place it into the pocket directly, but that would be cheating."
  • Thoughts on Epistemology
    namely whether the T in JTB is doing any useful work.J

    There are some folk on TPF who do not actually believe in truth or knowledge, and you are the foremost. This has been pointed out quite a few times. So it's no coincidence that you wonder whether "the T in JTB" is doing any useful work, or, "When do I ever know something...?"

    This is related to a recent discussion with @Relativist:

    If one locks the subject within their own beliefs, then knowledge is impossible.Leontiskos

    The other question has to do with the modern move where the subject is cut off from reality by fiat of premise. For example, if we can never get beyond our attitudes and make truth- and knowledge-claims that are not merely belief- or attitude-claims, then of course a kind of Cartesian skepticism will obtain. If every knowledge-claim is rewritten as a matter of the subject's attitude or nominalistic beliefs, then realism has been denied a hearing.Leontiskos

    -

    The objection to JTB seems to be this:

    <JTB means that there are three independent ingredients to knowledge, and once we have harvested all three we will be able to bake the knowledge cake. So we go find our Justification, and we go find our Truth, and we go find our Belief, and then we put them together in our mixing bowl, mix, and bake. Voila! We have knowledge. But where does Truth exist in isolation? Or Justification? Or Belief? They don't exist in isolation, to be harvested at will; therefore JTB fails.>

    ...That's a pretty wild understanding of JTB. The whole notion is incoherent, given that it presupposes that one can have knowledge of J independently of T and B (and knowledge of T independently of J and B, and knowledge of B independently of J and T). The "three independent ingredients" approach actually contradicts the whole epistemic notion of JTB.
  • The End of the Western Metadiscourse?
    Argument by bogeyman, eh?apokrisis

    That looks like a red herring, given that you seem to agree with what I've said.

    The ur-cause here is the evolutionary principle. What works is what survives. What can sustain itself over time through a capacity to repair and reproduce itself.apokrisis

    Right, but my point is that your approach is materially identical to post hoc rationalization. "What is superior/pragmatic is that which survives; Nazi Germany did not survive; Therefore, Nazi Germany was inferior." That is the premise, and then one has to provide reasoning to connect the ur-cause to the effect, which in this case has to do with fossil fuels and fascism.

    The reason such an approach is not formally identical with post hoc rationalization is because its norm really is survival, and survival really is measured in retrospect. On this approach what is good is precisely what survives, and this is associated with what "works" or what is "pragmatic" or what is "real," and there is no additional good/normativity.

    My other point with Nazi Germany is that your approach seems to have suffocated contingency. Most historians would say that the Axis Powers might have won the war, but on a fatalistic view everything that happens happens necessarily (again, unless one makes distinctions such as the short-term vs. long-term distinction). So let's move to that question of contingency and freedom.

    I was a climate change activist until about 2010. After that - seeing the reality of the politics and economics up close - I stop wasting my energy. It will be what it will be. And I make my own pragmatic plans within that.apokrisis

    But that's exactly what my argument predicts.

    So I see no problem of working within norms and then also challenging norms. The capacity to make this critical choice is central to being a pragmatist. You either play the game or change the game. And it is reason which tells you which way to go and any juncture.

    So a climate change scientist can see the need to reduce emissions. But if society fails to heed, then the climate scientist has to think that either society feels it is OK that global collapse is OK - some will survive - or that society lacks the capacity to escape the world view that fossil fuel has constructed for it.
    apokrisis

    What's interesting about this case is that the climate scientist seems to think that he is opposing activity that is suicidal on the level of the human species (and perhaps beyond). On your evolutionary principle "what works is what survives." So is it possible for the human species to commit accidental suicide and fail to survive? If so, then what survived was precisely what did not work (for humans).

    We can make the fatalism argument more abstract if you are concerned about "bogeymen." Suppose that political ideas are measured only by whether they survive. Thus if political idea X out-survives political idea Y, then political idea X is superior to political idea Y by the only possible metric.

    Now Apokrisis is standing before a society where X and Y are clashing. He must make a choice. Does he promote X? Y? Neither? If he chooses to promote one of the two ideas, such as he did temporarily in 2010, then he is at the same time predicting that X (say) will out-survive Y. Whether he is right or wrong is fairly simple, for time will tell. If X out-survives Y then he will say, "I was right." If Y out-survives X then he will say, "I was wrong, and now I will switch sides." He is always a "fair-weather fan" in that sense, for moral perplexity cannot arise where there is not more than one moral telos.

    The reason the reductio ad absurdum cannot simply be brushed aside with "bogeyman" labels is because there is a very strong cultural premise whereby one would continue to resist the Nazis even after the war was lost and the Nazi "survivability" proved itself superior. The reductio is an appeal to the fairly strong idea that good is not inevitable, and has to do with more than mere survival.

    A trivial example is that I refused to be promoted to a Sixer in the Cub Scouts as I said I didn’t want to order the other kids around. The look of incomprehension from the adults made me realise what this para-military organisation was all about and I left soon after.apokrisis

    What's interesting is that this is a moral choice in the classic sense, and not merely a "pragmatic" choice. You seem to be implicitly boasting that you are not the kind of person who wanted to "order the other kids around" and contribute to a "para-military organization." You are not saying, "My survivability and the survivability of my social environment will increase if I refuse the promotion to Sixer, therefore I will refuse the promotion." You are doing much the opposite, "I will sacrifice the boon of the approval of my peers and the Scout Leader because I value something that is more important than that approval, and am willing to act on it." You harmed the survivability of the social whole in order to honor your individual conscience. After all, militaristic hierarchical organization is one of the most time-proven organizational orderings.

    This is because you have the fixed normative habit of seeing dichotomies as unresolved monisms rather than the identification of the complementary limits on being - the complementary limits that then make an active choice of where to strike the useful balance.apokrisis

    No, I don't think so. I don't assume that I have the epistemic access to recognize every dichotomy as either an unresolved monism or complementary limits on being. They may be either. I don't know ahead of time. I think there is a resolution but I don't assume that I will be able to understand it.

    So my systems perspectives says there can be local ends and global ends. These are measurably different in being selfish and collective. Or competitive and cooperative. So you have some general bounding contrast in play, and the system would want to balance those rival imperatives over all scales of its being. Hence the pragmatic understanding of society as a hierarchy of interest groups. The contrasting pulls of individuation and integration at every level of social order.apokrisis

    But what does the bolded mean, "the system would want"? Does the system have wants and desires, or is it being reified and anthropomorphized?

    I understand that you have, say, the pole of the individual human and the pole of the human species, where the first has to do with selfishness and the second has to do with collectivity. But my hunch is that survivability is the only telos for both. "Selfishness" has to do with individual survivability and "collective" has to do with the species' survivability. As a more robust alternative I would offer the classic poles of subsidiarity and solidarity.

    My difficulty is that this looks like a rather one-dimensional contrast. The only possible source of contrast and complexity is coming from individual survival vs. group survival. On my view the evolutionary reductionism does not properly account for the human mind and human teloi. Humans often place their end in things that are basically unrelated to survival, and this is precisely what accounts for the vast complexity of social life.

    For example, the suicide bomber attests to the power of the human mind, which is able to subordinate the end of survival to other ends. There are just too many anomalies for the survival theory. If the survival theory were correct then human social realities would be a great deal simpler than they in fact are.

    Happiness is probably a vague enough term to hide the difference between talking about seeking a life balance and pursuing a hedonic pole.

    But if we are to understand eudaimonia properly, we have to dig into that exact difference in viewpoint. Do we mean what it feels like to be in balance with our life and world - a state of equanimity - or what it feels like to be madly ecstatic … just turned down to some low simmer that feels like the sustainable norm. A quiet content. A state of equanimity in short. Neither especially happy nor upset. Just ticking along nicely in the sense that sudden joy or sudden upset are adaptive states we could flip into as quick as circumstances might demand or justify.
    apokrisis

    Perhaps neither (or either), but is either one the same as the evolutionary survival account? For example, the telos of pleasure certainly seems to fold into a eudaimonic account more easily than a survival account, given that people and also groups will often harm their survivability for the sake of pleasure. I actually think your survival-account would track the data points quite well if humans did not exist at all, as the aberrations would seem to be much fewer among non-human animals.

    So you keep saying that my position is the one that can’t say anything much about the good and the bad. But my reply is that you don’t even seem to have started to understand the dynamical nature of such things. You are treating the good as a fixed destination placed at some impossible distance from wherever we are. I make the argument for how it is all about the dynamical balance that can stabilise our sense of being a self in its world. The pragmatism of being as adapted as possible, both in the short term and the long term, to the game that is living a life as a social creature.apokrisis

    Oh, that's fine, but I think you will find that if you want to teach people how to pursue such a good you will require a lot more than survivability language. If this is right, then the end you outline will not actually be persuasive to most people, and it will then need to be dressed up in other clothing. So you get a new caste of priests mediating the supreme telos to the masses who cannot interact with it directly. It seems that whenever someone dreams up a new ultimate telos (such as the Enlighteners did), they quickly find that hardly anyone is waiting in line to get on board, and that the masses need to be provided with a "temporary" proxy.

    Take technology for example. A new technology can drastically influence the course of human history. Many technologies seem positively opposed to the survival telos (e.g. nuclear weapons, contraception, perhaps even social media), and they are propagated nonetheless. If any such technologies are historically contingent, then we have cases where survivability is strongly impacted by a contingent cause that is not itself ordered to survivability.

    I also find that "balance" approaches tend to be almost indistinguishable from other robust approaches in practice. For example, I think you will end up appealing to the cardinal virtues of prudence, temperance, justice, and fortitude, just in a roundabout way. The question is then whether the simplification is helpful: whether pragmatism prefers that humans conceive of an ur-cause or not.
  • Self-Help and the Deflation of Philosophy
    Meet the new boss…Joshs

    Auguste Comte, generally recognized as the father of social science, explicitly modeled his approach on that of religion in general and Catholicism in particular with his "Religion of Humanity." Indeed, thinkers who apply evolutionary thought to the social sphere don't generally draw a hard and fast distinction between religion and social doctrine.